Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-2pzkn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-03T23:50:02.874Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Distributive numerals in Albanian

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 November 2023

BUJAR RUSHITI
Affiliation:
Laboratoire de linguistique formelle, Université Paris Cité, Université Paris Cité & University AAB, Kosovo
CARMEN DOBROVIE-SORIN
Affiliation:
Laboratoire de linguistique formelle, Centre national de la recherche scientifique, Université Paris Cité, France
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper investigates nga-marked numerals in Albanian. They qualify as distributive numerals, since the presence of nga on the numeral yields a distributive reading of the sentences they belong to. Beyond their differences, most of the previous accounts rely on the hypothesis that distributive numerals introduce some kind of semantic feature, e.g. a covariation feature; an evaluation plurality requirement, also called a post-suppositional plurality requirement; or a distributivity force. Our main claim goes against this trend of thinking. We propose that distributive numerals do not carry any semantic feature but only a formal syntactic feature that needs to enter a syntactic dependency relation with a distributivity feature. The analysis is implemented in terms of Zeijlstra’s (2004) upward agree.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

This paper is concerned with the Albanian nga, which qualifies as a distributivity marker in that it marks an indefinite determiner phrase (DP) that obligatorily covaries with an entity that ranges over a set that is introduced either by a plural DP (or by a conjunction of DPs, not illustrated here) or by (the restriction of) a universal quantifier:

As indicated by the brackets, the presence of nga is optional in both examples. In example (1a), the version with nga is only compatible with the distributive reading on which each of the children listened to two possibly different songs, whereas the version without nga is ambiguous, also allowing a collective reading on which the children listened to the same two songs together. In example (1b), the distributive reading is independently triggered by the presence of the distributive quantifier secili ‘each’, but nga itself is not felt as redundant.

The facts just described have been investigated for similar markers in unrelated languages, e.g. the Korean ssik (Gil Reference Gil1982; Choe Reference Choe1987); the suffix -gáa in Tlingit (Cable Reference Cable2014); the Romanian câte (Farkas Reference Farkas2002; Panaitescu Reference Panaitescu2018, Reference Panaitescu2019); and the numeral reduplication in Hungarian (Farkas, Reference Farkas1997a, Reference Farkas2001), Telugu (Balusu Reference Balusu2006), and Kaqchikel (Henderson Reference Henderson2014).

These various markers are comparable to the so-called binominal each (see the gloss of (1a) above) but clearly differ from it because not only are they morphologically unrelated to the distributive determiners of these various languages but also their distribution is larger than that of binominal each. Some previous proposals have insisted on the common properties of the two types of markers Champollion (Reference Champollion2016), whereas others have stressed their differences Zimmerman (Reference Zimmerman2002). In the limits of the present paper, we do not compare nga and binominal each.

We leave aside many aspects of the distribution of nga, which are parallel to what we know about its crosslinguistic counterparts listed above. We thus do not examine those examples in which the nga-marked cardinal depends on a temporal or spatial adjunct, as in example (2). The example shows that the nga-marked cardinal co-varies in the scope of the quantificational adjunct në ditë ‘per day’. Example (2a) would be true in a scenario where Mary reads two (different) poems every day. We also ignore the so-called adverbial nga -marked numerals illustrated in (2b), where nga can be used to form reduplicated numerals akin to the English construction Num by Num (see Brasoveanu & Henderson Reference Brasoveanu and Henderson2009). For a more detailed description of the distribution of nga, see Rushiti (Reference Rushiti2019) and Bajrami et al. (Reference Bajrami, Hamiti and Blakqori2020).

This paper makes an original contribution in the documentation and analysis of distributively marked numerals in Albanian, a little-studied language. But we also aim toward a better understanding of this phenomenon by making a new theoretical proposal, which we expect to extend to distributive numerals (DistNums) across languages (modulo possible parametric variation coming either from the properties of the DistNums themselves or from other language-particular items, e.g. pluractional markers).

Beyond their differences, most of the previous accounts rely on the hypothesis that DistNums introduce some kind of semantic feature, either a covariation feature (Farkas Reference Farkas1997a); an evaluation-plurality requirement (Brasoveanu & Farkas Reference Brasoveanu and Farkas2011), also called a post-suppositional plurality requirement (Henderson Reference Henderson2014; Kuhn Reference Kuhn2015); or a distributivity operator (Kuhn Reference Kuhn2019). Our main claim is that DistNums are semantically vacuous in the sense that they do not carry any semantic feature but only a formal syntactic feature that needs to enter a dependency relation with a distributivity feature. According to our view then, the covariation meaning triggered by DistNums is not due to a semantic feature but can instead be explained as a consequence of being read off ‘distributivity concord’, a purely syntactic dependency relation, which we implement in terms of the upward agree mechanism that Zeijlstra (Reference Zeijlstra2004) proposed for the analysis of negative concord (NC).

That distributive concord should be handled by the syntax and not be viewed as a semantic phenomenon is motivated by the fact that the relation between the nga-marked element and a (overt or covert) distributive operator strictly obeys syntactic locality. This contrasts with the relation between a narrow-scoped unmarked indefinite and a distributive operator.

This paper is organized as follows. Section 2 introduces the puzzle: nga triggers a distributive reading in sentences with no overt distributive quantifiers but does not yield ‘double distributivity’ when co-occurring with a distributive quantifier. Section 3 reviews previous accounts, and Section 4 contains our new proposal in terms of distributive concord. Section 5 examines those configurations in which nga is licensed by a silent distributive operator. Section 6 concludes.

2. The puzzle of distributive numerals

The examples in (3) show the contrast between distributive numerals and unmarked numerals in Albanian.

Example (3a), built with an unmarked cardinal indefinite, is ambiguous between a collective and a distributive reading. The collective reading can be paraphrased as the children together washed two white puppies. The distributive reading can be paraphrased as each of the children washed two (potentially) different white puppies. Example (3b) contains the distributive marker nga. Due to its presence, the sentence as a whole can only receive a distributive reading.

The plural DP in the subject position of (3a) is the ‘key’, i.e. the constituent that supplies the set over which the distribution of puppies (in ‘shares’ of two) takes place. The terms key and share are abbreviations of Choe’s (Reference Choe1987), ‘Sorting Key’ and ‘Distributive Share’.

The example in (4) shows that nga cannot be licensed by a singular DP:

This constraint is identical to that of binominal each, as observable in the translation.

Note now that nga-marked DPs can also be licensed by distributive quantifiers, such as secili ‘each’, which may appear either in a determiner or in a ‘floated position’; see examples (5) and (6) or çdo ‘every’ (7):

The (5a), (6a), and (7a) examples, in which the object indefinite is unmarked, can have two interpretations. According to the first interpretation, there are two white puppies in the discourse context such that each of the children washed those two white puppies. This reading is traditionally analyzed as involving the ‘wide scope’ of the indefinite, hence the notation ‘two>each’ in the gloss above.Footnote 2

According to the second reading, puppies co-vary with children; each child is reported to have washed two (different) white puppies. This reading is traditionally analyzed as involving the narrow scope of the object, hence the notation ‘each>two’. The (5b), (6b), and (7b) examples can only have the narrow scope reading.

Putting together the observations made so far, we obtain a disjunctive constraint:

On the descriptive level, this generalization is well documented for other languages that have distributive numerals (see among others Farkas Reference Farkas1997a, for Hungarian; Balusu Reference Balusu2006, for Telugu; Oh Reference Oh2001, Reference Oh2006, for Korean; Gryllia Reference Gryllia2007, for Greek; Henderson Reference Henderson2012, Reference Henderson2014, for Kaqchikel; and Panaitescu Reference Panaitescu2018, Reference Panaitescu2019, for Romanian). Some examples are given:

In sum, the disjunctive constraint in (8) appears to be empirically well-grounded but is theoretically problematic because it acknowledges the inability to give a uniform characterization of DistNums. Beyond their differences, existing accounts attempt to reduce the disjunction by assuming one of the two conjuncts to be primitive and attempting to derive the other conjunct as a consequence of the first.

3. Previous approaches

Although theoreticians agree on the main empirical generalizations regarding DistNums, no common consensus has been reached on the theory of these markers.

A large majority of existing theories assume that DistNums are endowed with an built-in semantic property that forces covariation but they diverge regarding the analysis of covariation, and correlated to it regarding the source of distributivity: is it contributed by the context or by DistNums themselves?

Regarding the covariation requirement, some theoreticians propose to capture it by assuming that the entity denoted by the marked DP must be plural. For Cable (Reference Cable2014), the relevant notion of plurality is the currently used one, also called domain or ontological plurality, i.e. reference to a non-atomic entity, to be distinguished from Brasoveanu’s (Reference Brasoveanu2007, Reference Brasoveanu2008) ‘evaluation plurality’, which ‘involves non-atomic reference relative to the whole matrix of variable assignments’ (Brasoveanu & Farkas Reference Brasoveanu and Farkas2011). In other words, the requirement of evaluation plurality postulated by Brasoveanu & Farkas as being the semantic contribution of DistNums is a ‘post-suppositional condition’ in the sense of Henderson (Reference Henderson2012, Reference Henderson2014), which means that the plurality condition is checked on the output of the semantic computation. The intuition behind the post-suppositional analysis of DistNums was also assumed by Kuhn (Reference Kuhn2019), whose formal implementation is however different.Footnote 4 While dynamic semantics and post-suppositions may indeed be needed for discourse-coherence phenomena, e.g. donkey anaphora, one may question extending such tools to DistNums, which are subject to strict locality (see Section 4.2).Footnote 5 Note also that the plurality condition (be it a presupposition or a post-supposition) has been questioned by Cabredo-Hofherr & Etxebarria (Reference Cabredo-Hofherr and Etxeberria2017) in their analysis of the Basque na-marker.Footnote 6

For some authors, DistNums contribute distributivity (Balusu Reference Balusu2006; Cable Reference Cable2014; Kuhn Reference Kuhn2017; Reference Kuhn2019; Cabredo-Hofherr & Etxeberria Reference Cabredo-Hofherr and Etxeberria2017). Of these, let us first focus on Cable’s analysis of distributive numerals in Tlingit, which are formed by means of the suffix -gaa attached to the numeral – cf. example (16).

According to Cable, sentence (16a) has the same range of interpretations as its English gloss. For instance, (16a) is true not only in a distributive scenario (in which each of the sons caught three fish) but also in a scenario where the speaker’s sons together caught three fish. On the other hand (16b), which contains the distributive numeral nás’gigáa, cannot receive a collective reading but is compatible with two distinct distributive readings, given in (16b-i) and (16b-ii). The former says that each of the sons caught three fish. The interpretation in (16b-ii) is true in a scenario where Alex and Bob went fishing every day during the last week and caught three fish each day. Cable uses the term ‘participant-distributive reading’ to refer to the interpretation in (16b-i) and ‘event-distributive reading’ for the interpretation in (16b-ii). In order to capture the two interpretations of (16b), Cable assumes the following denotation for the distributive suffix -gaa:

According to (17), the distributive suffix -gáa takes as its first argument an integer of type n. Cable assumes an integer semantics for numerals, e.g. [[two]] = 2. The second argument of -gáa is a predicate Q of type <et>, which is supplied by the modified N xáat ‘fish’ in example (16b). Next, -gáa takes as an argument a relation ‘P’ between entities and events (notated as λP<e, εt>) and returns a predicate of events, λeε, which holds of an event ‘e’ iff (i) there is an ‘x’ such that Q(x) holds, and the relation P holds between x and e, and (ii) the pair <e,x> is the sum of those pairs <e’,y> such that (i) y is a proper part of x, and (ii) y is a plurality of cardinality of n, (iii) e’ is a proper part of e, and (iv) y is a participant in e’.

Let us now apply (17) to the sentence in (16b). For Cable, (16b) has the logical form (LF) structure in (18a) and the truth conditions in (18b):

As Cable (Reference Cable2014: 586) shows, (18b) is read informally as follows: “there is a (plural) event e of catching, whose agent is my sons and whose theme is a bunch of fish x, and the pair consisting of e and x is the sum of those pairs <e’, z> such that z is a triplet of fish, e’ is a part of e, and z participates in e’.”

Note that the truth conditions in (18b) hold in both participant-distributive and event-distributive scenarios. Cable (Reference Cable2014: 587 ex. (61)) illustrates the participant-distributive scenario as in example (19):

The event-distributive scenario is illustrated in example (20), corresponding to Cable (Reference Cable2014: 587 ex. (62)).

According to Cable’s proposal, the compatibility with the scenarios illustrated in (19) and (20) is not a matter of ambiguity (no difference in the semantic analysis) but instead due to the relatively weak truth conditions imposed by DistNums.

In (18b), Cable uses the asterisk ‘*’ to indicate that the predicates ‘*caught’, ‘*Agent’, and ‘*Theme’ are cumulative. For instance, in the participant-distributive scenario, the predicate *caught(e) indicates that there is a (plural) event e1+e2 of my sons cumulatively catching a bunch of fish, which can be broken into triplets of fish. Each triplet of fish is mapped to an individual Agent of the catching event. Since the events e1 and e2 are each mapped to an atomic agent, we obtain the participant-distributive scenario. A similar account holds for the event-distributive scenario in (20), the difference being that each triplet of fish is mapped to time-individuated events, each of which has a plural agent (Tom+Ben).

In sum, in Cable’s system, distributive numerals convey that their argument can be divided into proper parts and distributed among several subevents. As Cable notes, a sentence that contains the distributive suffix n-gaa NP can be true if and only if every subevent contains an entity of cardinality n that satisfies the NP predicate.

Cable notes that his analysis cannot account for those configurations in which DistNums are licensed by a universal quantifier such as each. See in particular Albanian examples of the type in (21), already introduced in Section 1:

There is no salient difference between (21) – with both secili ‘each’ and nga – and a parallel sentence with secili alone and a narrow-scope interpretation of the cardinal NP (each of the sons in the discourse context caught three fish). This meaning of (21) cannot be generated by Cable’s system because the distributive numeral is supposed to break a plurality of fish into triplets of fish and map each triplet to an atomic catching subevent. Given the presence of secili ‘each’, the sentence should mean that each son was an agent of several catching subevents each of which involving three fish, the result being that each son caught more than three fish. In other words, given Cable’s semantics of distributive numerals (21) should have a ‘double distributive’ meaning, i.e. it should mean ‘each son caught fish three by three’. But this is clearly not the correct interpretation of (21).

Sentences such as (21) pose similar problems for other accounts that may differ from Cable’s in some of the technical details but resemble Cable insofar as it is the DistNum itself that contributes distributivity. In the implementation proposed by Kuhn & Aristodemo (Reference Kuhn and Aristodemo2017) and Kuhn (Reference Kuhn2019), the problem is solved by the assumption that DistNums are evaluated above the distributivity operator. Specifically, Kuhn (Reference Kuhn2019, Reference Kuhn2021) proposes that quantifier raising (QR) raises the DistNum higher than the distributive operator, as shown in the LF in (22):

The effect is one of innocent redundancy, which means that, even though (according to Kuhn) DistNums contribute distributivity, they do not yield double distributivity when co-occurring with another distributive quantifier.

According to some other authors, DistNums do not themselves contribute distributivity but only induce obligatory co-variation when occurring at LF in the scope of a distributive operator (Oh Reference Oh2001, Reference Oh2006; Brasoveanu & Farkas Reference Brasoveanu and Farkas2011; Henderson Reference Henderson2012, Reference Henderson2014; Guha Reference Guha2018; Panaitescu Reference Panaitescu2018). Among these various proposals, we concentrate on Oh (Reference Oh2006), which is close to the view that we ourselves defend in the present paper. Oh’s core proposal is that ssik-marked numerals in Korean are to be analyzed as ‘Distributive Polarity Items’. More precisely, Oh argues that Korean -ssik-marked numerals are subject to syntactic licensing in the scope (or C-command domain) of a distributive operator. This assumption directly captures examples such as (23), in which the -ssik-marked numeral is licensed by the floated universal quantifier, which qualifies as a distributive operator:

Note now that -ssik-marked numerals can also appear in sentences without a universal quantifier:

According to Oh, (24) is ambiguous between the participant-key reading (each man is mapped to three boxes) and the event-key reading (two men together carried three boxes on each occasion). Corresponding to these two readings, Oh proposes two distinct LF structures, both of which involve a covert distributive operator notated D but differ regarding which element counts as the restrictor of the D operator. In (25a), the restrictor is the subject DP (two men), which gives rise to the participant-key reading according to which the distribution of suitcases is three per individual. In (25b), it is the event argument that restricts the D operator, yielding the event-key reading. In Oh’s system, the (Davidsonian) event argument is projected as an event pronoun (e2) in the syntax and bound by a syntactically projected existential quantifier.

As pointed out by Cable (Reference Cable2014: 566), Oh’s analysis faces some problems. Thus, the licensing of distributive numerals in Korean is subject to locality constraints, in contrast to the licensing of NPIs (see the discussion in Section 4.1). Another problem for Oh’s claimed parallelism between DistNums and NPIs is the fact that -ssik is licensed in the scope of a covert D operator – see example (24) – whereas NPIs cannot be licensed by covert negative operators (cf. Zeijlstra Reference Zeijlstra2004).

4. Proposal: distributive marking involves upward agree

Our analysis goes against those proposals that assume that DistNums contribute distributivity (Champollion Reference Champollion2016; Kuhn Reference Kuhn2017, Reference Kuhn2019, Reference Kuhn2021) and sides with those that assume that DistNums signal a dependency relation with respect to a distributivity operator that is external to the DistNums themselves (Oh Reference Oh2001, Reference Oh2006; Zimmermann Reference Zimmerman2002; Brasoveanu & Farkas Reference Brasoveanu and Farkas2011; Henderson Reference Henderson2012, Reference Henderson2014; Guha Reference Guha2018; Panaitescu Reference Panaitescu2018). However, we also crucially depart from most of the latter proposals and follow Oh (Reference Oh2006) in assuming that the dependency relation is not semantic, but rather syntactic in nature.Footnote 7 We implement this hypothesis by extending Zeijlstra’s (Reference Zeijlstra2004) analysis of NC. According to this theory, Neg-words do not contribute semantic negation but instead need to enter a purely syntactic relation, upward agree, with a negative operator. Similarly, we argue that DistNums do not contribute semantic distributivity but instead need to enter upward agree with a (overt or covert) Dist operator.

We first briefly present Zeijlstra’s analysis of NC, and show that the main ingredients can be imported into the analysis of distributive numerals (Section 4.1). We then show that the relation between distributive numerals and distributive operators obeys strict locality constraints (Section 4.2.).

4.1. From negative concord items to distributive concord items

The core hypothesis of our analysis is that the dependency relation between distributive numerals and distributive operators is a syntactic rather than semantic relation, which we implement in terms of Zeijlstra’s (Reference Zeijlstra2012) upward agree. Correlatively, our proposal differs from all previous analyses of DistNums (with the exception of Oh Reference Oh2006 and Kimmelman Reference Kimmelman2015) in assuming that the defining property of DistNums is not a semantic feature (be it ‘covariation requirement’ or ‘distributivity’) but rather a syntactic uninterpretable feature, the uninterpretable Distributivity [uDist] feature, that needs to be checked against an interpretable Distributivity [iDist] feature.

The initial motivation for our analysis of distributive numerals is the fact that a distributive numeral co-occurring with a distributive quantifier yields an interpretation compatible with only one distributive relation. This non-multiplication of distributivity echoes the non-multiplication of negation in NC. The second important advantage of treating DistNums on the model of negative concord items (NCIs) is an explanation of the locality constraints to which they are subject (Section 4.2).

NC arises when multiple negative elements yield only one single semantic negation (cf. Laka Reference Laka Mugarza1990; Zeijlstra Reference Zeijlstra2004, Reference Zeijlstra2012, among many others as well as most recently Giannakidou & Zeijlstra Reference Giannakidou and Zeijlstra2017; Giannakidou Reference Giannakidou and Déprez2020). The following example illustrates NC in Albanian:

When used in isolation, nuk is enough to render a sentence negative. However, when nuk co-occurs with askush as in (26), the latter does not contribute negation (if it did, the negation introduced by nuk would be cancelled, yielding a positive interpretation of the overall sentence).

Zeijlstra (Reference Zeijlstra2012) analyzes NC as involving upward agree upward agree, a unidirectional Agree that applies in an upward fashion between a Neg-marked indefinite DP or adverb and a C-commanding neg marker on the (inflected) verb. In this system, an item carrying an uninterpretable feature [uF] enters a feature-checking mechanism with a C-commanding item that carries an interpretable feature [iF].

Turning now to distributive numerals the example in (28) shows that the distributive quantifier secili ‘each’ and the nga-marked NP nga dy libranga two books’ together yield only one distributive relation (no multiplication of distributivity).

The observed non-multiplication of distributivity can be captured by applying Zeijlstra’s mechanism of upward agree to distributive numerals:

Note that Zeijlstra’s (Reference Zeijlstra2012) condition (c) given in (27) is stated in terms of ‘closest Goal’. The reason of replacing ‘closest Goal of α’ with ‘local to α’ in (29) is that intervention effects (suggested by possible violations of ‘closest goal’) seem irrelevant for our purposes, whereas locality (meaning essentially clause-boundedness) is crucial.

According to the DistConc analysis proposed here, nga carries unvalued or [uDist] features that induce an obligatory upward agree relation with a distributive operator. Modulo the difference in the content of the features themselves (negative vs. distributive) the non-multiplication of distributivity is captured in the same way as the non-multiplication of negation in NC.

Insofar as our proposal brings out parallelisms between the distributive dependency created by DistNums and negative dependencies, it is similar to Oh’s (Reference Oh2006) analysis briefly reviewed in the previous section. Given our present-day knowledge, Oh’s proposal seems self-contradictory because on the one hand she explicitly claims that DistNums enter a syntactic (rather than semantic) dependency with a distributivity operator, but on the other hand she assumes that DistNums behave on a par with NPIs, which in the meantime have been demonstrated Zeijlstra (Reference Zeijlstra2012) to be semantically rather than syntactically licensed, in contrast to NCIs. Note however that Oh (Reference Oh2006) is aware of the existence of various types of NPIs and the parallelism she proposes between ssik and NPIs concerns only those NPIs that need to be syntactically licensed, as made explicit in the following quote signaled to us by a reviewer: “Negative indefinites (or so-called n-words) in German, including ‘kein’, are special NPIs that have to be licensed by an abstract negation and do not have negative force by themselves.”

Oh’s proposal can thus be viewed, despite prima facie evidence, as a predecessor of our own analysis. Benefitting from the progress made in the meanwhile, we improve on Oh both theoretically, by making a fully implemented proposal in terms of upward agree, and empirically, by bringing up evidence showing that DistNums behave on a par with NCIs and contrast with NPIsFootnote 9. It should be clear that the resemblance between DistNums and NCIs is the very abstract notion of upward agree relation to which both of them are subject.

4.2. Clause-boundedness

An important advantage of the syntactic account proposed here is that it captures the clause-boundedness constraint to which DistNums are subject. Indeed, upward agree is constrained by locality (see (29)), which explains important contrasts between NCIs (which rely on upward agree) and NPIs, which are semantically licensed. In this section, we argue that similar locality contrasts exist between DistNums and dependent unmarked indefinites.

It has been shown (cf. Zanuttini Reference Zanuttini1991; Progovac Reference Progovac1994; Przepiórkowski & Kupść; Reference Przepiórkowski and Kupść1997: 10–13; Giannakidou & Quer Reference Giannakidou and Quer1997; Giannakidou Reference Giannakidou1997, Reference Giannakidou1998, Reference Giannakidou2000; Zeijlstra Reference Zeijlstra2012, among many others) that an NC relation is constrained by clause-boundedness, i.e. NC can only be established if the participating elements belong to the same clause. The Albanian examples in (30)Footnote 10 show the difference between NPIsFootnote 11 (built with ndo- as in ndonjë ‘any’) and NCIs (built with the negative prefix as- as in asgjë ‘nothing’) with respect to clause-boundedness:

These examples, built with the complementizer se “that” (introducing indicative clauses),Footnote 12 show that NPIs can be licensed by a negation that is outside the clause that contains the NPI itself. In such a configuration NCIs are unacceptable.

According to Zeijlstra’s (Reference Zeijlstra2012) analysis, the contrast between NCIs and NPIs is due to the fact that the former but not the latter entertain a syntactic dependency relation, upward agree, with the sentential neg operator. The dependency that characterizes NPIs, on the other hand, is semantic in nature and is not subject to locality: the NPI must occur in the scope of a downward entailing operator, which need not be local to the NPI.

The example in (31) shows that long-distance licensing of nga-marked numerals in the complement of tha ‘said’ is impossible:

Granting that DistConc is a purely syntactic relation (implemented here in terms of upward agree), the unacceptability of (31) is expected given the unacceptability of the NCI in (30).

Turning now to the so-called neg-raising phenomenon, it can be observed in Albanian with verbs such as dua ‘want’ or dëshiroj ‘desire’:Footnote 13

Interestingly, in this case the parallelism between NC and DistConc breaks down. Indeed, DistNums cannot be licensed long distance with dua ‘want’:

In sum, distributive numerals differ from NCIs in that they cannot be long-distance bound with neg-raising verbs. This difference is not surprising given the syntactic analysis of neg-raising (see Collins & Postal Reference Collins and Postal2014),Footnote 14 according to which neg is base-generated inside the embedded clause (at which stage locality is satisfied) and subsequently raised to its overt position. Under this syntactic view, neg-raising examples such as (32) do not constitute counter evidence to the locality of NC. On the other hand, there is no reason to assume that in neg-raising contexts each itself would be raised from the embedded clause, where it would be first merged. It is only neg rather than a random licensor (item marked with interpretable features) that can be generated in an embedded clause and moved past a main verb in the mapping to overt syntax. Sentential negation and distributivity operators are alike in that both can function as licensors of upward agree, which is strictly local. They differ in that neg, but not each, can raise above neg-raising verbs.

It is interesting to observe that unmarked cardinal numerals can be interpreted as dependent on the distributive quantifier secili ‘each’, even if the latter does not belong to the same clause. The two examples below differ between each other only in that the main verb does not allow vs. allows neg-raising. In both cases, an unmarked indefinite can be licensed by secili, which occurs in the main clause:

In the so-called wide scope scenario, there are two students in the discourse context such that each professor said of those two students that they won. In the narrow scope scenario, students co-vary with professors. Each professor in the discourse context said of different groups of two students that they won.

The sharp contrast between the ungrammaticality of the examples in (31)–(33) and the perfect acceptability of the examples in (34) clearly shows that nga-marked DPs are not to be analyzed on a par with dependently interpreted unmarked indefinites (contra Brasoveanu & Farkas Reference Brasoveanu and Farkas2011).Footnote 15 Our explanation of the contrast is that DistNums must enter a syntactic relation (upward agree) with their licensor, whereas unmarked indefinites must enter a semantic dependency.Footnote 16 The contrast between DistNums and unmarked indefinites is thus parallel to the contrast between NCIs and NPIs.

The data are replicated in Romanian. In each of the (a) sentences below, the cardinal can either scope below or above the distributive quantifier in subject position. In the (b) sentences on the other hand, the distributive markers (câte in Romanian) are ungrammatical due to a violation of the clause-boundedness constraint. Examples (35) and (36) show that distributive numerals are blocked in the complement clauses of a spus ‘(has) said’ and voia ‘wanted’, respectively.

Further evidence in favor of the locality constraint on DistNums is given by Kuhn (Reference Kuhn2017, Reference Kuhn2019) for Hungarian. The following examples show that an if-clause blocks the licensing of a distributive numeral, although it does not disturb unmarked indefinites (which show scope ambiguities):

The same constraint can be observed for nga-marked numerals in Albanian. In (38a) the indefinite dy studentë ‘two students’ can co-vary in the scope of secili profesor ‘each professor’ or outscope it. But (38b) is ungrammatical because the licensing of nga is impossible across syntactic islands.

Romanian and Greek data confirm the same constraint:

In sum, DistNums are subject to a strict locality constraint, in clear contrast with unmarked indefinites. This difference shows that the crucial property of DistNums is not a semantic feature that signals obligatory narrow focus or dependency with respect to a distributivity operator. If this were so, we would expect DistNums to be able to be dependent on a Distributivity operator that lies outside their local domain, on par with unmarked cardinals; see examples (35)–(37) and (38)–(40). This expectation is not fulfilled.

Throughout the paper we have indicated that unmarked cardinal indefinites allow for both a ‘narrow’ scope (or rather dependent reading) and a ‘wide’ scope reading, in contrast to DistNums, for which only the former is possible.

Although it is somewhat orthogonal to our main concerns, it is worthwhile recalling that the extra-wideFootnote 17 scope (i.e scope above the clausal domain) of unmarked indefinites is strong evidence against a quantificational analysis of indefinites and in favor of a choice-functional analysis (Reinhart Reference Reinhart1997). This analysis explains why those indefinites that seem to scope outside islands (or outside the clause in which they sit at S-structure) can take ‘existential’ scope but not distributive scope over another indefinite:

The reading we have so far indicated by ‘cardinal>each’ (see in particular examples (37a) and (38a)) can also be observed in (41a, b). Indeed, in addition to the dependent reading of the lower indefinite (on which we are talking about 6 students) we also have a ‘wide’ scope reading, on which we are talking about only two students. But crucially, this second reading cannot be paraphrased as “for each of the two students there are three (different) professors who said that each student graduated/who wanted that each student obtains the diploma.” This would be true in a scenario involving two students and six professors. This illustrates the well-known fact that the ‘extra-wide scope’ of unmarked indefinites is not a genuine scope phenomenon: the unmarked indefinite should not be analyzed as a quantifier that raises outside its local domain. Talking in terms of scope is a short-hand description of the relevant interpretation. The most plausible analysis, which allows the indefinite to be analyzed in its S-structure position, involves choice functions (Reinhart Reference Reinhart1997) or some refinement thereof.

Rounding up, unmarked indefinites can be interpreted either as ‘scopeless’ or as dependent elements. In both cases they are insensitive to locality, which is captured by (Skolemized) choice-functional analyses. DistNums are, on the other hand, subject to a strict locality constraint, which indicates that a choice functional analysis is inappropriate. In this paper we have concentrated on the syntactic analysis, according to which DistNums must enter a purely syntactic relation implemented in terms of upward agree. The semantic composition that would be read off the proposed LFs would arguably involve existential quantifiers taking obligatory narrow scope with respect to a distributive operator. We leave the implementation of this view for future work.

An alternative account of the clause-boundedness of DistNums was proposed by Kuhn (Reference Kuhn2019), according to whom these elements must be QR-ed above the distributive key. Since QR is necessarily local, DistNums and the distributive key are necessarily local to each other. It seems to us that this proposal, which is specifically designed for DistNums,Footnote 18 is not supported by independent evidence and its theoretical advantages remain to be evaluated.Footnote 19

5. When the distributivity operator is silent

An important challenge for the distributive concord analysis proposed here comes from those examples in which nga-marked DPs are not licensed by a distributive operator, such as secili ‘each’ or çdo ‘every’, but rather by a plural DP (or a plurality of time intervals or spatial areas, left aside here). For such cases, the simplest hypothesis would seem to be that nga is itself a distributive operator, the plural DP providing only the restriction of that operator. We would thus end up assuming that nga is ambiguous between a distributivity concord marker (when it is licensed by an overt distributive operator, secili ‘each’ or çdo ‘every’) and a distributivity operator (when it is licensed by a plural DP). In what follows, we show that this undesirable move is not necessary and that the distributive concord analysis proposed in the previous section can be extended provided that we assume that a silent distributivity operator is present in the LF representation of examples built with plural DP keys. In Section 5.1, we argue that this assumption is not a mere stipulation but is in fact supported by our current knowledge regarding plural predication. The remaining subsections are devoted to other configurations that require postulating a silent distributivity operator: fragment answers on the one hand and multiple nga’s on the other hand (see Sections 5.2 and 5.3, respectively).

5.1. When the key is a plural DP

Let us consider examples, such as (42b), where nga is not licensed by a distributive quantifier but rather by a plural DP:

Sentence (42a) is ambiguous between a collective and a distributive reading. This ambiguity can be explained by assuming that the two interpretations are structurally different, involving distinct LF representations, depending on whether Link’s (Reference Link1983, Reference Link1987) silent pluralization or distributivityFootnote 20 operator (D-operator henceforth) is projected or not at LF:

Assuming that the cardinal indefinite two puppies denotes an existential quantifier, the formula in (43a) can be rewritten as follows:

According to this formula, the example in (42a) has a collective reading, i.e. it is true in a situation in which there is a plurality x made up of two puppies such that the children washed x.

Turning now to the formula in (43b), Link (Reference Link1987) viewed the D-operator as a silent version of the adverbial or floated use of each in English:

In this example, each applies to a predicate over atomic individuals (λx. wash two puppies(x)) and returns a predicate each(λx. wash two puppies(x)) that is true of any sum individual whose atomic parts each satisfy λx. wash two puppies (x).

The D-operator can be viewed as having the denotation just described for the floated each (see in particular Champollion Reference Champollion2019: 6):

Given this denotation of D, we obtain (47) as the denotation of the predicate in (42b). By applying (46) to [[the children]] and by translating two puppies as an existential, we get the formula in (48):

This formula says that ‘For each atomic member x of the maximal plurality of children, there are two puppies y such that x washed y’. Since the existential – which quantifies over plural entities of two puppies – is in the scope of the distributivity operator, the groups may vary from one child to the other.Footnote 21

To recap, the formulae in (43a) and (43b), which differ by the presence and absence of the D-operator, respectively correspond to the collective and distributive readings of sentences built with unmarked numeral indefinites.

Turning now to DistNums, it is natural to assume that they trigger the obligatory projection of the D-operator due to the fact that they carry a [uDist] feature that needs to be checked by the [iDist] feature on the D-operator. This feature-checking analysis is illustrated in (49), which corresponds to example (42b):

The data we have discussed in the present section show that nga-marked numerals can enter an upward agree relation with a covert D-operator. Since the covert D-operator is independently needed for the analysis of the distributive readings of unmarked cardinals,Footnote 22 our analysis is ‘non stipulative’, i.e. it relies on already existing assumptions. The only role of nga-marking is to force the projection of the D-operator: the non-projection of the D-operator would yield ill-formedness because the uninterpretable features of nga would remain unchecked.

5.2. Fragment answers

Fragment answers provide an interesting context in which a covert D operator is needed. On the other hand, fragment answers constitute another context in which DistNums differ from NPIs.

The example below shows that the NPI ndonjë ‘any(one)’ is banned in fragment answers as opposed to the NCI asnjë ‘no one’.

Fragment answers are elliptical constituents that receive a sentential interpretation. Thus, the Neg-word asnjë occurring on its own in (51) is interpreted as meaning ‘I have met no students’. According to Giannakidou (Reference Giannakidou2000, Reference Giannakidou2006), fragment answers involve unpronounced material (notated with striking out) that contains the sentential negation operator (nuk in Albanian), which licenses the fragment Neg-word:

As pointed out by Watanabe (Reference Watanabe2004), Giannakidou’s analysis is problematic in that the elided negative operator is not subject to the identity condition, which is known to constrain ellipsis. Moreover, the elided negation should be able to license not only Neg-words but also NPIs. However, fragment NPIs are unacceptable.

These problems are taken care of in Zeijlstra’s (Reference Zeijlstra2008) analysis, according to which the elided material does not contain a sentential negation operator and the licensing of fragment Neg-words is ensured by a silent negation operator notated Op¬. Thus, in Zeijlstra’s framework the example in (51) is to be represented as:

In addition to assuming a silent Op¬, this representation is obtained by raising the fragment Neg-word to a Focus-related position and then deleting the remaining material. This configuration allows upward agree because the licensor (Op¬) C-commands the element to be licensed (Neg-word). Crucially for our present purposes, fragment NPIs are correctly ruled out: since NPIs do not carry any uninterpretable neg feature, they cannot be licensed via upward agree.

However, Zeijlstra’s analysis of fragment Neg-words is not compelling since it needs to postulate a covert Op¬ that occurs nowhere else in strict NC languages.Footnote 23 Moreover, the postulated covert Op¬ does not seem to be subject to any identity constraint. It seems fair to say that fragment Neg-words remain a problem for an upward agree account and more generally for all those analyses that take Neg-words to be indefinite-like existentials that do not carry negative semantics. One may therefore assume (following Zanuttini Reference Zanuttini1991; Haegeman & Zanuttini Reference Haegman and Raffaella1991, Reference Haegeman, Raffaella and Rizzi1996; Watanabe Reference Watanabe2004) that fragment answers constitute a context (maybe the only one) in which Neg-words in strict NC languages are Neg quantifiers, which means that they are not licensed by a covert Op¬, but instead they themselves contribute Negation.

As we see below, the problems raised by fragment Neg-words do not concern fragment DistNums, for which an upward agree analysis is unproblematic. The examples in (53) show the use of nga-marked numerals in fragment answers:

Romanian displays the same behavior:

Given the analysis of DistNums proposed in this paper, example (53) can be analyzed as in (55):

This analysis of fragment DistNums differs from Zeijlstra’s analysis of fragment Neg-words and is more in line with Giannakidou’s analysis in that the covert D-operator does not sit in a high position but instead is part of the elided material.

Interestingly, the problems raised by Neg-words turn into supporting evidence for DistNums. The first favorable observation is that silent D-operators are not manufactured on purpose for fragment DistNums but have been independently motivated for full sentences built with plural DPs in subject positions and unmarked cardinal indefinites in object positions (see example (3) in Section 2).

Moreover, the silent D-operator in fragment DistNums can be shown to be subject to the Identity constraint on ellipsis. Indeed, fragment DistNums are unacceptable if the subject of the question is a singular DP:

This unacceptability is due to the fact that the D-operator cannot be inserted in a sentence in which the external argument is singular (Kratzer Reference Kratzer, Edited and Dölling2007 on verb plurality). The question in (56) is well-formed, but it cannot be answered with a fragment DistNum because the insertion of a D-operator is impossible.

Given the identity condition on ellipsis, the LFs of the fragment answers in (56) do not contain a silent D-operator (because there is no D-operator in the question that could license under Identity the D-operator in the fragment answer). Example (57a) is ruled out (as indicated by #), because the licensing of DistNums depends on the presence of a D-operator. Since unmarked numerals do not need to be licensed by a D-operator, the LF in (57b) is well-formed, but of course the distributive interpretation is blocked (because the D-operator is absent).

In sum, the contrast between the fragment answers in (53) and (56a) on the one hand and (56a) vs. (56b) on the other hand constitute important evidence in favor of our proposal, according to which distributive force cannot be contributed by the DistNum itself. Such elements are marked with purely syntactic features that require them to enter a licensing relation (upward agree) with an overt or covert D-operator.

5.3. Conjunction

According to the analysis proposed here, DistNums can be licensed by a covert distributive operator. Kuhn (Reference Kuhn2015, Reference Kuhn2017) argues that examples of the type in (58)Footnote 24 constitute evidence against this hypothesis:

Let us imagine that (58) describes a context where six students are having dinner. In this scenario, the first conjunct, in which the object is a plain indefinite két eloételt ‘two appetizers’ receives a collective reading. This means that only two appetizers were ordered by the six students together. The second conjunct, on the other hand, obligatorily receives a distributive reading, due to the presence of nga. This means that the number of main dishes is the same as the number of students: six. According to our proposal, this reading can be obtained only if a covert D-operator is projected (in order to check the [udist] feature of nga një). Kuhn argues that the presence of a covert distributive operator would force co-variation of the plain indefinite in the first conjunct, contrary to fact. Kuhn’s argument presupposes that the D-operator must take scope over the highest VP:

The problem can be solved by assuming that the example in (58) involves the coordination of two VPs (with deletion of the verb in the second conjunct), the D-operator being projected on the second conjunct alone:

The hypothesis that a covert D operator need not apply to the overall VP but can also apply to only one of the conjuncts is well-known for the analysis of Dowty’s (Reference Dowty1986) famous example given in (61):

The only difference between the example in (60) and that in (61) is that the former also involves the ellipsis under identity of the main verb in the second conjunct.

5.4. Multiple nga’s

This section examines data where two nga-marked cardinal indefinites co-occur with one distributive quantifier. Such sentences can have two interpretations: (a) each nga is licensed by its own distributive operator and (b) the two nga’s are licensed by a single distributive operator. Example (62) illustrates this:

The example in (62) can be true in the scenario (63):

This interpretation can be analyzed as involving two distributive operators, corresponding to each of the two nga’s. This means that in addition to the overt quantificational DP çdo ligjëratë ‘every lecture’, we need to assume a silent distributivity operator ranging over students and licensing nga tre artikuj ‘nga three articles’. Evidence in favor of this assumption comes from the observation that by inserting a floated secili ‘each’ we obtain the interpretation of (62) corresponding to the scenario described in (63):

(62) is also compatible with the scenario in (65),Footnote 25 which yields either a collective reading (which talks about joint presentations) or a cumulative reading (on which at each lecture three articles in all were presented by two students in all):

Corresponding to this scenario there is only one distributive operator that enters two agree relations, with each one of the nga-marked numerals.

We use the term Multiple Agree to refer to the configuration just described, where two DistNums check their [udist] features against a single [idist] feature of a single distributive operator. The other interpretation, corresponding to the scenario in (63), where each DistNum checks its [udist] feature against the [idist] feature of a separate distributive operator is referred to as Multiple Layers of Agree. Examples (66) and (67) provide the syntactic configurations of the two interpretations under discussion.

6. Conclusions

We have proposed a syntactic analysis of DistNums: they are marked with an uninterpretable feature that forces them to enter upward agree with a (covert or overt) distributive operator. This unique assumption explains the core crosslinguistic empirical generalizations that have been observed for DistNums: (i) because they are semantically empty (rather than inherently distributive), they do not add another layer of distributivity; (ii) because upward agree is constrained by locality, DistNums must be local to the distributive operator that licenses them; and (iii) because upward agree is subject to C-command, DistNums take obligatory narrow scope with respect to the distributive operator.

While semantic analyses exist to explain the facts (Kuhn Reference Kuhn2017; Law Reference Law2022), the present work is the first paper to build an explicit syntactic analysis of distributive concord. Compared to these semantic analyses, the present analysis moreover has the advantage of making use of a syntactic assumption that has been independently motivated for NC.

Footnotes

We would like to thank Hedde Zeijlstra, Peter Hallman, Daniel Büring, Patricia Cabredo-Hofherr, Lucia Tovena, Jeremy Kuhn, Ion Giurgea, and Mara Panaitescu as well as three anonymous reviewers for the Journal of Linguistics for comments and feedback on earlier versions of this paper. This work was partially supported by a public grant overseen by the IdEx Université Paris Cité (ANR-18-IDEX-0001) as part of the Labex Empirical Foundations of Linguistics (EFL). The first author was also supported by the University AAB. All errors are our own.

[2] This notation is used here only for descriptive purposes; it does not mean that we adhere to the scopal analysis of indefinite DPs (see Farkas Reference Farkas1997a, Reference Farkas1997b, Reference Farkas2001; Reinhart Reference Reinhart1997; Steedman Reference Steedman2003, Reference Steedman2006, among others, for choice-functional analyses of what had been traditionally analyzed as a scope ambiguity). As is made clear later in the paper, we assume a choice-functional analysis for unmarked indefinites but not for marked cardinals (see Section 4.2).

[3] The Greek examples in (10) are from Arhonto Terzi and Nikos Angelopoulos, personal communication to one of the authors.

[4] According to Kuhn (Reference Kuhn2019: 5–7), DistNums are ‘plurality filters on the output’ that restrict a set only to its plural objects. For instance, plurality filters restrict the set {a, b, c, a⊕b, a⊕c, b⊕c, a⊕b⊕c} only to its plural objects {a⊕b, a⊕c, b⊕c, a⊕b⊕c}. Kuhn’s ‘plurality filters’ are meant as an alternative to Henderson’s (Reference Henderson2014) assumption that DistNums are encoded with a post-supposition (a test which applies after value assignment has taken place) requiring that the output set of assignments map the index of the numeral to more than one thing. The Kaqchikel sentence (i) – where the DistNum ju-jun co-occurs with the pluractional affix ala’ – is true in a scenario where the speaker looked for different books. Thus ju-jun introduces the test ‘xi>n’, which requires the variable introduced by ju-jun to be mapped to multiple entities (in case n > 1 the output contains multiple plural entities). This entails that there must be more than one book that was looked for.

[5] Kuhn (Reference Kuhn2017, Reference Kuhn2019) is aware of the locality constraint on DistNums and captures it by assuming that those DPs that are marked by DistNums need to QR to a position where they have access to the plurality that supplies the distributive key. Since QR is local, DistNums should be local to the key (plural DP or distributive quantifier). The QR hypothesis also allows Kuhn to account for the lack of ‘double distributivity’; see the discussion of examples (22) in the main text.

[6] Two pieces of evidence are brought up by these authors: (i) in Basque, na-marking is compatible with non-additive functions such as temperature, e.g. Ontziak 36na gradutan egon behar dute laborategi honetan “The recipients have to be at 36 degrees each in this laboratory”, and (ii) na-marked numerals can be adequately used in contexts where the (group) entity referred to does not vary from one assignment to the other provided that the speaker ignores the non-variation. Note that the fact reported in (i) for Basque has been argued not to be reproduced in Romanian, where the use of non-additive functions yields degraded acceptability for the use of the DistNum câte (see Panaitescu Reference Panaitescu2019). On the other hand, the fact in (ii) can be captured in the pragmatics: the semantic interpretation would yield a ‘plural’ output, which can be overridden in the pragmatics, by assigning the same referential index to the entities in that plurality.

[7] We would like to thank a reviewer for pointing to an analysis in terms of [idist] and [udist] features in Kimmelman (Reference Kimmelman2015) regarding distributive quantification in Russian sign language. It seems impossible to find it in any form other than a conference abstract: https://drive.google.com/file/d/0B24EkVft6n6oV29XNTdROEI5cGs/edit?resourcekey=0-Im8u48X4Cxsa7XAwWjUl5w.

[8] We use ‘OPdist’ to mean an overt distributive operator such as secili ‘each’ as well as a covert distributive operator notated as D.

[9] Note, however, that the distinction between NPIs and NCIs is even today not as clear-cut as one might think, and their respective definitions vary from one author to the other. Importantly, neither NCIs nor NPIs can be unambiguously identified in the Lexicon. Only N(eg)-words are identifiable by being lexically marked as negative (nobody, nothing, no, etc.). But being a Neg-word does not say anything about its syntactic or semantic properties. Depending on whether a language (or even a particular configuration) requires or bans Neg-concord, a Neg-word is analyzed as an NCI, an NPI, or a Neg quantifier.

[10] This is the Albanian counterpart of a Greek example by Giannakidou (Reference Giannakidou and Déprez2020: 471 ex. (38)).

[11] See Xherija (Reference Xherija, Brown, Gu, Loos, Mielens and Neveu2014) for some discussion of strong and weak NPIs in Albanian.

[12] For Albanian complementizers see the discussion in Joseph (Reference Joseph2016) and references cited therein.

[13] neg-raising with believe is disallowed with Albanian (on a par with Serbo-Croatian) but allowed in Greek and Italian. We do not have an explanation for this crosslinguistic difference but this issue does not directly bear on the puzzle of DistNums that we address in the paper.

[14] This syntactic account has been questioned by theoreticians who provide evidence in favor of semantic implicature-based accounts (Zeijlstra Reference Zeijlstra2017; Mirrazi & Zeijlstra Reference Mirrazi and Zeijlstra2021).

[15] Henderson (Reference Henderson2014) provides an important independent argument against Farkas’s (Reference Farkas1997a) and Brasoveanu & Farkas’s (Reference Brasoveanu and Farkas2011) attempts to subsume distributive numerals under the analysis of unmarked dependent indefinites: in Kaqchikel unmarked numerals cannot scope below a pluractional operator whereas distributive numerals can.

[16] This does not mean, however, that the semantic dependencies characteristic of dependent unmarked indefinites and NPIs is the same: whereas dependent indefinites are not to be analyzed in scopal terms but rather in terms of dependent indices (Farkas Reference Farkas1997a) or Skolem functions (Steedman Reference Steedman2012), the constraint on NPIs is currently formulated in terms of scope (NPIs have to occur in the scope of downward entailing licensors).

[17] See Szabolcsi (Reference Szabolcsi2010) for the distinction between existential and distributive scope.

[18] Kuhn (Reference Kuhn2017) suggests that his analysis of DistNums extends to the internal reading of same and different but does not demonstrate that this proposal is superior to a parasitic scope analysis à la Barker (Reference Barker2007).

[19] Kuhn (Reference Kuhn2017) discusses a counter-example to his QR-based account of the locality constraint on DistNums, also investigated by Law (Reference Law2022).

In this example, the noun phrase that restricts the distributive numeral contains a pronoun, which is bound by the universal quantifier that licenses the distributive numeral. The distributive numeral cannot be assumed to raise above the universal quantifier, since in that case the pronoun would remain unbound. Kuhn suggests a scope-splitting mechanism, which Law (Reference Law2022) implements in Charlow’s (Reference Charlow2022) framework.

[20] As defined by Link (Reference Link1983), the pluralization or star operator could only apply to inherently distributive predicates such as laugh, whereas Link’s (Reference Link1987) D-operator can apply to any predicate, in particular to complex predicates such as those denoted by VPs that contain internal arguments. Note, however, that some authors use the star notation for a pluralization or distributive operator that resembles the D-operator in not being restricted to inherently distributive predicates. See Champollion (Reference Champollion2019) for a clarification of the differences in empirical coverage between the star-operator and the D-operator. This choice is not directly relevant for our present concerns. For convenience our analysis is implemented in terms of the D-operator.

[21] Note, however, that they do not need to vary: indeed, the same group of two puppies can be washed several times, each time by a different child. But this reading needs to be contextually induced by information indicating absence of co-variation. See also Footnote footnote 5.

[22] A reviewer has raised the question as to whether the D operator that licenses distributive numerals in Albanian is the same as the D operator that is responsible for the distributive readings of unmarked indefinites. For Korean, Oh (Reference Oh2006) argued that it is not the same. Oh’s motivation was that in Korean the event-key reading is possible only with distributive numerals. For the reviewer, the Korean data suggests the need to posit two different D operators, for the participant-key and for the event-key readings, respectively. We agree with this suggestion. But because, in the limits of this article, we have left event-key readings aside, we leave for further research the issues related to such readings: (i) the constraints on the insertion of a silent event-key D and (ii) the constraints on the dependency relation itself: why is it that only DistNums (in contrast to unmarked cardinal indefinites) can depend on the event-key D?

[23] In order to block massive overgeneration, the insertion of a covert Op¬ should be viewed as a last resort mechanism, which has however not yet been made precise. Concretely, we do not understand why in strict NC languages the covert Op¬ can be inserted in fragments and only in fragments.

[24] Kuhn gives an example from Hungarian, where DistNum’s are marked by reduplication of the numeral:

[25] The interpretation illustrated in the scenario (65) can also be observed with German data involving jeweils-marked numerals. In the example in (i) both books and girls co-vary with boys, which indicates that both instances of jeweils are licensed by the QDP jeder junge ‘every boy’:

References

REFERENCES

Bajrami, Bade & Hamiti, Vjosa & Blakqori, Teutë. (2020). An Empirical Contribution to the Study of Distributivity Markers: Evidence From Kosovo Albanian. TURUK International Language, Literature and Folklore Researches Journal, 2443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balusu, R. (2006). Distributive reduplication in Telugu. Proceedings NELS, 36, p. 39.Google Scholar
Barker, C. (2007). Parasitic scope. Linguistics & Philosophy, 30(4).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brasoveanu, A. (2007). Structured nominal and modal reference. Ph.D. dissertation, New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University.Google Scholar
Brasoveanu, A. (2008). Donkey pluralities: plural information states versus non-atomic individuals. Linguistics and philosophy, 31, 129209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brasoveanu, A., & Henderson, R. (2009). Varieties of distributivity: 'one by one'vs' each'. Semantics and Linguistic Theory, 19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brasoveanu, Adrian, & Farkas, Donka F. (2011). How indefinites choose their scope. Linguistics and philosophy 34, 155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cable, S. (2014). Distributive numerals and distance distributivity in Tlingit (and beyond). Language, 562606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cabredo-Hofherr, P. & Etxeberria, U. (2017). Distributive numerals in Basque. Proceedings of 21st Amsterdam Colloquium, (pp. 185194).Google Scholar
Champollion, L. (2016). Overt distributivity in algebraic semantics. Semantics and Pragmatics, 9, 16–1.Google Scholar
Champollion, L. (2019). Distributivity in formal semantics. Annual Review of Linguistics, 5, 289308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charlow, S. (2022). Post-suppositions and semantic theory. Journal of Semantics.Google Scholar
Choe, J.-W. (1987). Anti-quantifiers and a theory of distributivity. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachusetts Amherst.Google Scholar
Collins, Collins & Postal, Paul. (2014). Classical neg raising: An essay on the syntax of negation (Vol. 67). MIT press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dotlačil, J. (2015). Why is distributivity so hard? New evidence from distributive markers and licensors in Czech. Proceedings of FDSL, 10.Google Scholar
Dowty, D. (1986). A Note on collective predicates, distributive predicates and All. In Proceedings of the Third Eastern States Conference on Linguistics (ESCOL 86) (pp. 97115). Ohio State University.Google Scholar
Farkas, D. (1997a). Dependent indefinites. Empirical issues in formal syntax and semantics.Google Scholar
Farkas, D. (1997b). Evaluation indices and scope. In A. Szabolcsi, Ways of scope taking (pp. 183215.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farkas, D. (2001). Dependent indefinites and direct scope. Logical perspectives on language and information, (pp. 4172.).Google Scholar
Farkas, D. (2002). Varieties of Indefinites. Semantics and Linguistic Theory, 12, pp. 5983.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farkas, D. (2015). Dependent indefinites revisited. Workshop on co-distributivity. Paris.Google Scholar
Giannakidou, A. & Quer, Josep. (1997). Long-distance licensing of negative indefinites. In P. H. Edited by Danielle Forget, Negation and Polarity: Syntax and semantics. Selected papers from the colloquium Negation: Syntax and Semantics. Ottawa, 11–13 May 1995 (pp. 95114).Google Scholar
Giannakidou, A. (1997). The landscape of polarity items. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Groningen.Google Scholar
Giannakidou, A. (1998). Polarity sensitivity as (non) veridical dependency. Linguistik Aktuell/Linguistics Today, 23 - John Benjamins Publishing Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giannakidou, A. (2000). Negative… concord? Natural Language & Linguistic Theory, 18(3), 457523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giannakidou, A. (2006). N-words and negative concord. In The Blackwell Companion to Syntax 3 (pp. 327391).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giannakidou, A. (2020). Negative concord and the nature of negative concord items. In Déprez, M. T. Viviane (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Negation (pp. 458478). Oxford Handbooks Online.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giannakidou, A., & Zeijlstra, H. (2017). The landscape of negative dependencies: negative concord and n-words. In The Wiley Blackwell companion to syntax (pp. 138).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gil, D. (1982). Quantifier scope, linguistic variation and natural language semantics. Linguistics and Philosophy, 421472.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gryllia, S. (2007). A distance distributing prepositional numeral. Selected papers on theoretical and applied linguistics, 17(1), pp. 117126.Google Scholar
Guha, I. (2018). Distributivity across domains: a study of the distributive numerals in Bangla. Ph.D. dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Haegeman, Liliane & Raffaella, Zanuttini. (1996). Negative concord in West Flemish. In Rizzi, A. B., Parameters and Functional Heads: Essays in Comparative Syntax (pp. 117–80). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haegman, Liliane & Raffaella, Zanuttini. (1991). Negative heads and the Neg criterion. The Linguistic Review, 233–51.Google Scholar
Henderson, R. (2012). Ways of pluralizing events. Ph.D. dissertation, UC Santa Cruz.Google Scholar
Henderson, R. (2014). Dependent indefinites and their post-suppositions. Semantics and Pragmatics 7, 6–1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joseph, B. D. (2016). The semantics and syntax of complementation markers as an areal phenomenon in the Balkans, with special attention to Albanian. In E. b. Kehayov, Complementizer semantics in European languages, 57 (p. 265).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kimmelman, V. (2015). Distributive quantification in Russian sign language. Presentation at Formal and Experimental Advances in Sign Language Theory. Barcelona, Spain.Google Scholar
Kratzer, A. (2007). On the plurality of verbs. In Edited, T. H.-Z. by: Dölling, Johannes, Event structures in linguistic form and interpretation (pp. 269300).Google Scholar
Kuhn, J. (2015). Cross-categorial singular and plural reference in sign language. Ph.D. dissertation, New York University.Google Scholar
Kuhn, J. (2017). Dependent indefinites: the view from sign language. Journal of Semantics, 34(3), 407446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, J. (2019). Pluractionality and distributive numerals. Language and Linguistics Compass, 13(2).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, J. (2021). The dynamics of negative concord. Linguistics and Philosophy, 45(1), 153198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, Jeremy & Aristodemo, Valentina. (2017). Pluractionality, iconicity, and scope in French Sign Language. Semantics and Pragmatics, 10(6), 149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laka Mugarza, M. I. (1990). Negation in syntax-on the nature of functional categories and projections. Ph.D. dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Law, J. H. (2022). The mereological structure of distributivity: A case study of binominal each. Journal of Semantics, 39(1), 159211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Link, G. (1983). The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms: A lattice-theoretical approach. In Formal semantics: The essential readings (pp. 127147). Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Link, G. (1987). Generalized quantifiers and plurals. In I. P. (ed.), Generalized quantifiers (pp. 151180). Berlin, Germany: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mirrazi, Zahra & Zeijlstra, Hedde. (2021). Neg-raising without lexical excluded middle inferences: Resolving Horn Clauses and other problems. In Proceedings of the 23rd Seoul International Conference on Generative Grammar (SICOGG 23): A Comparative Approach to the Syntax-Semantics Interface, 299, p. 299.Google Scholar
Oh, S.-R. (2001). Distributivity in an event semantics. Semantics and linguistic theory, (pp. 326345).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oh, S.-R. (2006). Plurality markers across languages. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Connecticut.Google Scholar
Panaitescu, M. (2018). Romanian dependent numerals as ratios. Romance languages and linguistic theory 13 (p. 245). Nijmegen, 13: Selected papers from ‘Going Romance’ 29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Panaitescu, M. (2019). Distributivity and Additivity: the case of the Romanian distributive marker câte. Universitätsbibliothek Tübingen.Google Scholar
Progovac, L. (1994). Negative and positive polarity: A binding approach (Vol. 68). Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Przepiórkowski, Adam, & Kupść, Anna. (1997). Negative concord in Polish. Tech. Rep. 828 Institute of Computer Science, Polish Academy of Sciences.Google Scholar
Reinhart, T. (1997). Quantifier scope. How labor is divided between QR and choice functions. Linguistics and Philosophy 20, 335397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rushiti, B. (2019). Share-marking in Albanian: the distributive marker nga. Ph.D. dissertation, Université de Paris.Google Scholar
Steedman, M. (2003). Scope alternation and the syntax/semantics interface. CSSP. Paris.Google Scholar
Steedman, M. (2006). Surface-compositional scope-alternation without existential quantifiers. Ms available on http://hompages.inf.ed.ac.uk/steedman./papers.html.Google Scholar
Steedman, M. (2012). Taking scope: The natural semantics of quantifiers. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Szabolcsi, A. (2010). Quantification. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watanabe, A. (2004). The genesis of negative concord: Syntax and morphology of negative doubling. Linguistic Inquiry 35(4), 559612.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Xherija, O. (2014). Weak and strong NPIs: nobody and anybody in Albanian and Modern Greek. In Brown, C., Gu, Q., Loos, C., Mielens, J. and Neveu, G. (eds.) Proceedings of the 15th Meeting of the Texas Linguistic Society. Austin, TX: Texas Linguistics Society, (pp. 184201).Google Scholar
Zanuttini, R. (1991). Syntactic Properties of Sentential Negation: A Comparative Study of Romance Languages. University of Pennsylvania dissertation.Google Scholar
Zeijlstra, H. (2004). Sentential negation and negative concord. Ph.D. dissertation, Netherlands Graduate School of Linguistics.Google Scholar
Zeijlstra, H. (2008). On the syntactic flexibility of formal features. In T. Biberauer, The limits of syntactic variation, 132, (pp. 143173).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zeijlstra, H. (2012). There is only one way to agree. The linguistic review, 29(3), 491539.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zeijlstra, H. (2017). Does neg-raising involve neg-raising? Topoi, 37(3), 417433.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zimmerman, M. (2002). Boys buying two sausages each: On the syntax and semantics of distance-distributivity.. Ph.D. dissertation, Netherlands Graduate School of Linguistics.Google Scholar