Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x5gtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-23T10:44:34.926Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Empty Names and Pragmatic Implicatures

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Fred Adams
Affiliation:
University of Delaware, Newark, DE19716, USA
Gary Fuller
Affiliation:
Central Michigan University, Mount Pleasant, MI48859, USA

Extract

What are the meanings of empty names such as ‘Vulcan,’ ‘Pegasus,’ and ‘Santa Claus’ in such sentences as ‘Vulcan is the tenth planet,’ ‘Pegasus flies,’ and especially ‘Santa Claus does not exist’?

Our view, developed in Adams et al. (1992, 1994, 1997, 2004), consists of a direct-reference account of the meaning of empty names in combination with a pragmatic-implicature account of why we have certain intuitions that seem to conflict with a direct-reference account.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, F. and Dietrich, L.. 2004. ‘What's in a(n empty) Name?Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85 (2004) 125–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, F. Fuller, G. and Stecker, R.. 1993. ‘Thoughts Without Objects.Mind and Language 8 (1993) 90104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, F. Fuller, G. and Stecker, R.. 1997. ‘The Semantics of Fiction.Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78 (1997) 128–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, F. and Stecker, R.. 1994. ‘Vacuous Singular Terms.Mind and Language 9 (1994) 387401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, F. Stecker, R. and Fuller, G.. 1992. ‘The Semantics of Thought.Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 73 (1992) 375–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braun, D. 1993. ‘Empty Names.Nous 27 (1993) 449–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, T. 1991. ‘Truth and Singular Terms.’ Philosophical Applications of Free Logic, Lambert, K. ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 189204.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. 1989. ‘Against Direct Reference.Midwest Studies 14 (1989) 206–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, G. 1982. The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Everett, A. 2005. ‘Recent Defenses of Descriptivism.Mind and Language 20 (2005) 102–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, M. 2007. ‘Direct Reference, Empty Names and Implicatures.Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (2007) 419–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grice, H.P. 1989. Studies in the Ways of Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. 1972. ‘Naming and Necessity.’ In Semantics of Natural Language, Davidson, D. and Harman, G. eds. Boston: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Recanati, F. 1993. Direct Reference: From Language to Thought. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Reimer, M. 2001. ‘The Problem of Empty Names.Australian Journal of Philosophy 79 (2001) 491506.Google Scholar
Stanley, j. 1997. ‘Names and Rigid Designation.’ In A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Hale, R. and Wright, C. eds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Urmson, j. 1968. ‘Criteria of Intensionality.Aristotelian Society Proceedings, Supplementary Volume 42 (1968) 107–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar