Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x24gv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-11T23:59:02.798Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Relativism, Fallibilism, and the Need for Interpretive Charity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 October 2022

Nadine Elzein*
Affiliation:
University of Warwick

Abstract

‘Relativists' and ‘absolutists' about truth often see their own camp as promoting virtues, such as open-mindedness and intellectual humility, and see the opposing camp as fostering vices, like closed-mindedness and arrogance. Relativism is accused of fostering these vices because it entails that each person’s beliefs are automatically right for the person who holds them. How can we be humble or open-minded if we cannot concede that we might be wrong? Absolutism is accused of fostering these vices because the view is seen as entailing certainty. This also seems to preclude us from conceding that we could be wrong. However, no relativist defends the Protagorean version of relativism that entails infallibilism. And no absolutist posits infallible certainty. Fallibilism really is a precondition of various virtues, but both camps take themselves to be defending fallibilist positions against opponents who they take to be committed to infallibilism. Philosophers may inadvertently end up promoting precisely the sort of infallibilism they oppose by creating a false dichotomy and caricaturing the opposing camp. This underscores the importance of interpretive charity in both academic and public debate.

Type
Paper
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Astola, Mandi, ‘Collective responsibility should be treated as a virtue’, Royal Institute Philosophy Supplementary Volume, 92 (2022) 2744.Google Scholar
Baghramian, Maria, ‘I. The Virtues of Relativism’, Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 93 (2019) 247–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bloom, Allan, The Closing of the American Mind: How Higher Education Has Failed Democracy and Impoverished the Souls of Today's Students (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1987).Google Scholar
Bloor, David, ‘Relativism and the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge’, in A Companion to Relativism, edited by Hales, Stephen (Oxford: Blackwell, 2011) 433–55.Google Scholar
Briatte, François, ‘Entretien avec David Bloor’, Tracés. Revue de Sciences humaines [En ligne], 12 (2007). English translation (unpublished but corrected and approved by David Bloor) available from url: https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-01511329/file/InterviewDB_FBriatte2007.pdf (accessed 3rd July 2021).Google Scholar
Code, Lorraine, ‘Must a Feminist Be a Relativist After All?’ In her Rhetorical Spaces (London: Routledge, 1995), 189207.Google Scholar
Code, Lorraine, What Can She Know? (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2018).Google Scholar
Costello, T. H., Bowes, S. M., Stevens, S. T., Waldman, I. D., Tasimi, A. & Lilienfeld, S. O., ‘Clarifying the structure and nature of left-wing authoritarianism’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Advance online publication (2021).Google Scholar
Derrida, Jacques, ‘Hospitality, justice and responsibility: a dialogue with Derrida’. In Questioning Ethics: Contemporary Debates in Continental Philosophy, edited by Dooley, Mark & Kearney, Richard, (London: Routledge, 1999) 6583.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul, Farewell to Reason (New York: Verso, 1987).Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel, Madness and Civilization: History of Insanity in the Age of Reason. Trans. Howard, Richard, (London: Tavistock Publications, 1967).Google Scholar
Geertz, Clifford, ‘Distinguished Lecture: Anti Anti-Relativism’. American Anthropologist, 86, (1984), 263–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herskovits, Melville J., ‘Tender- and Tough-Minded Anthropology and the Study of Values in Culture’, Southwestern Journal of Anthropology, 7 (1951) 2231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hönig, Kathrin, ‘Relativism or Anti-Anti-Relativism? Epistemological and Rhetorical Moves in Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science’, European Journal of Women's Studies, 12 (2005) 407419.Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans, ‘Absolutism and Relativism in Philosophy and Politics’. American Political Science Review, 42 (1948) 906914.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kakutani, Michiko, The Death of Truth, (Tim Duggan Books, 2019).Google Scholar
Knorpp, William Max Jr, ‘What Relativism Isn't’, Philosophy, 73 (1988), 277300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kusch, Martin, ‘Relativist Stances, Virtues and Vices’. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 93 (2019) 271291CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langton, Rae, ‘Feminism in Epistemology: Exclusion and Objectification’. In The Cambridge Companion to Feminism in Philosophy, edited by Fricker, M. & Hornsby, J., (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000) 127–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maguire, Joseph P., ‘Protagoras – or Plato?Phronesis, 18, (1973) 115–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marietta, Morgan, Tyler Farley, Tyler Cote and Paul Murphy, ‘The Rhetorical Psychology of Trumpism: Threat, Absolutism, and the Absolutist ThreatThe Forum, 15 (2017) 313–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rorty, Richard, Consequences of Pragmatism, (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota, 1982).Google Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C., The Empirical Stance, (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2002).Google Scholar
Watson, Lani, ‘Cultivating Curiosity in the Information Age’, Royal Institute Philosophy Supplementary Volume, 92 (2022) 129–48.Google Scholar
Zhu, Caroline, ‘Cancel Culture is Moral Absolutism, and it's unsustainable’, The Observer, January 17th 2020. https://observer.case.edu/zhu-cancelled-culture-is-moral-absolutism-and-its-unsustainable/. Accessed 26 November, 2021.Google Scholar