Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-ndmmz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-01T19:41:38.663Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Political Constructivism in Rawls's Political Liberalism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 August 2014

George Klosko*
Affiliation:
University of Virginia

Abstract

In Political Liberalism, John Rawls employs a distinctive method of “political constructivism” to establish his well-known principles of justice, arguing that his principles are suited to bridge the ineradicable pluralism of liberal societies and so to ground an “overlapping consensus.” Setting aside the question of whether Rawls's method supports his principles, I argue that he does not adequately defend reliance on this particular method rather than alternatives. If the goal of Rawls's “political” philosophy is to derive principles that are able to overcome liberal pluralism, then another and simpler method should be employed. The “method of convergence” would develop liberal principles directly from the convergence of comprehensive views in existing societies, and so give rise to quite different moral principles.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Baier, Kurt. 1989. “Justice and the Aims of Political Philosophy.” Ethics 99(07):771–90.Google Scholar
Barry, Brian. 1989. Theories of Justice. A Treatise ofSocial Justice, Vol. I. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Barry, Brian. 1995. Review of Political Liberalism, Ethics 105(07): 874915.Google Scholar
Cohen, Joshua. 1989. “Democratic Equality.” Ethics 99(07):727–51.Google Scholar
Cohen, Joshua. 1993. “Moral Pluralism and Political Consensus.” In The Idea of Democracy, ed. Copp, David, Hampton, Jean, and Roemer, John. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Connolly, William. 1983. The Terms of Political Discourse. 2d ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Easton, David. 1965. A Systems Analysis of Political Life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Exdell, John. 1994. “Feminism, Fundamentalism, and Liberal Legitimacy.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 24(09):441–63.Google Scholar
Gallie, W. B. 19551956. “Essentially Contested Concepts.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56:167–98.Google Scholar
Galston, William. 1989. “Pluralism and Social Unity.” Ethics 99(07):711–26.Google Scholar
Galston, William. 1992. Liberal Purposes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hibbing, John, and Theiss-Morse, Elizabeth. 1995. Congress as Public Enemy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hunter, James. 1990. Culture Wars: The Struggle to Define America. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
James, Hunter. 1994. Before the Shooting Begins: Searching for Democracy in America's Culture War. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Hunter, James, and Bowman, Carl. 1996. The State of Disunion: 1996 Survey of American Political Culture. Ivy, VA: In Media Res Educational Foundation.Google Scholar
Jelen, Ted, and Wilcox, Clyde. 1995. Public Attitudes toward Church and State. Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe.Google Scholar
Jones, Peter. 1995. “Review Article: Two Conceptions of Liberalism and Two Conceptions of Justice.” British Journal of Political Science 25(10):515–50.Google Scholar
Klosko, George. 1993. “Rawls's ‘Political’ Philosophy and American Democracy.” American Political Science Review 87(06):348–59.Google Scholar
Klosko, George. 1994. “Rawls's Argument from Political Stability.” Columbia Law Review 94(10):1882–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipset, Seymour. 1981. Political Man: The Social Bases of Politics. Rev. ed. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, David. 1992. “Distributive Justice: What the People Think.” Ethics 102(04):555–93.Google Scholar
Muller, Edward, Jukam, Thomas, and Seligson, Mitchell. 1982. “Diffuse Political Support and Antisystem Political Behavior: A Comparative Analysis.” American Journal of Political Science 26(05): 240–64.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1958. “Justice as Fairness.” Philosophical Review, 67(01):164–94.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1980. “Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory.” Journal of Philosophy 77(09):515–72.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1982. “The Basic Liberties and Their Priority.” In The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, ed. MacMurrin, Sterling. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1985. “Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 14(Summer):223–51.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1987. “The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus.” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 7(Spring):125.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1988. “The Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 17(Fall):251–76.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1989. “The Domain of the Political and Overlapping Consensus.” New York University Law Review 64(05):233–55.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1996. Political Liberalism. Paperback ed., with new Introduction. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Wenar, Leif. 1995. “Political Liberalism: An Internal Critique.” Ethics 106(10):3267.Google Scholar
Wolff, Robert P. 1977. Understanding Rawls. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.