Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-09T11:09:48.289Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Theory of Evolution as Personal Knowledge

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Edward Manier*
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame

Abstract

Dr. Marjorie Grene has argued that criteria taken from a personalist philosophy of science have regulative force in the dispute between orthogenetic and synthetic or neo-Darwinian theories of evolution, and that these criteria commend the acceptance of the orthogenetic position. Grene's position includes two basically correct theses concerning the limitations of operationism and reductionism. However, she fails to show that personalist tenets are necessary for the validation of these two theses. Moreover, the proposed modifications of evolutionary theory depend upon additional premisses: that biology must study individuals rather than populations, and that the synthetic theory must prove that natural selection and mutation are the only possible factors for control of the direction of evolutionary change. The evidence for these premisses is called into question.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1965

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] Beckner, Morton, Biological Way of Thought. New York: Columbia University Press, 1959.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2] Bock, W. J. and von Wahlert, G.Two Evolutionary Theories—A Discussion,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, XIV, No. 54 (August, 1963), pp. 140146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3] Carnap, Rudolph, “The Methodological Character of Theoretical Concepts,” Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. I. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1956, pp. 3876.Google Scholar
[4] Carter, G. S., “Two Evolutionary Theories, by M. Grene; A Further Discussion,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, XIV, No. 54 (February, 1964), pp. 345349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[5] Fisher, R. A., The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection, 2nd edition. New York: Dover, 1958.Google Scholar
[6] Frank, Philipp, Philosophy of Science. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, 1957.Google Scholar
[7] Grene, Marjorie, “The Logic of Biology,” in The Logic of Personal Knowledge. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1961, pp. 191205.Google Scholar
[8] Grene, Marjorie, “Statistics and Selection,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, XII, No. 45 (May, 1961), pp. 2542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[9] Grene, Marjorie, “Two Evolutionary Theories,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, IX, No. 34, (August, 1958) pp. 110-127 and no. 35, (November, 1958) pp. 185193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[10] Grene, Marjorie, “Two Evolutionary Theories: A Reply,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, XIV, No. 54 (August, 1963), pp. 152–54.Google Scholar
[11] Grene, Marjorie, “Two Evolutionary Theories: Reply to Dr. Carter,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, XIV, No. 56 (February, 1964), pp. 349351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[12] Nagel, Ernest, The Structure of Science. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1961.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[13] Pap, Arthur, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. New York: Free Press of Glencoe, 1962.Google Scholar
[14] Slobodkin, L. B., Growth and Regulation of Animal Populations. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston, 1962.Google Scholar
[15] Sokal, R. & Sneath, P., Principles of Numerical Taxonomy. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1963.Google Scholar
[16] Van Valen, L., “On Evolutionary Theories,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, XIV, No. 54 (August, 1963), pp. 146–52.Google Scholar