Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-pftt2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-05T12:14:05.868Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Democratic Equality and Relating as Equals

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Get access

Extract

Imagine a democratic society in which all members are full citizens and citizens relate to each other as equals. Social arrangements bring it about, to the maximum possible extent, that all adults are full functioning members of society. The society is not marred by caste hierarchies, invidious status distinctions, or unequal power relations. No one is able to dominate others. Moreover, the urge to dominate over others does not loom large in social life. Each person's relations with others manifest the belief, shared by all, that each person is fundamentally the equal of all others and that this equality calls for treating others with civility and mutual respect and forbearance. Each is viewed as having the right to live as she chooses, within broad constraints of morality. This individual entitlement to freedom establishes a strong presumption against paternalism, restricting a person's liberty against her will for her own good. Regarding distributive justice, the norm is that each should be enabled to have enough by way of resources and opportunities to sustain herself as a full functioning member of democratic society.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anderson, Elizabeth. 1993. Value in Ethics and Economics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 1999. “What is the Point of Equality?Ethics 109 (2): 287337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2009. “Democracy: Instrumental vs. Non-Instrumental Value.” In Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy, ed. Christiano, Thomas and Christman, John, 213-27. Chichester, Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 1989. “Equality and Equal Opportunity for Welfare.“ Philosophical Studies 56: 7793.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 2004a. “Democracy Is Not Intrinsically Just.” In Democracy and Justice, ed. Dowding, Keith, Goodin, Robert E., and Pateman, Carole, 4058. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 2004b. “Luck Egalitarianism Interpreted and Defended.” Philosophical Topics 32: 120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 2009. “The Supposed Right to a Democratic Say.” In Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy, ed. Christiano, Thomas and Christman, John, 197212. Chichester, Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 1989. “On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice.Ethics 99 (4): 906-44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 2000. If You're an Egalitarian, How Come You're So Rich? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 2008. Rescuing Justice and Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 2000. Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fleurbaey, Marc. 1995. “Equal Opportunity or Equal Social Outcome?Economics and Philosophy 11: 2555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry. 1987. “Equality as a Moral Idea.” Ethics 98: 21–43.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1981. Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Methods, and Point. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. 2003. Virtue, Vice, and Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hurley, Susan. 2003. Justice, Luck, and Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1957. Utilitarianism. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar