Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-sjtt6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-18T18:27:27.507Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Wittgensteinian blasphemy: what it's like to be a heretic

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 February 2023

Benjamin W. McCraw*
Affiliation:
Department of History, Political Science, Philosophy, and American Studies, University of South Carolina Upstate, Spartanburg, SC, USA

Abstract

In this article, I explore a Wittgensteinian approach to blasphemy. While philosophy of religion tends to have very little to say about blasphemy, we can note two key, typically unchallenged, assumptions about it. First, there is the Assertion from Anywhere Assumption: whether one can successfully blaspheme is entirely independent of one's religious views, commitments, or way of life. Second, there is the Act of Communication Assumption: blasphemy is essentially an act of assertion. I contend that a Wittgensteinian approach rejects both assumptions and, thus, reorients our conception of blasphemy. Take two characteristically Wittgensteinian claims. First, religious statements/beliefs have a different ‘grammar’ than empirical propositions. Second (and relatedly), holding religious beliefs necessarily connects with how one lives. Wittgensteinian blasphemy rejects the Assertion from Anywhere Assumption: to blaspheme, one must be in or have been in the religious framework one blasphemes. Being entirely outside of that context divests one's blasphemy from its proper content. Second, Wittgensteinian blasphemy rejects the Act of Communication Assumption: if religious belief is centrally a form of life, then blasphemy must be lived out as well. Wittgensteinian blasphemy is less about the utterances one makes and more about how one's life intersects (or fails to intersect) with religiosity.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Augustine, (2002) On Genesis. Edmund Hill E, O.P (trans.). New York: New City Press.Google Scholar
Baghramian, M and Carter, JA (2021) Relativism. In Zalta EN (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/relativism/.Google Scholar
Boghossian, P (2006) Fear of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructivism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burley, M (2008) Phillips and realists on religious beliefs and the fruits thereof. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 64, 141153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coliva, A (2010) Was Wittgenstein an epistemic relativist? Philosophical Investigations 33, 123.Google Scholar
Fisher, A and Ramsay, H (2000) Of art and blasphemy. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 3, 137167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glock, H-J (2007) Relativism, commensurability and translatability. Ratio 20, 377402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffman, FJ (1983) Remarks on blasphemy. Scottish Journal of Religious Studies 4, 138151.Google Scholar
Hoffman, FJ (1989) More on blasphemy. Sophia 28, 2634.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malcolm, N (1964) Is it a religious belief that ‘God exists’? In Hick, J (ed.), Faith and the Philosophers. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 103110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGraw, C (2007) The realism/anti-realism debate in religion. Philosophy Compass 3, 254272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perret, RW (1987) Blasphemy. Sophia 26, 414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, DZ (1963) Philosophy, theology, and the reality of God. The Philosophical Quarterly 13, 344350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, DZ (1965) The Concept of Prayer. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Phillips, DZ (1970a) Death and Immorality. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, DZ (1970b) Faith and Philosophical Enquiry. New York: Schocken Books.Google Scholar
Phillips, DZ (1976) Religion without Explanation. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Phillips, DZ (1986) Belief, Change and Forms of Life. Basingstoke: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, DZ (1988) Faith After Foundationalism. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Phillips, DZ (1994) Wittgenstein and Religion. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Phillips, DZ (1995) Philosopher's clothes. In Lewis, CM (ed.), Relativism and Religion. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 135153.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D (2011) Epistemic relativism, epistemic incommensurability and Wittgensteinian epistemology. In Hales, SD (ed.), A Companion to Relativism. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing, pp. 266285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rhees, R (2003) Without Answers. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Scott, M (2000) Wittgenstein and realism. Faith and Philosophy 17, 170190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scott, M (2010) Religious language. Philosophy Compass 5, 505515.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan, M (2012) Semantics for blasphemy. In Kvanvig, J (ed.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, vol. 4. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 160173.Google Scholar
Tilghman, BR (1998) Isn't belief in God an attitude? International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 43, 1728.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vroom, H (2011) On blasphemy: an analysis. Ars Disputandi Supplement Series 5, 7594.Google Scholar
Williams, M (2007) Why (Wittgensteinian) contextualism is not relativism. Episteme 4, 93114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Winch, P (1977) Meaning and religious language. In Brown, SC (ed.), Reason and Religion. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, pp. 193221.Google Scholar
Winch, P (1990) The Idea of a Social Science and Its Relation to Philosophy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar