Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-2pzkn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-03T16:37:07.269Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Historicising “Law” as a Language of Progress and Its Anomalies: The Case of Penal Law Reforms in Colonial India

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 May 2015

Get access

Abstract

This paper dispels the myth of liberal Enlightenment in relation to penal law reforms in colonial India by advancing two sets of argument. First, the liberal project of codification on the basis of universalist notion of utilitarianism never broke with cultural hierarchy inbuilt in the very act of colonisation. In this paper, I specifically look into the emerging phenomenon of evolutionary science in the nineteenth century – social Darwinism – to explain the dominant normative, as opposed to realist, justification of such racial hierarchy in colonial discourses since the nineteenth century. Second, using Dipesh Chakrabarty’s theoretical framework, I provincialise the penal law reform project in colonial India through the examination of literature in the field, and substantiate how the notion of utilitarian universality remained vague and unpromising in face of instrumental needs on ground – both in the colony and in the metropolis. Taken together, these propositions dispel the myth of the liberal project of penal law reforms in colonial India based on this universalist position and underscore the fallacies of the transition narrative of modernity itself.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Faculty of Law, National University of Singapore 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Onuma, Yasuaki, “When Was the Law of International Society Born? An Inquiry of the History of International Law from an Intercivilisational Perspective” (2000) 2 J. Hist. Int’L. L. 5354.Google Scholar

2 Vitoria, Francisco de, De Indis Reflection Prior, trans. by Bates, J. P. (Washington, DC: Oceana Press, 1917 [1532]) at 161.Google Scholar

3 Ibid.

4 Anghie, Antony, “Francisco De Vitoria and the Colonial Origins of International Law” (1996) 5:3 S. & L.S. 326.Google Scholar

5 Raman, Kartik K., “Utilitarianism and the Criminal Law in Colonial India: A Study of the Practical Limits of Utilitarian Jurisprudence” (1994) 28:4 Mod. Asian Stud. 756.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

6 Hall, William E., A Treatise on International Law, 8th ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1924) at 1.Google Scholar

7 Lawrence, Thomas J., The Principles of International Law (London: Macmillan and Co., 1895) at 58.Google Scholar

8 Ibid. at 18.

9 Anghie, Antony, Imperialism, Sovereignty and the Making of International Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005) at 54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

10 Maine’s “Minute on Codification in India,” dated July 17, 1879, at the NAI, Home (Legislative) August 1879, 217-20, cited in Kolsky, Elizabeth, “Codification and the Rule of Colonial Difference: Criminal Procedure in British India” (2005) 23 L. & Hist. Rev. 652.Google Scholar

11 Thus,

[t]he doctrines and ceremonies of religion; the rules and practice of education; the institutions, duties, and customs of domestic life; the maxims of private morality, and even of domestic economy; the rules of government, of war, and of negotiation; all form essential parts of the Hindu codes of law, and are treated in the same style, and laid down with the same authority, as the rules for the distribution of justice.

See, Mill, James, The History of India in 8 volumes, 4th ed. vol. II (London: James Madden & Co., 1840 [1817]) at 223-24.Google Scholar

12 Ibid. at 224.

13 In the Code of Manu, the titles, as they are there denominated, or divisions, of law, are eighteen, laid down in the following order: 1. Debt, on loans for consumption; 2. Deposits and loans for use; 3. Sale without ownership; 4. Concerns among partners; 5. Subtraction of what has been given; 6. Non-payment of wages or hire; 7. Non-performance of agreements; 8, Rescission of sale and purchase; 9. Disputes between master and servant; 10. Contests on boundaries; 11 and 12. Assault and slander; 13. Larceny; 14. Robbery and other violence; 15. Adultery; 16. Altercation between man and wife and their several duties; 17. The law of inheritance; 18. Gaming with dice and with living creatures. The Laws of Manu, Ch. VIII.

14 Mill (1840 [1817]), supra note 11 at 224.

15 Ibid. at 226.

16 “Animals are divided into: (a) belonging to the Emperor, (b) embalmed, (c) tame, (d) sucking pigs, (e) sirens, (f) fabulous, (g) stray dogs, (h) included in the present classification, (i) frenzied, (j) innumerable, (k) drawn with a very find camelhair brush, (l) et cetera, (m) having just broken the water pitcher, (n) that from a long way off look like flies.” See, Foucault, M., The Order of Things – An Archaeology of the Human Sciences (London: Routledge, 1989 [1966]) at xvi.Google Scholar

17 Ibid.

18 In The Order of Things: Archaeology of Knowledge, while talking about “justice,” he states that the legal system itself makes it impossible, by setting up a social power structure where a supposedly neutral judge pronounces supposedly neutral judgments in a setting of organised superiority and subservience. He argues that revolutionary groups cannot establish a more acceptable justice unless they move away from justice system itself, otherwise they re-institute the unjust bourgeois concept of justice. See, Foucault, M., The Order of Things – Archaeology of Knowledge, trans. Sheridan Smith, A. M. (London: Routledge, 2002 [1969]) at 6270.Google Scholar

19 Mill (1840 [1817]), supra note 11 at 253.

20 Ibid. at 254.

21 Halhed’s Code of Gentoo Laws, ch. xvi. sec.1, cited in Mill (1840 [1817]), supra note 12 at 256.

22 Mill (1840 [1817]), supra note 11 at 259-60.

23 Ibid. at 260.

24 Ibid. at 271.

25 Mill quotes from the Code of Manu a long list of persons who are excluded as witness under this rule:

Those must not be admitted who have a pecuniary interest; nor familiar friends; nor menial servants; nor enemies; nor men formerly perjured; nor persons grievously diseased; nor those, who have committed heinous offences. The king cannot be made a witness, nor cooks and the like mean artificers; nor public dancers and singers; nor a priest of deep learning in Scripture; nor a student of the Vedas; nor an anchoret secluded from all worldly connexions; nor one wholly dependent; nor one of bad fame; nor one who follows a cruel occupation; nor one who acts openly against the law; nor a decrepit old man; nor a child; nor a wretch of the lowest mixed class; nor one who has lost the organs of sense; nor one extremely grieved; nor one intoxicated; nor a madman; nor one tormented with hunger or thirst; nor one oppressed by fatigue; nor one excited by lust; nor one inflamed by wrath; nor one who has been convicted of theft.

In addition, women were held incompetent to give evidence, unless in the case of evidence for others of the same sex. Servants, too, mechanics, and those of the lowest class, are allowed to give evidence for individuals of the same description. See, Laws of Manu, ch. viii. 64-8, cited in ibid. at 272-73.

26 Mill (1840 [1817]), supra note 11 at 274.

27 Thomas Strange, Elements of Hindu Law at 309, cited by Horace Hayman Wilson, commentary to the 4th edition of Mill’s History of India, vol. II, footnote 1 at 274.

28 According to Mill:

A body of laws may be said to be complete when it includes every thing which it ought to include; that is, when all those rights, the existence of which is calculated to improve the state of society, are created; and all those acts, the hurtfulness of which to the society is so great as to outweigh the cost, in all its senses, necessary for preventing them, are constituted offences.

See Mill (1840 [1817]), supra note 11 at 282.

29 For Mill, the exactness of a body of laws is conformed: 1. when it constitutes nothing a right, and nothing an offence, except those things precisely which are necessary to render it complete; 2. when it contains no extraneous matter whatsoever; 3. when the aggregate of the powers and privileges which ought to be constituted rights, the aggregate of the acts which ought to be constituted offences, are divided and subdivided into those very parcels or classes, which beyond all others best adapt themselves to the means of securing the one, and preventing the other; 4. when it defines those classes, that is, rights and offences, with the greatest possible clearness and certainty; 5. when it represses crimes with the smallest possible expense of punishment; and 6. when it prescribes the best possible form of a judicatory, and lays down the best possible rules for the judicial functions. See, ibid. at 28283.

30 Mill, James, The History of British India in 6 Volumes, 3rd ed., vol. II (London: Baldwin, Cradock, and Joy, 1826 [1817]) at 197.Google Scholar

31 Ibid. at 203.

32 See, ibid. at 199-200.

33 Ibid. at 200.

34 Ibid.

35 Ibid. at 200-01.

36 Ibid. at 201.

37 Ibid. at 202.

38 Dubois, Abbe J. A., Description of the Character, Manners, and Customs of the People of India (London: Longmans, Green & Co. 1817) at 494 Google Scholar, cited by Horace Hayman Wilson, commentary to the 4th edition of Mill’s History of India, vol. II, footnote 1 at 288.

39 Ibid.

40 “Government of India”, 10 July 1833, in Trevelyan, Lady, ed., The Works of Lord Macaulay vol. VIII (London: Longmans, Green & Co., 1875) at 120.Google Scholar

41 Kolsky (2005), supra note 10 at 652.

42 Mill (1840 [1817]), supra note 11 at 285.

43 Ibid.

44 Ibid.

45 Ibid. at 286. Kolsky, however, contends that the discourse on the mismanaged administration of justice in India frequently ended up with this gloomy image of pre-colonial turmoil in order to justify “new forms of colonial intervention and to disguise the Company’s own failures of justice,” and the same language of chaos that depicted the tyranny of the common law in England was “slightly reoriented to condemn the lawlessness of the Oriental despot in India.” See Kolsky (2005), supra note 10 at 652.

46 See, Lipstein, K., “The Reception of Western Law in India” (1957) 9 Int’l. Soc. Sci. Bull. 87 Google Scholar, 88, 91. See also, Smith, K. J. M., James Fitzjames Stephen: Portrait of a Victorian Rationalist (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

47 Ibid., Smith (1988), supra note 46 at 134-35.

48 Ibid. at 33.

49 Ibid. at 34.

50 Kolsky (2005), supra note 10 at 636. See also, Kolsky, Elizabeth, Colonial Justice in British India: White Violence and Rule of Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011)Google Scholar; Chatterjee, Partha, The Nation and Its Fragments: Colonial and Postcolonial Histories (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993)Google Scholar.

51 For an account of social Darwinism, see, Hawkins, M., Social Darwinism in European and American Thought, 1860-1945 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997) at 61122 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Dickens, P., Social Darwinism (Buckhingham: Open University Press, 2000) at 725.Google Scholar Referring to Herbert Spencer as the pioneer of social Darwinism, Greene argues that the historical context of Darwin’s work in particular and the interaction between science and society in general tend to emphasise the links between Darwin and Spencer consisting of a network of shared assumptions and viewpoints about God, Nature, society, and history, which rendered Spencer a “Darwinian before Darwin.” See, Greene, J. C., Science, Ideology and World View (Oakland, CA: University of California Press, 1981) at 134 Google Scholar, 140. For a Spencerian account of social evolution, see generally, Peel, J. D. Y., ed., Herbert Spencer on Social Evolution – Selected Writings (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1972).Google Scholar

52 Ibid., Dickens (2000), supra note 51 at 16-17; Hawkins (1997), supra note 51 at 14-15; Kuper, Adam, Culture: The Anthropologists’ Account (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999) at 11.Google Scholar

53 Dickens notes that in the 1860s, there was intense debate in Britain between the monogenists, who argued that there was a common ancestor for all human races, and the polygenists, who held the view that different races are indeed separate species. See, ibid., Dickens (2000), supra note 51 at 14.

54 Brace, Charles Loring, “Letter to The Washington Independent (September 12, 1861)” in Donaldson, Emma Brace, ed., The Life of Charles Loring Brace Chiefly Told in His Own Letters, (London: Sampson, Low, Marston and Co., 1894) at 390.Google Scholar

55 Ibid. at 375.

56 Supra note 55, Hawkins (1997), supra note 51 at 64.

57 Buchner, Friedrich Carl Christian Ludwig, Man in the Past, Present and Future, trans. by Dallas, William Sweetland (London: Asher and Co., 1872) at 151 Google Scholar, 156, 157.

58 Supra note 55, Dickens (2001), supra note 51 at 31-44.

59 Ibid. at 32.

60 For example, Fukuyama famously claimed that liberal capitalism indicates “the end of the history” by giving every individual a sense of recognition and worth while simultaneously providing with high levels of material well-being. See generally, Fukuyama, Francis, “The End of History?” (1989) 16 Nat’l. Int. 318.Google Scholar Other writers, such as Kerr and Aron, saw the end in the convergence of different forms of industrialisations. See, supra note 55, Dickens (2000), supra note 51 at 35-41.

61 Betts, Raymond F., Assimilation and Association in French Colonial Theory 1890-1914 (New York: Columbia University Press, 1961) at 59.Google Scholar

62 Ferry, Edmond, La France en Afrique (Paris: Armand Colin, 1905) at 228 Google Scholar, 232, quoted in ibid. at 82-83.

63 Jules Harmand, “Preface” in Sir Strachey, John, L’Inde, trans. by Harmand, Jules (Paris: Bibliotheque generale de geographi, 1892) at xxi Google Scholar, cited in Betts (1961), supra note 61 at 53-54.

64 Maunier, Rene, The Sociology of Colonies, vol. I, ed. and trans. by Lorimer, E. O. (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1949) at 297.Google Scholar

65 Betts (1961), supra note 61 at 108. Endnotes in original omitted.

66 Ibid. at 59.

67 Kolsky (2005), supra note 10 at 641.

68 The Legislative Consultations of February 1, 1836, No. 20 (IOR P/206/81), cited in ibid. at 653.

69 Kolsky (2005), supra note 10 at 655.

70 Quoted during the Legislative Proceedings of March 9, 1883, by Council Member Hunter, cited in Kolsky (2005), supra note 10 at 657.

71 Kolsky (2005), supra note 10 at 667.

72 Ibid.

73 The debates of July, August, and September 1859, in Legislative Council Proceedings, vol. 5 (1859), quoted in ibid. at 671.

74 Foucault, Michel, “Truth and Juridical Forms” in Faubion, James D., ed., Essential Works of Foucault 1954-1984, vol. 3, trans. by Hurley, Robert et al. (London: Penguin Books, 2002 [2000]) at 48.Google Scholar

75 Ibid.

76 Chakrabarty, Dipesh, Provincializing Europe – Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000) at 37.Google Scholar

77 Ibid. at 39.

78 Ibid. at 43.

79 Ibid. at 237-38.

80 Ibid. at 238-39.

81 Ibid. at 239.

82 Ibid. at 244.

83 Ibid. at 247.

84 Ibid.

85 Ibid. at 249. Emphasis added.

86 Ibid. at 250.

87 Ibid. at 251.

88 Ibid. at 254.

89 Ibid.

90 Wilson, Jon E., “Anxieties of Distance: Codification in Early Colonial Bengal” (2007) 4:1 Mod. Intell. His. 23.Google Scholar

91 Ibid. at 8.

92 Ibid.

93 Ibid. at 9.

94 Ibid. at 20.

95 Thomas Macaulay, “Government of India”, 10 July 1833, Works, vol. 8 at 142, quoted in ibid. at 21.

96 Raman (1994), supra note 5 at 740.

97 Ibid. at 740-41.

98 Statement of the Indian Law Commission to Lord Auckland on 14 October 1837, in Parliamentary Papers 41 (1837-38), cited in ibid. at 767.

99 Bentham, Jeremy, Essay on the Influence of Time and Place in Matters of Legislation (London: Stevenson & Company, 1789) at 177 Google Scholar, 184.

100 Raman (1994), supra note 5 at 777.

101 Ibid. at 790.

102 Skuy, David, “Macaulay and the Indian Penal Code of 1862: The Myth of the Inherent Superiority and Modernity of the English Legal System Compared to India’s Legal System in the Nineteenth Century” (1998) 32:3 Mod. Asian Stud. 517.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

103 Ibid. at 532.

104 Ibid. at 525.

105 Records available at Old Bailey Proceedings Online, online: <www.oldbaileyonline.org> (last accessed 22 April 2014).

106 Old Bailey Proceedings Online, online: <www.oldbaileyonline.org>, version 7.0 (last accessed 6 March 2014), April 1801, trial of Thomas Burrell John Westkett (t18010415-90).

107 Old Bailey Proceedings Online, online: <www.oldbaileyonline.org>, version 7.0 (last accessed 6 March 2014), September 1805, trial of John Scape, alias Edwin (t18050918-36).

108 Ibid.

109 Ibid. at 538. Skuy demonstrates that Indian law reform mirrored developments in England in a variety of ways:

court reforms in the 1820s and 1830s in India occurred while the Peel Acts were passed; Macaulay wrote a criminal code for India while a Royal Commission wrote one for England; Macaulay submitted his Code to Parliament the same year Parliament passed the 1837 Acts; the Indian Law Commission reviewed Macaulay’s Code in 1847-48 just as the second Royal Commission finished its draft criminal code; and a few months before the Indian Penal Code became law, the British Parliament passed the 1861 Acts. In substantive and procedural terms, the Indian Penal Code reflected developments in English law.

See, ibid. at 553.

110 Malik, Shahdeen, “Perceiving Crimes and Criminals: Erratic Law Making in the Early 19th Century Bengal” (2002) 6:1&2 B’desh. J. L. 5961.Google Scholar Changes made in penal laws of this early period were later modified, enlarged, systematised, and enacted as the Penal Code in 1860.

111 Ibid. at 61.

112 For a survey of these approaches in relation to international law, see, Martti Koskenniemi, “Histories of International Law: Dealing with Eurocentrism” Inaugural Lecture delivered on 16 November 2011 on the occasion of accepting the Treaty of Utrecht Chair at Utrecht University.