Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-5nwft Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-18T11:47:04.471Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Revisiting Coercion as an Element of Prohibited Intervention in International Law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 October 2023

Marko Milanovic*
Affiliation:
Professor of Public International Law, University of Reading, UK. E-mail: m.milanovic@reading.ac.uk.
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

International law prohibits states from intervening in the internal and external affairs of other states, but only if the method of intervention is coercive. This Article argues that coercion can be understood in two different ways or models. First, as coercion-as-extortion, a demand coupled with a threat of harm or the infliction of harm, done to extract some kind of concession from the victim state—in other words, an act targeting the victim state's will or decision-making calculus. Second, as coercion-as-control, an action materially depriving the victim state of its ability to control its sovereign choices. This may be done even through acts like cyber operations that the victim state is entirely unaware of. The Article argues that many of the difficulties surrounding the notion of coercion arise as a consequence of failing to distinguish between these two different models.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press for The American Society of International Law

Table of Contents

  1. I. Introduction     602

  2. II. The Structure of the Non-intervention Rule     606

    1. A. The Prohibition of Intervention in Outline     606

    2. B. The Relationship Between the Prohibition of Intervention and Other Rules     607

    3. C. Interference with Internal and External Affairs (domaine réservé)     609

    4. D. Coercion     612

    5. E. Mental Element(s): Intent of the Intervening State and Knowledge of the Victim State     617

  3. III. The Problem of Justification     620

    1. A. The Problem Explained     620

    2. B. Justification Through the Reserved Domain Element     622

    3. C. Enabling Unilateral Law Enforcement?     623

  4. IV. The Extortion Model of Coercion     626

    1. A. The Extortion Model in Outline     626

    2. B. Intent and Knowledge     630

    3. C. The Threshold of Coercion     632

  5. V. The Control Model of Coercion     640

    1. A. The Control Model in Outline     640

    2. B. Intent and Knowledge     644

    3. C. Threshold of Coercion     646

  6. VI. Conclusion     648

I. Introduction

The prohibition of intervention, requiring states to refrain from coercively interfering in the internal or external affairs of other states, is widely recognized as a cardinal rule of customary international law.Footnote 1 There is also widespread agreement about the constituent elements of the rule: (1) an interference with a state's internal or external affairs that is (2) coercive in character. As authoritatively interpreted by the International Court of Justice (ICJ) in the Nicaragua case, the principle of non-intervention

forbids all States or groups of States to intervene directly or indirectly in internal or external affairs of other States. A prohibited intervention must accordingly be one bearing on matters in which each State is permitted, by the principle of State sovereignty, to decide freely. One of these is the choice of a political, economic, social and cultural system, and the formulation of foreign policy. Intervention is wrongful when it uses methods of coercion in regard to such choices, which must remain free ones. The element of coercion, which defines, and indeed forms the very essence of, prohibited intervention, is particularly obvious in the case of an intervention which uses force . . . .Footnote 2

While the existence and authority of the customary rule prohibiting intervention is not today challenged by any state, the content and application of this rule have been disputed since its inception.Footnote 3 This is particularly the case with the element of coercion. Even though the ICJ regarded coercion as the “very essence” of prohibited intervention, it did not define it. Nor have scholars or states otherwise managed to agree on a definition. Almost forty years after Nicaragua, “the scope of coercion for purposes of prohibited intervention remains particularly undertheorized and underdeveloped,” as Caroline Krass, the general counsel of the U.S. Department of Defense, rightly noted in a recent speech.Footnote 4

My ambition in this Article is precisely to clarify this notion of coercion. On the one hand, its parameters must acknowledge that states interact with each other and exert pressure on one another all the time, for reasons good or bad. On the other hand, “coercion” must inhibit some forms of pressure, drawing a red line beyond which a state's sovereign policy choices would no longer remain free.Footnote 5

A threat or use of military force in violation of Article 2(4) of the UN Charter to affect such choices would indisputably amount to coercion in this sense. When, for instance, Russia (furtively, but reasonably clearly) threatened Ukraine with invasion on account (inter alia) of Ukraine's sovereign choices to align with the West and pursue membership in the European Union and the North Atlantic Treaty Organization (NATO),Footnote 6 and then went ahead with that invasion when its demands were not met, one could think of no clearer example of a state coercing another with respect to its external affairs.

But the content of coercion below the use of force threshold has remained contested. This has especially been the case with measures of political and economic pressure, including unilateral sanctions.Footnote 7 When, for instance, in 2017 Saudi Arabia and its allies imposed a set of adverse measures on Qatar—a so-called “blockade,” which included flight bans, expulsions of nationals, disruption of trade, and even threats to physically sever Qatar from the Arabian peninsula by digging an artificial canal on Saudi territory—Qatar was asked to comply with a series of thirteen demands, which included shutting down the Al Jazeera TV station and severing ties with Turkey and Iran.Footnote 8 Was this interference with Qatar's internal and external affairs “coercive”? Or, when the United States persists in its comprehensive embargo against Cuba, with the goal of changing the nature of Cuba's government and with enormous consequences for the Cuban people, is this El Bloqueo “coercive” in character?Footnote 9 And so forth.

In addressing such questions we are confronted with the undeniable fact that the consolidation of the modern prohibition of intervention in international law, precipitated by a series of resolutions in the UN General Assembly (UNGA), demonstrated substantial disagreement between states on the legitimacy of such measures.Footnote 10 Western states in particular have generally opposed UNGA resolutions promoted by developing states that expressly or implicitly asserted that economic pressure was an unlawful form of intervention.Footnote 11 The constant and consistent resort to such measures by a substantial number of states, accompanied by their opinio juris that such measures are lawful, would seem to negate any effort to render “unilateral coercive measures” (as the UNGA calls them) unlawful on the basis of custom.Footnote 12 Even so, it is questionable whether such a conclusion can be squared with any understanding of coercion based on first principles.

The prohibition of intervention has thus suffered from internal tension and uncertainty, as have its elements. In the past decade or so, however, state practice and opinio juris have been responding to a new challenge—the emergence and use of new technologies that enable states to affect each other remotely by cyber means. States have repeatedly affirmed in numerous fora that the “old” law of non-intervention has to apply to this new problem, in essence saying that some types of cyber operations can constitute (coercive) intervention.Footnote 13 In this particular cyber context, states have increasingly been coming out with formal statements—expressions of their opinio juris—interpreting the rule of non-intervention and its constituent elements and applying them to specific examples, such as interferences with elections.Footnote 14 They are partly doing so in response to influential academic initiatives to adapt the existing rules of international law to the new challenges posed by cyber, foremost among them the Tallinn Manual.Footnote 15 And in doing so, they contribute to the clarification of the rule not only in the cyber context, but also outside it. I should now acknowledge that my own interest in this subject was provoked precisely by this cyber dimension, especially due to my role as one of the editors of the third iteration of the Tallinn Manual, a work-in-progress at the time of writing. But I am firmly of the view that we cannot arrive at some kind of cyber-specific understanding of non-intervention. This rule cannot apply with clarity only in that particular context, if its foundations and application in other contexts remain unclear.

I will argue in this Article that the coercion element of the non-intervention rule can today be clarified and reconceptualized. My argument is partly normative and partly based on recent developments in state practice. I will explain that coercion can be understood through two different, if complementary, models or conceptions. First, the extortion model, under which the coercing state issues a demand to the victim state, and threatens or implements certain harms if that demand is not met. Coercion-as-extortion consists of imposing costs on the victim state, so as to cause it to change its decision-making calculus and policy choices. This is precisely how coercion has traditionally been understood in this context, as “dictatorial” intervention.Footnote 16 The key challenge here is whether the threat of adverse consequences below the force threshold, such as economic sanctions, can be covered by this model, and, in particular, whether coercion-as-extortion can include measures that are otherwise lawful.

The second (complementary) approach to coercion is the control model, which conceptualizes coercion as an action by the coercing state that removes the victim state's ability to exercise control over its policy choices. In this model coercion is not about affecting the victim state's decision-making calculus—the victim state's leadership may even be entirely unaware of the actions taken against it—but consists of a material constraint on its ability to pursue the choices that it wanted to pursue. Consider here, for example, a cyber operation against the elections in another country, which may be entirely unrelated to any demands or threats by the coercing state.

In Part II of this Article I will explain the structure of the non-intervention rule. Part III deals with what I will call the problem of justification. Part IV examines coercion-as-extortion, Part V coercion-as-control, while Part VI concludes.

II. The Structure of the Non-intervention Rule

A. The Prohibition of Intervention in Outline

The non-intervention rule that concerns us here is exclusively interstate in nature: it protects and binds only states.Footnote 17 Non-state entities have no duty to respect it, although states may be responsible for a breach of the duty of non-intervention if such an entity acts on their behalf, i.e., if the entity's conduct is attributable to a state.Footnote 18 Similarly, state measures of coercion against non-state entities such as armed groups, companies, or individuals are outside the scope of this rule, unless such measures are being used to indirectly coerce a state. I will also not be discussing here provisions in the founding instruments of certain international organizations, such as Article 2(7) of the UN Charter, that prohibit the organization in question from intervening in the internal affairs of its members.Footnote 19 Rather, I will be addressing solely the non-intervention principle as it applies between states.

The prohibition of intervention is a rule of customary international law.Footnote 20 It is not expressly stated in the UN Charter apart from Article 2(7), although it is enshrined in regional treaties, such as the Charter of the Organization of American States (OAS).Footnote 21 The codification of the modern non-intervention rule culminated in the 1970 Friendly Relations Declaration,Footnote 22 a UNGA resolution adopted by consensus, with the express purpose of restating international law rather than political commitments,Footnote 23 and supported even by those Western states that opposed other resolutions dealing with non-intervention.Footnote 24 The ICJ today appears to see the Declaration as wholly reflective of customary international law, and its Nicaragua holding clearly drew upon it.Footnote 25 Two key paragraphs of the Declaration formulate the non-intervention principle as follows:

No State or group of States has the right to intervene, directly or indirectly, for any reason whatever, in the internal or external affairs of any other State. Consequently, armed intervention and all other forms of interference or attempted threats against the personality of the State or against its political, economic and cultural elements, are in violation of international law.

No State may use or encourage the use of economic political or any other type of measures to coerce another State in order to obtain from it the subordination of the exercise of its sovereign rights and to secure from it advantages of any kind. Also, no State shall organize, assist, foment, finance, incite or tolerate subversive, terrorist or armed activities directed towards the violent overthrow of the regime of another State, or interfere in civil strife in another State.Footnote 26

B. The Relationship Between the Prohibition of Intervention and Other Rules

Before examining the constituent elements of the non-intervention rule in more detail, it is necessary to consider the relationship between this rule and its cognates, especially sovereignty and the prohibition on the use of force. That relationship depends on several factors: (1) doctrinally, on the point that the different rules have different elements; (2) normatively, on understanding the reasons that make intervention distinctively wrongful; and (3) on the varying levels of stigma that the international community attaches, or should attach, to violations of each rule.

In Nicaragua, the Court noted that there was substantial overlap between the prohibitions on the use of force and intervention, holding that coercion “is particularly obvious in the case of an intervention which uses force, either in the direct form of military action, or in the indirect form of support for subversive or terrorist armed activities within another State [. . . and that these] forms of action are therefore wrongful in the light of both the principle of non-use of force, and that of non-intervention.”Footnote 27 On the facts, the Court found that the U.S. supply of weapons and training to the contra rebels was a use of force against Nicaragua, but that “the mere supply of funds to the contras, while undoubtedly an act of intervention in the internal affairs of Nicaragua . . . does not in itself amount to a use of force.”Footnote 28 The Court subsequently concluded that “financial support, training, supply of weapons, intelligence and logistic support [by the United States to the contras], constitutes a clear breach of the principle of non-intervention.”Footnote 29

Thus, for the Court in Nicaragua, the provision of weapons and training by the United States to the contras was both a use of force and intervention, while the provision of other support was “only” intervention.Footnote 30 Later in the judgment the Court turned to the principle of respect for territorial sovereignty and found that its effects “inevitably overlap with those of the principles of the prohibition of the use of force and of non-intervention. Thus the assistance to the contras, as well as the direct attacks on Nicaraguan ports, oil installations, etc. . . . not only amount to an unlawful use of force, but also constitute infringements of the territorial sovereignty of Nicaragua, and incursions into its territorial and internal waters.”Footnote 31

The Court took a similar approach in its Congo v. Uganda judgment, in which it concluded that:

Uganda has violated the sovereignty and also the territorial integrity of the DRC. Uganda's actions equally constituted an interference in the internal affairs of the DRC and in the civil war there raging. The unlawful military intervention by Uganda was of such a magnitude and duration that the Court considers it to be a grave violation of the prohibition on the use of force expressed in Article 2, paragraph 4, of the Charter.Footnote 32

In sum, the Court's jurisprudence makes it clear that the same act can simultaneously violate more than one rule. It is also clear that not every act of intervention will rise to the level of a use of force.Footnote 33

There is an implicit gradation of stigma in the Court's approach—a violation of the prohibition of the use of force is in some sense more serious than a violation of the prohibition of intervention, which is in turn more serious than a violation of territorial sovereignty (as with, for example, the trespass of one state's police or armed forces on the territory of another).Footnote 34 That violations of the non-intervention rule sit on a midway point of a kind of hierarchy of gravity also seems in line with state positions.Footnote 35

The hierarchy of stigma notwithstanding, the overlap between force, intervention, and breach of sovereignty is substantial, but not total. While the prohibition of intervention undoubtedly derives from a wider, overarching principle of sovereigntyFootnote 36—that is, a state has a right to be free from outside intervention because it is sovereignFootnote 37—the purpose of the prohibition is to protect certain sovereign choices from outside coercion even below the force threshold, and even without infringing upon the victim state's territory.

I should acknowledge at this point that there is an ongoing controversy in the cyber context as to whether sovereignty can be violated by another state's cyber operation, which was the unanimous view of the Tallinn Manual 2.0 experts.Footnote 38 The contrary position is that sovereignty is merely a principle from which specific rules can stem, and that it cannot be violated as such by cyber means. Initially articulated by some U.S. government lawyers,Footnote 39 this position was subsequently formally adopted by the UK government.Footnote 40 The UK remains isolated on this point—the United States has not officially adopted this view, despite its origins—and, at least so far, all other states commenting on it have argued that sovereignty is a rule, rather than a mere principle. My own personal view aligns with that of the Tallinn Manual experts, but I will not explore this issue further here.Footnote 41 The key point for my present purposes is that, were the UK's position to be seen as correct, the absence of a lower-threshold sovereignty rule would entail that the non-intervention rule would correspondingly become more important in regulating state-to-state peacetime cyber operations. And that would, in turn, incentivize loosening the coercion threshold in order to at least to some extent fill the void left by the absence of a sovereignty rule.

Let us now turn to the constituent elements of prohibited intervention.

C. Interference with Internal and External Affairs (domaine réservé)

An act of intervention has to interfere with a state's internal or external affairs. Such affairs are frequently referred to in the literature as the state's domaine réservé (reserved domain), although the terminology varies somewhat, to my mind without material difference.Footnote 42 I will use the term “reserved domain” as shorthand for a state's internal and external affairs.

The reserved domain is the object of prohibited intervention, while coercion is its instrument or method.Footnote 43 The two elements are cumulative.Footnote 44 In Nicaragua, the ICJ defined the former as encompassing those “matters in which each State is permitted, by the principle of State sovereignty, to decide freely.”Footnote 45 The Court then gave two very broad examples of internal and external affairs respectively: “the choice of a political, economic, social and cultural system, and the formulation of foreign policy.”Footnote 46 The first example clearly drew on the text of the Friendly Relations Declaration, very much shaped by the need for managing coexistence between two ideologically opposed blocks in the Cold War.Footnote 47 In the cyber context, recent state statements have frequently focused on the conduct of elections as an example of internal affairs within the reserved domain, and on matters such as state recognition or membership in international organizations as examples of external affairs.Footnote 48

The Nicaragua Court's reference to permission by virtue of state sovereignty must mean that the reserved domain does not include those matters on which a state cannot decide freely because its choices are limited by international legal obligations.Footnote 49 It is not, to take the most obvious example, for a state to decide freely whether it should subject a portion of its population to genocide. The reserved domain therefore exists within the bounds of international law.Footnote 50 And as international law is ever growing, through the accretion of custom and the adoption and ratification of new treaties, the reserved domain tends to be shrinking.Footnote 51 Perhaps the most substantial development in that regard is the growth of international human rights law, which today imposes many limitations on what states can do to their own people.Footnote 52

That said, the concept of reserved domain should not be understood as referring to those matters in a state's internal or external affairs that are entirely unregulated by international law. Today there are hardly any such matters.Footnote 53 Rather, internal and external affairs belong to the reserved domain if a state has any measure of discretion within the bounds of international law regarding such issues.Footnote 54 And despite the substantive growth of international law over the past century, there is no doubt that the scope of the reserved domain remains quite broad.Footnote 55

To give a few examples of reserved domain, when Russia demanded that Ukraine abandon any ambitions to join NATO, this clearly interfered with Ukraine's external affairs, since it is the sovereign right of every state to choose its alliances.Footnote 56 (Whether this interference violated the prohibition of intervention depends, as in all of the examples I will give, on whether it was also coercive—my point here is that the first element of the non-intervention rule, an interference with a state's reserved domain, was satisfied). When in 2017 Saudi Arabia, the United Arab Emirates (UAE) and their partners required Qatar to comply with a list of thirteen demands or face the consequences of refusing to do so,Footnote 57 the majority of these demands clearly fell within Qatar's reserved domain. For example, Qatar was required to scale down diplomatic ties and cooperation with Iran, shut down a Turkish military base in Qatar and halt military cooperation with Turkey, and cease contact with the political opposition in Saudi Arabia, the UAE, Egypt, and Bahrain—demands that undoubtedly interfered with Qatar's external affairs. Similarly, Qatar was required to shut down Al Jazeera and various other media outlets it had supported, and to align its military, political, social, and economic policies with the other Gulf and Arab countries—again undoubtedly an interference with Qatar's internal affairs. On all these matters Qatar had the freedom, within the bounds of international law, to choose its own policies. Some of the demands, however, might not have interfered with Qatar's reserved domain, to the extent that they required Qatar to comply with its prior international legal obligations—for example, the demand that Qatar end its alleged interference in the internal affairs of other sovereign states, end its support for alleged terrorist organizations, or pay reparation for loss of life and other financial losses allegedly caused by Qatar's policies.Footnote 58

Similarly, when the United States imposed a comprehensive trade embargo on Cuba, which has now lasted for more than half a century, it has done so with the clear purpose of changing the nature of Cuba's regime.Footnote 59 While developments in international law with respect to the protection of democracy have to be acknowledged, the reserved domain still paradigmatically includes a state's choice of its political and social system, as proclaimed in the Friendly Relations Declaration and affirmed by the ICJ in Nicaragua. There can be no doubt, therefore, that, when taken as a whole, the U.S. embargo against Cuba interferes with Cuba's internal affairs.

When the Trump administration exerted pressure on countries all over the world, including many allies, to compel them not to install Huawei equipment into their 5G telecommunications infrastructure,Footnote 60 there is again no doubt that this interfered with the reserved domain of these states. The choice of using one vendor or another for infrastructure projects is a decision squarely within the internal affairs of each state, as such subject to no international legal obligation. Similarly, when, in response to the December 2018 arrest in Canada of Meng Wanzhou, a Huawei executive and daughter of the company's founder, pursuant to a U.S. request for her extradition on fraud charges, China arrested two Canadian citizens and exerted other forms of pressure on Canada to compel Meng's release,Footnote 61 it is clear that this was an interference with Canada's reserved domain, which in principle includes matters of criminal law and extradition on which every state retains a large measure of discretion.

In conclusion, the notion of reserved domain in the non-intervention context is fluid and relative,Footnote 62 but it does not pose too much difficulty. The only truly complex point is to what extent the reserved domain encompasses situations in which measures are used to enforce compliance with existing legal obligations, which I will return to below when discussing whether intervention can be justified. In all of the examples given above, there clearly was an interference with the target state's reserved domain. The much more difficult question for all of these examples is whether the interference was coercive in character, and it is to this question that I will now turn.

D. Coercion

There is no real definition of coercion for non-intervention purposes in any authoritative instrument. As the Dutch government put it somewhat euphemistically, the “precise definition of coercion, and thus of unauthorised intervention, has not yet fully crystallised in international law.”Footnote 63 In Nicaragua, despite holding that coercion constituted the “very essence” of prohibited intervention,Footnote 64 the Court said nothing about the meaning of this concept in the abstract. In both Nicaragua and Congo v. Uganda, the Court clearly held that coercion was a concept broader than force.Footnote 65 The only example of coercion below the force threshold given by the Court, however, is that of a state providing support such as money or intelligence to a rebel group on the territory of another state.Footnote 66 Yet, in response to Nicaragua's argument that various forms of economic pressure put upon it by the United States—including the suspension of financial aid, a reduction in the sugar quota, and a trade embargo—constituted coercion, the Court observed laconically that “it is unable to regard such action on the economic plane as is here complained of as a breach of the customary-law principle of non-intervention,”Footnote 67 without providing any reasoning for this position. In particular, the Court said nothing about whether and why such measures do not qualify as coercion, although its decision was most likely motivated by the evident disagreement among states on the issue of economic coercion, during the drafting process of the relevant UNGA resolutions and elsewhere.Footnote 68

We are therefore left with the following “easy” cases of coercion in the context of non-intervention: (1) acts involving the use of force contrary to Article 2(4) of the Charter, whether force is used directly by the intervening state or indirectly, through the supply of weapons or training to a rebel armed group; (2) threats of force, equally prohibited by Article 2(4), which are, as I will explain, especially pertinent to the extortion model of coercion; and (3) support for non-state armed groups operating on another state's territory below the force threshold, such as through the provision of funding or the sharing of intelligence. Another easy case relates to what coercion is not: (4) mere persuasion, i.e., an attempt by one state to convince another that a particular course of action is for some reason optimal, which does not involve any threat of harm by the former.Footnote 69 Simple diplomatic engagement with another state, even if it regards matters that clearly fall within that state's reserved domain, such as its choice of a political system or its choice as to what kind of 5 G infrastructure it wants to build, cannot be coercion.Footnote 70

Everything in between these two ends of the spectrum is, in some sense, a “hard” case. A minimalist positivist approach to such hard cases would be simply to deny their hardness, by arguing that coercion should not be understood as a general concept with any distinct content on the basis of some overarching principle, but rather as an enumerated list of actions that states have generally agreed count as coercion, most of which are already prohibited by Article 2(4) of the Charter. In that sense coercion, so it has been argued, would be confined to items (1)–(3) above, and nothing else.Footnote 71

An alternative view, which I very much favor, is that a commitment to positivism does not compel this kind of impoverished minimalism, which would reduce the notion of coercion to an enumerated list. If an action is coercive only if states specifically agree that this should be the case, then it becomes impossible to apply this notion to any new development, including cyber operations, absent new state agreement, i.e., some form of lawmaking via treaty or custom, which is highly unlikely to take place with any degree of promptness. To give an example, even though virtually all states that have recently published their formal positions on the application of the non-intervention principle to cyberspace have pointed to some types of election interference operations as a paradigmatic example of a violation of this principle,Footnote 72 the vast majority of states have still not expressed their views on any of these issues. The minimalist position also renders irrelevant the idea that intervention is a combination of two constitutive elements, because there is no need for having these elements if all instances of intervention anyway require specific agreement by states. Moreover, its reduction of coercion to force plus non-forcible support to rebels narrows the scope of prohibited intervention so much that it becomes underinclusive and redundant.Footnote 73

A minimalist approach to coercion also undermines the generality of legal rules, the notion that they can be applied to factual problems that the legislator did not specifically envisage or provide for. The generality of legal rules, often with a clear “core” of situations to which a rule applies and a much less certain “penumbra,” is perfectly normal both in domestic and international law. A (hypothetical) domestic rule prohibiting the use of vehicles in the park may be clear in most of its applications, but less clear in some—for example, as to whether it prohibits the display of a car mounted on a pedestal in the park, or the use within it of a bicycle or a newly developed (and newly insufferable) electric scooter.Footnote 74 But the fact that the rule is indeterminate in some instances does not affect its generality or binding nature. Similarly, in international law we do not in principle define legal concepts as exhaustive lists of universally agreed upon examples. We do not do this for instance, with the notion of prohibited force in Article 2(4) of the UN Charter, or with the notion of fair and equitable treatment due to foreign investors in bilateral investment treaties, or with the human rights to privacy or expression. These are all generic concepts accepted by states as such, even if they are open-textured, with disagreement on some of their specific applications.Footnote 75

In sum, a positivist conception of coercion need not be minimalist and confined only to those examples of prohibited intervention affirmed as such by the ICJ in Nicaragua. A positivist can argue, as I do, that the prohibition of intervention is a rule of customary international law, but that this rule and its elements such as coercion exist at a higher degree of abstraction or generality. That is, states concur that coercion is a required element of intervention,Footnote 76 see it as a generic concept, and agree that it is in principle broader than force, but might not see its boundaries identically.Footnote 77 There is nothing unusual in this. Some measure of indeterminacy is just fine, as is managing indeterminacy by utilizing arguments about policy, effectiveness, or justice.Footnote 78

How then should coercion be defined if not as an exhaustive list of universally accepted instances? We can briefly dispense with the dictionary definitions of coercion such as “the act or process of persuading someone forcefully to do something that they do not want to do,”Footnote 79 or as acting “to compel to an act or choice; to achieve by force or threat; to restrain or dominate by force.”Footnote 80 Linguistically coercion is clearly a cognate of force and is an act done with the purpose of changing the victim's behavior. But the meaning of words such as coercion and force in ordinary language is relevant for us only marginally, because of their distinct uses as terms of art in the very specific (and interstate) international legal context. That said, the ordinary meaning of the term still includes forms of compulsion other than force, and so we are essentially left in the same place as after reading the ICJ's judgment in Nicaragua.

For their part, the Tallinn Manual experts defined coercion as “not limited to physical force, but rather . . . an affirmative act designed to deprive another State of its freedom of choice, that is, to force that State to act in an involuntary manner or involuntarily refrain from acting in a particular way.”Footnote 81 In a similar vein, the Netherlands, one of the few states to have provided a more general definition of coercion,Footnote 82 has done so as “compelling a state to take a course of action (whether an act or an omission) that it would not otherwise voluntarily pursue,”Footnote 83 essentially a more succinct version of the Tallinn Manual definition.

These definitions point to the undermining of the victim state's will as the essence of coercion (“involuntary,” “voluntarily”), so as to effect a change in its behavior. This somewhat anthropomorphic approach corresponds to the extortion model of coercion, and is similar to how coercion is conceptualized in many domestic law contexts. But it arguably does not fully capture what coercion can mean in the non-intervention setting, and tells us nothing about what types of actions short of force can count as coercion.

The notion of coercion has given rise to much thinking in moral and legal philosophy.Footnote 84 Coercion also figures prominently in various domestic legal contexts, some of which I will explore further below. International law has a few direct analogues. For instance, in the law of treaties, coercion invalidates state consent to be bound by a treaty in two distinct scenarios. The first, per Article 51 of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (VCLT), is coercion of a state representative who had expressed consent on the state's behalf: “[t]he expression of a State's consent to be bound by a treaty which has been procured by the coercion of its representative through acts or threats directed against him shall be without any legal effect.” This form of coercion is directed against an individual and is clearly broader than the use of violence (“acts or threats” can include non-forcible compulsion).Footnote 85 The second, per Article 52 VCLT, is coercion of the state as such: “[a] treaty is void if its conclusion has been procured by the threat or use of force in violation of the principles of international law embodied in the Charter of the United Nations.” Here coercion is similar in nature to the one in the non-intervention context, i.e., it is the state as an abstract entity that is being coerced, but the scope of coercion is strictly limited to the use or threat of force contrary to Article 2(4) of the Charter.Footnote 86

Similarly, in the law of state responsibility, coercion can function as a rule for attributing derivative responsibility—if one state coerces another to commit an internationally wrongful act, the coercing state is responsible for that act.Footnote 87 The International Law Commission (ILC) defines coercion in this context narrowly, saying that “[n]othing less than conduct which forces the will of the coerced State will suffice, giving it no effective choice but to comply with the wishes of the coercing State.”Footnote 88 But even with this ostensibly narrow approach, the ILC does not confine its definition of coercion to unlawful force, arguing that the compulsion it had in mind can “involve intervention, i.e. coercive interference, in the affairs of another State”Footnote 89 and that “coercion could possibly take other forms, e.g. serious economic pressure, provided that it is such as to deprive the coerced State of any possibility of conforming with the obligation breached.”Footnote 90 Finally, coercion can amount to force majeure and constitute a circumstance precluding wrongfulness—that is, a state that is coerced by another into committing an internationally wrongful act may escape responsibility for committing that act, for which the coercing state would, however, remain responsible.Footnote 91

A common thread here is that threats or uses of force are paradigmatic examples of coercion. But coercion is not generally limited to force and can extend to other forms of compulsion. There is no intrinsic point at which non-forcible pressure amounts to coercion; rather, that threshold is variable and contextual.

How precisely coercion should be conceptualized for the purposes of the prohibition of intervention depends primarily on its distinct purpose in the international legal system. As noted above, the central argument of this Article is that, in the context of the non-intervention rule, coercion can be understood in two different but complementary ways. In coercion-as-extortion, the coercing state issues a demand to the victim state, and threatens or implements certain harms if that demand is not met. In the extortion model, coercion consists of imposing costs on the victim state so as to change its decision-making calculus and cause it to change its policy choices.Footnote 92 By contrast, coercion-as-control is an action by the coercing state that removes the victim state's ability to exercise control over its policy choices. In this model coercion is not about affecting the victim state's decision-making calculus but consists of a material denial of its ability to pursue the choices that it wanted to pursue. The two models will be addressed in greater detail in Parts IV and V below.

E. Mental Element(s): Intent of the Intervening State and Knowledge of the Victim State

While there is widespread agreement that an interference with internal or external affairs (reserved domain) and coercion are constitutive elements of the prohibition of intervention, there is more controversy as to whether the non-intervention rule requires subjective mental elements. There are two such possible elements, each of which are generally argued to exist (or not) by virtue of inherently being part of the notion of coercion. First, there is the question whether coercion, and thus intervention, can only exist if the intervening state intends to coerce the victim state, i.e., whether to be coercive the intervening state's relevant action has to be intentional in some sense of that word. Second, whether, in order to be coerced, the victim state must know of the coercive action of the intervening state.

That coercion must be intentional is often regarded as self-evident.Footnote 93 Arguments in favor of subjective elements tend to turn on the nature of the notion of coercion, on the alleged impossibility of coercing without intending to do so, or of being coerced without being aware of that fact.Footnote 94 Arguments against these elements claim that it is somehow inappropriate to use subjective elements in prescribing the rules of conduct for abstract legal entities such as states, or to assess their responsibility for breaching these rules.Footnote 95 They also point to practical difficulties in proving such mental elements, whether in or outside a courtroom.

As I will shortly explain, subjective elements will depend on the type of coercion we are discussing. But before doing so, it is important to note that there is no formal legal reason why the non-intervention rule could not incorporate mental elements. There is certainly no presumption in international law against such elements, nor is it true that they cannot be attributed to an abstract entity such as the state. It is perfectly common both in international and in municipal law for the responsibility of natural or legal entities to depend on subjective considerations of culpability (fault).Footnote 96 In some contexts, such as criminal law, such considerations take center-stage, and may be required by fair-labeling concerns and the moral condemnation implied in determining that a breach of the law has occurred. But considerations of fault are not limited to the criminal law context.

As far as the international law of state responsibility is concerned, if a primary rule of international law requires the existence of a mental element, this simply means that a natural person, a human being whose conduct is attributable to the state, has had the required level of fault. For example, for a state to be held responsible for committing genocide, one of its organs or agents had to possess the requisite genocidal intent.Footnote 97 The proof of such mental states of individuals—those who act on a state's behalf—is done routinely in judicial settings and outside them, employing multiple modes of evidence, including inference.Footnote 98 Specific rules of international law can, and frequently do, require states to act, through their organs or agents, with some level of fault, such as intent or knowledge. Whether they should do so depends on the specific context.Footnote 99

The real question, therefore, is whether the customary non-intervention rule requires some degree of fault. That question cannot be answered by relying on default assumptions or presumptions. Turning to the primary authorities on the rule, such as the Friendly Relations Declaration or the OAS Charter, we can establish that some of these texts do use language that implicitly refers to some form of intent. For example, the Declaration stipulates that “[n]o State may use or encourage the use of economic, political or any other type of measures to coerce another State in order to obtain from it the subordination of the exercise of its sovereign rights and to secure from it advantages of any kind.”Footnote 100 Similarly, the OAS Charter provides that: “[n]o State may use or encourage the use of coercive measures of an economic or political character in order to force the sovereign will of another State and obtain from it advantages of any kind.”Footnote 101

In Nicaragua, Nicaragua itself argued that the U.S. measures against it were done with two purposes—overthrowing the Nicaraguan government or alternatively coercing it into accepting American demands,Footnote 102 and that these two purposes were plainly evident from numerous official statements by high-ranking U.S. officials.Footnote 103 On this point the Court did not expressly say whether some form of intention was indispensable to the notion of coercion in the non-intervention context, but implicitly this appears to have been its position. Nevertheless, the Court's key holding was that it was unnecessary to prove that the United States specifically intended to overthrow the Nicaraguan government in order to find that it intervened against Nicaragua by supporting the contras. In other words, a coercive intent of the United States to compel Nicaragua to make or abstain from certain policy choices should not be equated with the specific intent of the contras to overthrow the Nicaraguan government.Footnote 104 The Court followed the same approach in Congo v. Uganda.Footnote 105

In the cyber context, the Tallinn Manual experts were somewhat divided on the question of intent, with the majority being of the view that coercion had to be intentional.Footnote 106 As for the recent formal positions of states on non-intervention in cyberspace, some have pronounced on this particular point directly. For example, according to the Dutch government, intervention is defined as “interference in the internal or external affairs of another state with a view to employing coercion against that state.”Footnote 107 Further, “[t]he goal of the intervention must be to effect change in the behaviour of the target state.”Footnote 108 For Finland, hostile interference by cyber means against a state can constitute coercion if “it is done with the purpose of compelling or coercing that State in relation to affairs regarding which it has free choice.”Footnote 109 According to New Zealand, coercion requires “an intention to deprive the target state of control over matters falling within the scope of its inherently sovereign functions . . . . While the coercive intention of the state actor is a critical element of the rule, intention may in some circumstances be inferred from the effects of cyber activity.”Footnote 110 For Canada, coercion includes cyber activities “designed to deprive the affected State of its freedom of choice.”Footnote 111 For Switzerland, coercion means that “a state seeks to cause another to act (or refrain from acting) in a way it would not otherwise.”Footnote 112 And according to Germany, “the acting State must intend to intervene in the internal affairs of the target State—otherwise the scope of the non-intervention principle would be unduly broad.”Footnote 113

Some states have used language that implicitly rather than explicitly evokes or requires intent, for instance when discussing specific examples of prohibited intervention.Footnote 114 But many states have stayed silent on whether the prohibition of intervention incorporates subjective elements of fault, even when they opined on other aspects of the rule. This is either because they did not consider the issue to be of sufficient importance, or (more likely) because they were unsure what the optimal position on this point should be and wanted to reserve their view for some later date. None of these states have addressed the question whether the victim state needs to know that it is being subjected to coercion, which had also divided the Tallinn Manual experts (the majority being of the view that there was no such requirement).Footnote 115

What, then, are we to make of these subjective elements? The first point to make is that, because they relate to the coercive action, these elements are part and parcel of the notion of coercion and do not exist independently of it. This means that the existence and nature of these elements will inevitably depend on the model of coercion being employed. Second, discussions of intent often lead to misunderstanding because that word can be used with different meanings, and because such discussions are often hampered by inconsistent terminology (e.g., intent, purpose, with a view, goal, etc.). Third, in that regard, both the proponents and opponents of an intent element do not actually disagree that the coercive action by the intervening state must be intentional under some minimal description.Footnote 116 There is no conceivable scenario in which a state wholly inadvertently coerces another. Rather, they disagree on whether a particular effect of the action (the description of which varies) must be intended for that action to be labeled as coercive. This will again, as I will explain shortly, depend on the model of coercion being used. Fourth, whether the coerced state needs to have knowledge of being coerced is an issue easier to settle than that of intent. I will develop this point below, when discussing the two models. Finally, the stakes of this debate are in fact lower than they first appear when it comes to coercion-as-extortion. As I will explain, under the extortion model of coercion (Part IV) the coercing state necessarily intends that its demand and threat cause a change in the behavior of the coerced state, while the coerced state is necessarily aware that it is being coerced. By contrast, under the control model (Part V) the coercing state issues no demand and no threat, and here the issue of intent matters much more than with coercion-as-extortion. If intent is required, it will be an intention of the coercing state to deprive the victim state of its ability to control its reserved domain.Footnote 117 However, the victim state need not, and often is not, aware that is being coerced in this sense of the word.

III. The Problem of Justification

A. The Problem Explained

This brings us to what I will call the problem of justification. Because of the structure of the non-intervention rule, the interpretation of its constituent elements will be influenced by views (or intuitions) as to whether intervention, or coercion, can ever be justified in some sense. Consider the example of state responses to Russia's aggression against Ukraine and its purported annexation of Ukrainian territory. At least some such responses harm Russia, and by inflicting harm attempt to influence Russia to modify its behavior or to become unable to further engage in it. And at least some such responses must be justified, even though Russia's will is unquestionably being bent through coercion-as-extortion.

This, then, is the central dilemma of the non-intervention rule. On the one hand, the core value that it protects is that states, by virtue of being sovereign (and additionally because of their people's right to self-determination), have a right to make their own decisions without external coercion. Put differently, the law must protect the autonomy of the (relatively) weak from domination by the (relatively) powerful. Similarly, the non-intervention rule must enable the co-existence of states with different ideologies and political systems, and reduce the risk that coercive measures might escalate to war.Footnote 118

On the other hand, it is not only that the reality of states constantly exerting pressure of all kinds on one another militates against a very broad understanding of prohibited intervention, in an obvious apology v. utopia dynamic.Footnote 119 It is also that pressure—or coercion—can be used for objectively good ends. The sovereign right of states to make their own decisions cannot be understood as the apex value of the international system. Sovereignty cannot override every other consideration, for example the human rights of the state's own population, which it may be grossly violating.Footnote 120

It is difficult for the non-intervention rule to navigate this tension because, as articulated in its authoritative sources, it is framed in categorical, absolute terms—“[n]o State or group of States has the right to intervene, directly or indirectly, for any reason whatever, in the internal or external affairs of any other State.”Footnote 121 As written, this rule admits of no exceptions. There is no in-built balancing test of justified coercive intervention, for example, one that would be necessary and proportionate to achieving some legitimate end. Thus, as Lori Fisler Damrosch has put it, at the core of the prohibition of intervention lies “an unresolved tension between the desire to find some sort of limiting principle and the reluctance to adopt one that might be too limiting.”Footnote 122 This is, again, especially the case with regard to coercive measures that are themselves otherwise lawful, such as the suspension of trade or financial aid, where the question is whether such measures should nonetheless become unlawful by falling within the scope of prohibited intervention, an issue I will explore in more detail below.

The categorical nature of the non-intervention rule means that considerations of justification are packed into arguments about its scope. In particular, states (and scholars) are incentivized to argue that particular actions, such as economic sanctions, are not coercive in character. This is not because they would regard such actions as falling outside some coherent and principled general concept of coercion, but because such actions are frequently used for good ends, while the rule apparently admits of no possibility of justified coercion.Footnote 123 The notion of coercion is thus unavoidably distorted. It becomes moralized, tied up with consideration of justifiability, from which it becomes impossible to untangle.Footnote 124

Instead of arguing about the scope of coercion, it is possible to rely on justificatory mechanisms external to the non-intervention rule, the general circumstances precluding wrongfulness recognized in the customary law of state responsibility. Through the operation of these circumstances an act of coercive intervention would not be regarded as unlawful. But these will be of very limited utility. Some, such as consent, cannot apply even conceivably—a state that validly consents to an act by another state by definition could not have been coerced into providing that consent.Footnote 125 Coercion and valid consent are mutually exclusive.Footnote 126 Other circumstances precluding wrongfulness, such as duress and necessity, are limited by strict criteria, and rightly so. Intervention could be considered as excused or justified under these criteria only very exceptionally.

B. Justification Through the Reserved Domain Element

A proper understanding of the reserved domain element of prohibited intervention provides a more coherent way of thinking about justified intervention than arguments about the scope of coercion or reliance on circumstances precluding wrongfulness. Recall how the reserved domain is a concept bounded by international law, encompassing those matters in the state's internal or external affairs over which it has a degree of discretion under international law;Footnote 127 or, in the words of the ICJ in Nicaragua, those “matters in which each State is permitted, by the principle of State sovereignty, to decide freely.”Footnote 128 This definition of reserved domain as bounded by international law logically entails that coercive acts with regard to a state's choices that fall outside the reserved domain cannot be intervention. In other words, even though the coercion element of prohibited intervention might be satisfied, the reserved domain element would not be. The coercive act in question therefore could not violate the customary prohibition of intervention, although it may well violate some other applicable rule of international law.Footnote 129

For instance, a cyber operation that prevented the armed forces of a state from spreading direct and public incitement to genocide over social media—say by shutting down the relevant accounts on that network, or by disrupting Internet access—would not violate the prohibition of intervention, since disseminating genocidal propaganda does not fall within the internal affairs of the target state over which it may decide freely.Footnote 130 The state does not have a free choice, within the bounds of international law, as to whether to commit or incite genocide against its own population. That choice is simply not part of the “internal affairs” the state is entitled to have control over; it retains no discretion over the matter. The cyber operation in question therefore cannot violate the prohibition of intervention, even if we qualified it as being coercive in character (here as coercion-as-control). But, depending on how the cyber operation was done, it might violate the target state's sovereignty or some other rule.

Similarly, if we were to accept arguendo that economic sanctions can constitute coercion for the purpose of the non-intervention rule, not every use of such sanctions would constitute intervention. This would only be the case if they were used to coerce a state regarding policies or choices that properly belong within its reserved domain. If, however, the sanctions were directed against policies or choices that fall outside the reserved domain, they would not violate the prohibition of intervention, again even if we regarded them as coercive.Footnote 131

This would of course only be the case if, on an objective inquiry, the particular policy regarding which a state was being coerced was not one on which international law left it with a measure of discretion.Footnote 132 This plainly may be a contested matter, especially in the absence of a binding judicial determination. Similarly, there may be rules of international law that compel a state to achieve a particular result, but leave it with a substantial degree of discretion on how that result is to be achieved. But if this understanding of the reserved domain element is correct—and I fail to see how the commission of internationally wrongful acts could reasonably be said to be within the scope of a state's internal or external affairs—then this element can have a more important role to play in accommodating justifiability considerations within the non-intervention rule than has been acknowledged so far. And it can do so without distorting the notion of coercion. Coercion would not be prohibited by the non-intervention rule so long as it was strictly confined to compelling the target state's compliance with its international legal obligations.Footnote 133 Again, the key point here is whether, as an objective matter, the target state retains a measure of discretion regarding particular policies or choices.

C. Enabling Unilateral Law Enforcement?

There are several possible objections to the understanding of the reserved domain element given above, all reflecting a concern that such an understanding would (arguably undesirably) enable unilateral coercive measures of law enforcement. First, even if coercive measures are intended to enforce compliance with an international legal obligation, there will be cases in which states disagree on the content of these obligations and such disagreement may be objectively reasonable. Second, it is unclear how coercive measures that do not constitute intervention because the reserved domain element is not met fit into the traditional dichotomy between retorsion and countermeasures (reprisals) in international law.Footnote 134 Third, under the conception of the reserved domain element proposed above, coercive measures would not constitute intervention even if they were grossly disproportionate to the ostensibly legitimate aim of enforcing legal obligations that is being pursued. Finally, and relatedly, this would in effect allow states using coercive measures to evade the customary requirements for lawful countermeasures in the law of state responsibility.

It is fair to say that the conception of the reserved domain element I have argued for does, to some extent, enable unilateralism, in the sense that the fact that particular measures are (1) unilateral and (2) coercive would not render them prohibited under the non-intervention rule, so long as they were being used to enforce compliance with international law.Footnote 135 But some degree of unilateralism and self-help is simply a fact of life in a non-hierarchical, decentralized system of international law, and each of the concerns outlined above has a satisfactory response.

First, it is undeniable that states may take different positions on points of law, or that there may be several plausible interpretations of an obligation incumbent upon a state, while an independent body making an objective determination of what the law requires might not always be available. This is also a fact of life in the international system, and this fact alone cannot be a reason for categorically preventing the use of coercive measures or confining them solely to cases of unambiguously clear violations of international law (which will even then likely be disputed by the offending state). Indeed, the exact same issue arises in the context of countermeasures, and in principle the same answer can be given—a state taking coercive measures to ensure that another state complies with its legal obligations does so at the risk of making the wrong assessment.Footnote 136 If the coercing state's understanding of the law ultimately proves incorrect, the reserved domain element would be engaged, and coercion would constitute prohibited intervention. The key point here is that the reserved domain element is engaged whenever the coerced state, as a matter of an objective inquiry, retains a measure of discretion on how to comply with a legal obligation.

Second, the retorsion-countermeasures dichotomy actually poses no issue for coercive measures intended to enforce compliance with prior obligations.Footnote 137 As I explained above, such measures simply do not constitute intervention (with a caveat further explored below), but that does not necessarily mean that they are lawful. They can still violate other rules of international law, such as sovereignty, the law of immunities, human rights, or trade law. If they do violate other rules of international law, such coercive measures would need to comply with the criteria for countermeasures in order to be lawful. If they do not violate any other rules of international law, they would constitute retorsion.

Put differently, if coercive measures are confined to enforcing compliance with prior obligations, the prohibition of intervention is not the benchmark against which the legality of these measures is to be assessed. For instance, coercive measures that cause grave harms to (say) the access to food or medicines by the population of the affected state may be wrongful not because they coerce that state on a matter on which it actually has no right to be free from coercion, but because they infringe on the human rights of its people, or unduly restrict international trade, or violate some other rule. Consider, for example, trade restrictions employed against Russia in order to make it desist from its aggression against Ukraine. Even if such measures crossed the threshold of coercion (and some of them likely do), they would still not constitute intervention into Russia's internal or external affairs. This is simply because Russia objectively has no right to use force against Ukraine and no discretion on the matter, despite its protestations to the contrary. If such measures contravened World Trade Organization (WTO) law or human rights law or some other body of international law, the criteria for countermeasures would need to be applied for any wrongfulness of such measures to be precluded. But, legal or illegal, coercive measures would still not constitute intervention into Russia's affairs on which it may decide freely.

Third, the issue of the proportionality of the harm inflicted by the coercing state on the coerced state for the purpose of ensuring the latter's compliance with the law only arises outside the confines of the non-intervention rule. That such measures do not constitute intervention says nothing about the permissibility of third-party or collective countermeasures, i.e., those employed by a non-injured state, which remains the subject of controversy.Footnote 138 I do not here take any position on this issue. I am solely arguing that such measures do not constitute intervention if the reserved domain element is not met. This does not mean that the criteria for lawful countermeasuresFootnote 139 are being evaded,Footnote 140 but that they only apply if a rule other than the prohibition of intervention is engaged.

The final question that arises is whether the wrongfulness of intervention can ever be precluded through the reliance on countermeasures, if both the reserved domain element as understood above and the coercion element are met. To my mind, this issue points to the centrality of intent as the link between coercion and reserved domain, between the threat and the demand.Footnote 141 As explained above and further explored below, in coercion-as-extortion the coercing state must intend to compel the victim state to comply with its demand. If that demand is compliance with a prior international legal obligation, and that obligation exists as a matter of an objective inquiry, the prohibition of intervention simply does not apply.

In coercion-as-control, however, the coercing state performs an action depriving the victim state of its ability to control its reserved domain, while intending to deprive it of such control. It is that act alone, without any threat or demand, that constitutes intervention. It is possible for such acts of intervention to be used as countermeasures, if they complied with the relevant conditions in the law of state responsibility. Consider a scenario in which State A intervenes in State B by funding a rebel group on B's territory. B responds symmetrically by funding a rebel group on A's territory (an act which, as we shall see, falls within the coercion-as-control model). B then informs A that it will stop the funding if A ceases its own wrongful act of continuing to support rebels on A's territory. To my mind, it is only in a scenario such as this one that intervention can genuinely constitute a countermeasure, so that its wrongfulness is precluded if the relevant criteria are met.Footnote 142 In this scenario, B's first-order intent is to deprive A of control over its reserved domain, by funding a rebel group (which would constitute coercion-as-control). It then has a further, second-order intent to use this wrongful act to induce compliance by A with its legal obligation (which would further constitute coercion-as-extortion).Footnote 143 But, unlike in the reserved domain scenarios above, B's own act of intervention has already been completed because the target state was intentionally deprived of its ability to control its reserved domain, and an illegality really is being used to respond to an illegality. This is again, to my mind, the only scenario in which countermeasures can be relied on to preclude the wrongfulness of intervention.

IV. The Extortion Model of Coercion

A. The Extortion Model in Outline

Let us now turn to the extortion model of coercion, which is in many ways paradigmatic of that notion. As we will see, the parameters of that model are broadly similar to how coercion is understood in ordinary language and domestic contexts, as well as in the philosophical literature.Footnote 144

In coercion-as-extortion, the coercing state performs at least two, and sometimes three, distinct actions.Footnote 145 First, it makes a demand of the victim state, and this demand relates to matters within the victim state's reserved domain, asking that state to engage or not engage in certain behavior. Second, it threatens the victim state with harm (e.g., force, economic sanctions, or cyber operations—the harm itself need not have any connection to the reserved domain, i.e., may deal with an entirely unrelated area) if the demand is not met.Footnote 146 It is precisely the threat of harm and its link with the demand that is the essence of coercion: “do what we say, or else.”Footnote 147 On its own a demand can never be coercive as such. Third, if the demand is not met, the coercing state may implement the threatened harm in order to induce the coerced state to comply.

For its part, the victim state can either accept or reject the demand. Its decision on this point can shift during the various stages of this demand-threat-harm process—it might accept the demand immediately after the threat is made, so that the harmful consequences are never implemented; it may reject it initially but accept it subsequently, because the harm inflicted upon it has become so great that it concedes in order for it to stop; or, it might never give in to the demand even if the threatened harmful consequences are implemented fully.

In the extortion model, coercion works by the threat or infliction of harm affecting the coerced state's decision-making calculus, that is whatever cost-benefit analysis its leadership might engage in when making their policy choices.Footnote 148 The victim state in effect still has a choice as to whether to comply with the demand or not, but that choice is heavily constrained by outside pressure.Footnote 149

The examples of the Cuban embargo by the United States, the Saudi-led blockade of Qatar, and Russia's invasion of Ukraine that we have looked at above can all illustrate the operation of the extortion model of coercion. In all of these cases, the coercing state made demands of the coerced state regarding matters in its reserved domain (e.g., changing the nature of the regime, demilitarization, “denazification,” implementation of specific policies), coupled with threats of harm. In all of these cases, the demand was rejected, and the harmful consequences were implemented fully. In none of these cases, however, was the implementation of these harms successful in producing the desired change in the target state's behavior. In the case of Qatar, the Saudi-led coalition eventually gave up on its demands, which Qatar successfully resisted, so that some semblance of normal relations was restored.Footnote 150 In the cases of Cuba and Ukraine, the coerced states continue to resist, while the coercing states continue, at the time of writing, to implement the harms. And with regard to both Cuba and Ukraine, the coercing states persist in their demands, while saying that the implemented harms would cease if the demands were met. For example, Russia has declared that it is willing to stop its “special military operation” if Ukraine agreed to demilitarize, “denazify,” and accept Russia's annexation of parts of its territory—as the Russian foreign minister put it, either Ukraine will give in to these demands or “the Russian army [will] solve the issue . . . . They may stop senseless resistance at any moment.”Footnote 151 Ukraine so far has no intention of doing so.

Bearing this in mind, we can distinguish between four different variants of the extortion model of coercion:

  1. (1) Failed coercion through threat alone. State A issues a demand and a threat to State B. B rejects the demand, but A never implements the threatened consequences.

  2. (2) Successful coercion through threat alone. State A issues a demand and a threat to State B. Fearing the harmful impact of the threatened consequences, B accepts A's demand before any harm is inflicted.

  3. (3) Successful coercion through the infliction of harm. State A issues a demand and a threat to State B. B rejects the demand, and A therefore implements the threatened consequences. Their impact is so severe that eventually B accepts A's demand. A then stops the harm it had implemented.

  4. (4) Failed coercion despite the infliction of harm. State A issues a demand and a threat to State B. B rejects the demand, and A therefore implements the threatened consequences. Regardless of their impact, B persists in its rejection of A's demand. A either continues or even escalates the harm it has been inflicting, or eventually gives up as it considers it to be futile.

The four scenarios of coercion-as-extortion above are valid regardless of how we set the threshold of coercion. That is, they can equally apply to threatened uses of force, economic embargoes or cyber operations. A key question that these scenarios pose is whether they would all constitute coercion even at the highest point of threatened or inflicted harm, i.e., force. This, in turn, depends on whether we think that scenarios in which threats alone are made should be treated differently from those in which the threatened consequences are implemented, and on whether we consider that scenarios in which the coercing state succeeds in getting what it wants should be treated differently from those in which it fails.

I would argue that the distinct wrong captured by the prohibition of intervention, and coercion as its constituent element, is in impermissibly affecting the free choices a state is meant to enjoy by virtue of its sovereignty and the right of its people to self-determination, i.e., in the “the subordination of the exercise of its sovereign rights.”Footnote 152 The essence of “dictatorial” intervention is precisely in the Diktat that infringes on the victim state's decisional autonomy.Footnote 153 On that logic, inflicting harms on a state to compel its compliance with an illegitimate demand is clearly worse than simply threatening it with such harms,Footnote 154 but the threat alone is bad enough.Footnote 155 Nor should, on that logic, the existence of intervention depend on whether it is successful in changing the behavior of the victim state.Footnote 156 For example, that Ukraine has against all odds managed to resist Russian aggression and demands does not mean that it has not been subjected to intervention. Or, the situation in which Qatar has used its wealth to build up resilience on various fronts, thus managing to resist Saudi demands against it, should not be treated any differently than one in which a weaker state would have found itself unable to resist such demands.Footnote 157 Requiring intervention to be successful in order for it to be wrongful would only serve to punish, without any reason of principle, those states that have somehow managed to resist coercion.Footnote 158 As the general counsel for the U.S. Department of Defense has rightly put it:

Requiring coercion to actually produce the desired effect could have paradoxical results. It may disadvantage States that are better able to deflect or endure coercive acts because their resilience would foreclose a determination of prohibited intervention. And it could reward States whose attempted intervention fails. It could also mean the same act, directed towards two different States, could be a prohibited intervention against one State but not the other, depending only on attributes of the target State, for example, whether a target State's cyber defenses were advanced enough to withstand the act. Such an outcome could impede the ability of States with more robust and resilient defenses to call out violations and, if desired and appropriate, to respond lawfully with countermeasures or other tools of international law.Footnote 159

I too fail to see how scenarios (1)–(4) above could plausibly be differentiated, precisely because doing so would penalize successful resistance against illegitimate threats.

A particularly instructive example of how states today see coercion through the extortion model is a legislative proposal pending before the institutions of the European Union on an EU anti-coercion legal instrument, crafted as a systemic response to arguably unjustified instances of economic coercion against the EU and its member states by powerful third states, such as the United States and China.Footnote 160 The proposal for a draft regulation originated with the European Commission,Footnote 161 and is as of the time of writing being considered by the European CouncilFootnote 162 and Parliament.Footnote 163 Among the envisaged responses to economic coercion is the taking of countermeasures by the EU or its member states, i.e., acts that would otherwise be in breach of their international obligations. But such measures can only be taken if the coercion against the EU or its members is itself wrongful. This is how the proposed regulation defines such instances:

Coercion is prohibited and therefore a wrongful act under international law when a country deploys measures such as trade or investment restrictions in order to obtain from another country an action or inaction which that country is not internationally obliged to perform and which falls within its sovereignty, when the coercion reaches a certain qualitative or quantitative threshold, depending on both the ends pursued and the means deployed. . . . Acts by third countries are understood under customary international law to include all forms of action or omission, including threats, that are attributable to a State under customary international law.Footnote 164

While the draft does not expressly invoke the prohibition of intervention, the definition it uses is precisely that of intervention and its two constituent elements—the wrongful act is a violation of the non-intervention rule.Footnote 165 Indeed some of the amendments proposed by committees of the European Parliament would include language specifically referring to non-intervention and the Friendly Relations Declaration.Footnote 166 Most importantly, coercion here is manifestly conceptualized as a form of extortion. Its definition also adopts the approach to the reserved domain element that I have argued for above, requiring that the object of coercion be to compel action or inaction that the victim state “is not internationally obliged to perform,” and also requiring the crossing of a somewhat vaguely defined threshold of harm.

B. Intent and Knowledge

Let us now return to the problem of the subjective elements of the non-intervention rule, which as I explained above depend on the model of coercion being employed.Footnote 167 As we have just seen, in the extortion model the coercing state performs at least two, and sometimes three, distinct actions: demand, threat, and harm. All of these actions must be intentional under one specific description: causing the victim state to comply with the demand, i.e., effecting some kind of desired change in its behavior in line with that demand. Indeed, it can be argued that it is precisely this coercive intent to inflict harm so as to compel compliance with a demand, namely the subordination of another state's will, that captures the distinctive wrongfulness of intervention.Footnote 168 The EU definition of coercion we have just looked at is precisely of this kind, and contains an element of intentionality (“in order to obtain”).

As a point of comparison, domestic criminal laws on extortion type of offenses invariably include some kind of intent element, implicitlyFootnote 169 or explicitly. For example, the Canadian Criminal Code punishes anyone who “without reasonable justification or excuse and with intent to obtain anything, by threats, accusations, menaces or violence induces or attempts to induce any person . . . to do anything or cause anything to be done.”Footnote 170 In the law of England and Wales, a person is guilty of blackmail “if, with a view to gain for himself or another or with intent to cause loss to another, he makes any unwarranted demand with menaces.”Footnote 171 In the U.S. Model Penal Code (and in the jurisdictions which have relied upon it), a “person is guilty of criminal coercion if, with purpose unlawfully to restrict another's freedom of action to his detriment, he threatens to [commit various proscribed actions].”Footnote 172 And in the Serbian Criminal Code both the offenses of extortion and blackmail require the offender to be acting with the “intent to acquire material gain for himself or another.”Footnote 173

Similarly, in the extortion model the coerced state will invariably know that it is being coerced, because coercion in this model works through the exertion of pressure on the victim state's decision-making calculus, so that the threatened or actual infliction of harms on the victim state would cause it to change its decisions.Footnote 174 Without knowing of the demand or of the threatened consequences, the victim state cannot decide to modify its behavior as a consequence of the coercion.

Proving intent and knowledge in coercion-as-extortion—even if such a requirement formally existed—would generally not be difficult. This is because the demand and the threat need to be communicated to be effective. When, for example, Saudi Arabia and its allies made their list of thirteen demands to Qatar and threatened adverse consequences in case of non-compliance, it is manifest that by doing so they intended to cause a change in Qatar's behavior and it is equally manifest that Qatar knew that. And when their demands were rejected, and Saudi Arabia and its allies implemented the threatened harms, there can again be no doubt that these harms were intended to induce a change in Qatar's behavior, i.e., to compel it to comply with the demands, and that Qatar knew this. Proving coercive intent and knowledge in this extortion context requires little effort. What else could all the relevant actions (demand, threat, harm) be if not intentional, and how could Qatar be coerced unknowingly?

It is true that in some cases the coercing state's threats might be veiled, in the sense that it wants to maintain some kind of plausible deniability and be able to argue that it never made a threat linked to its demands. For example, up until the very moment of Russia's full-scale invasion of Ukraine in February 2022, Russian officials denied that they were threatening Ukraine with war.Footnote 175 But the language they otherwise used could easily be understood by everyone as a threat of force, especially in the context of Russia amassing its military on Ukraine's borders. Once the invasion began, of course, any doubt about the nature of Russia's threats were dispelled. In short, while there might be some genuinely difficult cases in which it is unclear whether a state is making threats against another in order to induce it comply with its demands, the very nature of coercion-as-extortion means that proving the existence of such threats will generally be straightforward.Footnote 176

This brings us to the first liminal case in which the intent question does matter—let us call it the scenario of successful coercion by bluff. Here the coercing state makes its demand and makes its threat, but it has not yet followed through with the threatened harm. The victim state may nonetheless feel compelled by the threat to give in to the demand and does so. In such a situation it may be perfectly possible that the coercing state was in fact bluffing, i.e., that it never really intended to carry its threat out. Consider a counterfactual scenario—which many at the time thought reflected reality—of Russia amassing its armed forces on the Ukrainian border in late 2021 in order to compel Ukraine to comply with its demands on demilitarization and the like. Yet, in this counterfactual scenario, President Putin was bluffing and never intended to launch an invasion, but nonetheless succeeded in getting his demands fulfilled. At the time, Ukraine, for its part, might not have known, i.e., have been virtually certain,Footnote 177 whether Putin was bluffing, depending on the intelligence it had available.

Would we in this scenario regard Ukraine as being coerced into giving in to Russia's demands? The answer surely must be in the affirmative. Properly understood, the threat was intentional, even if it was a bluff. The intention that matters is to cause a change in the victim state's behavior, i.e., to compel it to do or not do something it would otherwise not have willingly done. And in this scenario, it is clear that Russia's demand and threat were intentional in that sense. Whether Russia further intended to carry out its threat is immaterial, because it is the threat alone that could plausibly cause a change in Ukraine's behavior by constraining its will in making its sovereign choices. We could not sensibly require a victim state in this position to positively know that the coercing state is not bluffing, so long as its belief that the threat was genuine was objectively reasonable. In other words, by making a threat, the coercing state can intend to cause a change in the behavior of the coerced state even without intending to carry out its threat in case of non-compliance. The extortion model of coercion requires only the former kind of intent, not the latter. And as I explained above, the extortion model should include scenarios in which the coercing state succeeds in obtaining what it wishes using threats alone.Footnote 178

C. The Threshold of Coercion

The key point of uncertainty with regard to the extortion model of coercion is the threshold of the harm that is threatened and possibly implemented by the coercing state. We have already seen above (Section II.D) how there are some easy cases of coercion and not-coercion. A situation in which the intervening state threatens or uses force or supports rebels clearly is coercion. A situation in which there is no threat of harm, but merely an effort of persuasion, cannot be coercion. All other types of threatened or implemented harms in between these two ends of the spectrum are in some sense a hard case, primarily because states have so far been unable to agree on any clear threshold of harm.

Would, for example, threatening or implementing trade restrictions or other economic sanctions cross the threshold of harm so as to constitute coercion? What about threats to suspend military or intelligence cooperation? What about threats to suspend visa-free travel for the other state's citizens or to withhold consent to the state's admission into an international organization? Consider, for example, how for many years Greece obstructed (North) Macedonia's efforts to join the European Union and NATO on account of its dispute about the latter's name,Footnote 179 or how Turkey has (as of the time of writing) conditioned Sweden joining NATO on compliance with various Turkish demands, including the extradition of a hundred or so supposed “terrorists.”Footnote 180 Is this coercion, or are these “hardball” tactics that should be considered legitimate in international negotiations?

Or consider cases of so-called “hostage diplomacy,” in which one state detains, prosecutes or otherwise ill-treats the citizens of another in order to induce the latter to comply with a demand. When, for example, China detained two Canadians on apparently trumped-up charges in order to induce Canada to release Huawei's Meng Wanzhou,Footnote 181 was this not only a violation of the human rights of the detained individuals, but also China coercing Canada, and thereby intervening in its internal or external affairs? When Iran detained two British-Iranians in order to compel the UK to pay its (undisputed) debt of 400 million pounds to Iran,Footnote 182 was this again not only a violation of these individuals’ rights, but also Iran exercising coercion against the UK?Footnote 183

The question before us, therefore, is whether there can be any threshold of threatened or inflicted harm that can properly be qualified as coercion that is not arbitrary and is not manifestly overinclusive or underinclusive. It should come as no surprise that there are many reasonably analogous questions in domestic law in which the same issue arises, and which are to some extent instructive for discussing coercion in the non-intervention rule. In particular, domestic legal systems not only punish extortion or racketeering-type offenses that involve threats or use of violence in order to obtain money or some other property, but also criminalize other types of coercion that do not involve violence.

For example, under the German Criminal Code the crime of coercion (Nötigung) covers anyone who “unlawfully, by force or threat of serious harm, compels a person to do, acquiesce to or refrain from an act.”Footnote 184 Such coercive acts are unlawful “if the use of force or the threat of harm is deemed reprehensible in respect of the desired objective.”Footnote 185 The notion of threats of serious harm is considerably wider than force and can include, for example, the unjustified filing of criminal complaints against an individual.Footnote 186 Similarly, in Swiss law the crime of coercion covers any person “who, by the use of force or the threat of serious detriment or other restriction of another's freedom to act compels another to carry out an act, to fail to carry out an act or to tolerate an act.”Footnote 187 This definition is again plainly broader than force. Similarly, the U.S. Model Penal Code's definition of criminal coercion covers threats to commit any criminal offense (i.e., not just a violent one), as well as threats to accuse anyone of a criminal offense, expose secrets, or take or fail to take official actions.Footnote 188 Again, the basic point that emerges here is that when domestic systems define extortion or coercion-type offenses they do not generally limit the threatened harm to violence alone, but do so more broadly, while engaging in some kind of line-drawing exercise.

A particularly instructive domestic example is the crime of blackmail. While the formulation of this offense of course varies comparatively,Footnote 189 its distinctive feature is generally that its component elements are not themselves criminal, or not even necessarily immoral. Consider, for instance, a scenario in which someone discovers that an acquaintance is engaging in adultery. Asking that acquaintance for money or some other favor would not in and of itself be either unlawful or immoral. Truthfully informing that person's spouse of the adultery would certainly be lawful and may even be virtuous. But combining these two acts—threatening the adulterer with exposure of his wrongdoing unless he paid a sum of money or complied with some other demand—would constitute a criminal offense in many legal systems and would generally be regarded as immoral. The same would apply, for instance, in a situation where one person threatened another to report her for committing a criminal offense (which did in fact happen), unless the latter paid money or complied with some other demand.Footnote 190 This supposed “paradox” of blackmail—that a combination of two legal acts can become unlawful—has been much discussed in the legal and philosophical literature.Footnote 191 The key takeaway for us here is that, as a legal matter, threatening to commit lawful acts while coupling that threat with a demand can in some circumstances be regarded as unlawful. In that sense, coercion for the purpose of the non-intervention rule can at least conceivably include threats of otherwise lawful actions, e.g., the suspension of some economic relations.

Domestic legal systems deal with many other relationships or transactions that involve a degree of coercion or some form of exploitation. Consider, for example, legal protections of employees from employers; protections of tenants from evictions or exorbitant rent raises by landlords; the rules of both public and private law that deal with the vitiation of consent in situations of particular vulnerability or economic disadvantage, for example in the context of usury, price gouging, form or adhesive contracts, and so forth.Footnote 192 In all such cases one party to a relationship or transaction exercises a form of pressure or influence against the other party that is not forcible in nature, but nonetheless genuinely constrains the other party's freedom to make their own decisions or results in substantial unfairness. Some of these cases involve constraint through threats—think, for example, of the situation of an indigent person whose power supplier threatens to cut off their electricity in winter due to unpaid bills, compelling them to choose between heating their home or feeding their family. Others cases may involve constraint through offers rather than threats—for example, a monopolistic large retailer who can simply dictate prices and other contractual terms to companies in their supply chain.Footnote 193

All such cases tend to involve difficult line-drawing exercises between forms of pressure that are considered impermissible, and forms of pressure in “hard” economic transactions that should not be regarded as unlawful, even though they might be unjust or immoral.Footnote 194 This is the case even with coercion or extortion-type criminal offenses. Consider, for example, the situation of a union leader who threatens their employer that their workers will go on strike unless their demands for better pay or conditions are not met. That threat, and any industrial action the workers might take, is coercive, but we would widely regard this form of coercion as justified (at least in principle). By contrast, if the union leader threatened the employer with industrial action while demanding money for his or her own personal gain, we would regard such demands and threats as impermissibly coercive, potentially even criminal.Footnote 195 Note, for instance, how Canadian law defines extortion as threats made “without reasonable justification or excuse,”Footnote 196 how the German definition of prohibited coercion explicitly incorporates a balancing test by providing that threatening harms is only unlawful if it “is deemed reprehensible in respect of the desired objective,”Footnote 197 how English law prohibits only (subjectively) unwarranted demands in blackmail,Footnote 198 or how the U.S. Model Penal Code expressly provided for an affirmative justification defense for any threatened harms that do not rise to the level of a criminal offense.Footnote 199

What can this detour into domestic law teach us about the extortion model of coercion in the international law prohibition of intervention? First, that while focusing on the threat or use of violence is perfectly sensible in understanding coercion, this notion simply cannot be reduced to force alone. If the interest we are protecting is the autonomy of individuals, or states, to make their own decisions, that autonomy can be infringed by multiple methods that can be as effective, and in some circumstances as condemnable, as force. Second, that all domestic systems engage in attempts at line-drawing between permissible and impermissible forms of pressure that suffer from some degree of arbitrariness and indeterminacy, just like in international law—but these are attempts we can learn from. Third, that in many domestic systems even threats of otherwise lawful harms can become unlawful coercion. Finally, that in many contexts the boundaries of impermissible coercion that are drawn by domestic law are shaped by what I termed the problem of justification, i.e., that some instances of coercion can be regarded as justified.Footnote 200

How, then, can we conceptualize the coercion-as-extortion threshold for the purpose of the non-intervention rule in international law? There are in my view three viable approaches in that regard, which can to some extent be complementary: (1) coercion as threat or use of force, or any other harm below the force threshold that states can specifically agree on; (2) coercion as the threat or infliction of harm that would breach the rights of the victim state or its nationals; (3) coercion as the threat of infliction of harm that is by its character, scale, and effects particularly serious or severe, even though it might not violate the rights of the victim state. Let us examine each in turn.

Force and minimalism. As we have already seen there is no dispute that the threat or use of unlawful force will meet the coercion threshold. The same goes for supporting rebel groups on another state's territory, or threatening to do so. A minimalist approach would include within the notion of coercion those actions on which states can specifically agree, but would exclude any actions on which there is substantial controversy, such as economic sanctions.Footnote 201 For example, because even the most systematic uses of economic sanctions, as with the American embargo against Cuba, have not generally been accepted as violating the prohibition of intervention, such sanctions should simply not be regarded as coercive in character.Footnote 202

I have already explained how that approach is underinclusive. As the general counsel for the U.S. Department of Defense has rightly put it:

Although some may assume that a coercive action must involve force—because, of course, force is inherently coercive—such an interpretation is unduly limited. The prohibition against intervention makes sense as a standalone rule under international law only if it is distinct from the prohibition on the use of force, which means coercion for purposes of prohibited intervention in the cyber domain must include at least some acts below the threshold of a use of force.Footnote 203

Violation of rights. The second approach would include within the notion of coercion not just the threat or use of force, but also the threat or commission of any internationally wrongful act by the coercing state against the victim state or one of its nationals.Footnote 204 Thus, for example, if State A threatened State B with cyber operations that would violate B's sovereignty, or went ahead with such operations (e.g., wiper malware attacks against banks and hospitals) if its demand was not met, the cyber operations in question would not only violate B's sovereignty, but would also constitute coercion and thus a breach of the prohibition of intervention. Or, if A engaged in “hostage diplomacy” against B, such an action would not only breach the rights of these individuals, but also B's right to be free of coercive intervention. Or, to turn to economic coercion, such threatened or implemented measures would constitute coercion for non-intervention purposes if they breached some prior obligation owed by A to B,Footnote 205 for instance under WTO law, international investment law or bilateral treaties of friendship and commerce,Footnote 206 or indeed if such measures violated the human rights of B's population, say because of their impact on the enjoyment of the right to food or the right to health.Footnote 207

The rationale behind this approach is that the line to be drawn between permissible and impermissible forms of pressure by one state on another should align with the rules of international law that already apply between the relevant states.Footnote 208 This approach is analogous to those philosophers of coercion who regards the essence of coercion as the violation of an individual's rights.Footnote 209

This conception of the coercion threshold would “upgrade” an act that is already unlawful by labeling it as intervention, due to the coercive purpose with which it is used. In addition to this elevated stigma, the practical added value of this approach is that it would render unlawful the mere threats of the relevant internationally wrongful acts when such threats are coupled with a demand and are made with a coercive purpose, even when such threats would not necessarily be unlawful under the specific substantive rules in question. For example, Article 2(4) of the UN Charter expressly prohibits both the use of force and the threats of force, but there is arguably no rule prohibiting states from threatening to breach another state's sovereignty or a rule of WTO law. If, however, such a threat is coupled with a demand in order to coerce the victim state regarding its internal or external affairs, the threat as such would become unlawful qua intervention. Put differently, if State A threatened State B with a cyber operation against its critical infrastructure that would breach its sovereignty, the threat alone would not as such constitute a breach of B's sovereignty unless it was acted upon. But if the threat was made to coerce B, A would be responsible for breaching the prohibition of intervention even if the cyber operation was not conducted and no breach of sovereignty occurred.

The upside of this approach is that it provides a reasonably clear baseline for the concept of coercion, one grounded not just in the prohibition on the use of force, but also in all other relevant rules of international law. Such coherence between the non-intervention rule and the related network of international rules would arguably enhance its legitimacy and compliance-pull.Footnote 210 The downside of this approach is that it is potentially underinclusive in that, with the exception of the threats point above, the non-intervention rule would only prohibit those acts that are already prohibited under some other rule of international law.

Severity of harm. A third approach would ground coercion not in the violation of the victim state's legal rights, but in the magnitude or severity of the harms the coercing state threatens it with or inflicts upon it. In other words, threatening or inflicting severe harms would be coercive if done for the purpose of compelling the victim state to comply with a demand, even if the harm in question would not be unlawful as such.Footnote 211

There is no conceptual problem with the prohibition of intervention sweeping more widely than other rules of international law, i.e., prohibiting behavior that is not already prohibited by some other rule.Footnote 212 As the ICJ has put it, “[t]here can be no doubt that, as a general rule, a particular act may be perfectly lawful under one body of legal rules and unlawful under another.”Footnote 213 We should recall in that regard that the definitions of extortion-type offenses in numerous domestic systems do precisely that. Blackmail is the paradigmatic example here—as explained above, it generally consists of threatening an individual with an otherwise lawful action of disclosing some information embarrassing to them, combined with an otherwise lawful request for money or some other benefit.Footnote 214 It is the coercive threat-demand combination, coupled with an improper purpose linking the two and its infringement upon individual autonomy, that justifies criminal punishment in such situations. Similarly, we have seen how various domestic systems define extortion offenses by reference to the severity or gravity of the harm threatened or inflicted, without necessarily requiring that this harm would be unlawful if taken in isolation.Footnote 215

Grounding the coercion threshold in the severity or magnitude of the threatened or inflicted harm makes normative sense because coercion-as-extortion works precisely on that basis. The threat or infliction of harm is the reason for the coerced state to act and make or change its decisions. The greater the harm, the greater the constraint, and the easier it is to demonstrate that the threat or infliction of the harm could or did cause a change in the behavior of the victim state. And we already employ similar tests, which are in principle workable in practice, in international law. Consider, for example, how the use of force and armed attack thresholds for the purpose of Articles 2(4) and 51 of the UN Charter are habitually defined by reference to their “scale and effects,”Footnote 216 or how the crime of aggression is defined in the Rome Statute by reference to the “character, gravity and scale” of the underlying act of aggression.Footnote 217 Similar approaches have been advocated for violations of sovereignty in the cyber context.Footnote 218

A severity assessment would necessarily be contextual. It would need to consider various factors, including the capabilities of both the coercing and victim states and any relationships of dependency or vulnerability.Footnote 219 A threat that is severe for San Marino might not be severe for the United States. That said, the fact that the victim state may be able to resist the harm and not give in to the intervening state's demands cannot ipso facto mean that the harm was not sufficiently severe. In other words, we should not confuse the severity of the harm with a requirement that the threat or imposition of the harm actually cause the victim state to change its behavior.Footnote 220 If we again take the example of the U.S. embargo against Cuba, there should be no doubt that it would meet any severity threshold (to the extent that economic measures can generally cross that threshold) even though Cuba has managed to resist it at great cost.

The main feature of this approach is that it does not require the underlying harm to be unlawful, so long as it is sufficiently severe. It could thus cover measures of economic coercion that are not contrary to say trade law or investment law, such as the suspension of financial aid in a situation of dependency, so long as their impacts were sufficiently severe. Crucially, in their official positions some states have already clearly relied on criteria such as scale or severity to define the coercion threshold.Footnote 221 And this makes sense—it is again the severity of the threatened or inflicted harm that, in the words of the German government, ensures that the victim state's “will is manifestly bent by the foreign State's conduct.”Footnote 222 Perhaps the most detailed articulation of such an approach so far is the proposed EU anti-coercion instrument, which regards as coercive those harms that cross “a certain qualitative or quantitative threshold [. . . ensuring] that only economic coercion with a sufficiently serious impact or, where the economic coercion consists in a threat, only a threat that is credible” is covered by the instrument.Footnote 223

But this approach may also be criticized for relying on vague notions of severity and for being overinclusive, unrealistically prohibiting a lot of “carrot-and-stick” diplomacy that states habitually engage in. One response to that criticism is that the severity threshold can be set relatively high to address overinclusiveness concerns, especially bearing in mind that the non-intervention rule allows for no exceptions. Similarly, that the vagueness of a severity criterion is indisputable does not mean that it is unmanageable—after all, international law already does this in many other contexts, and we have also seen how similar formulations are used domestically even for criminal offenses. That said, there will undoubtedly be some hard cases of applying this approach. Was, for example, Greece's use of unanimity requirements for joining organizations such the EU or NATO to compel Macedonia to change its name (clearly an issue within any state's reserved domain), severe enough in its impacts on Macedonia to count as coercion?Footnote 224

In sum, there are multiple possible approaches to calibrating the coercion-as-extortion threshold. At the barest minimum it includes the threat or use of force, but it can be extended without great difficulty to cover the threat or infliction of harms that are already internationally wrongful on some other basis. The real dilemma is whether coercion-as-extortion should also cover threats or infliction of lawful harms that are nonetheless severe in their potential or real impacts on the coerced state. In my view such severe harms should be covered by coercion-as-extortion, and thus constitute prohibited intervention, if they are designed to compel the coerced state to comply with a demand that infringes on its authority to determine its own internal or external affairs. As I already argued, however, if the reserved domain element is not met because coercion is used to compel a state to comply with its obligations under international law, there would be no prohibited intervention. This to my mind sufficiently addresses concerns that the non-intervention rule would become overinclusive.Footnote 225

V. The Control Model of Coercion

A. The Control Model in Outline

This brings us to the control model of coercion. Unlike coercion-as-extortion, coercion-as-control requires no demand or threat. Although the coercing state may still make threats and demands, coercion-as-control does not work by influencing the decision-making calculus of the coerced state. Rather, the coercing state directly interferes with the coerced state's internal or external affairs by taking an action that materially deprives the coerced state of its ability to control its policy choices within its reserved domain. A good starting point for thinking about coercion-as-control is the definition of intervention offered by the authors of Oppenheim: “the interference must be forcible or dictatorial, or otherwise coercive, in effect depriving the state intervened against of control over the matter in question. Interference pure and simple is not intervention.”Footnote 226 Incidentally it is precisely this definition of coercion that was recently adopted almost verbatim by the United Kingdom's attorney general.Footnote 227

We can again understand the essence of coercion-as-control by reference to domestic examples. Consider, for example, situations in which a state agent arrests or detains an individual, or searches their person or property, or seizes funds from their bank accounts, or blocks access to a website. In all of these situations the individual is, in some relevant sense, being subjected to coercion. The state agent might or might not make threats and demands, but the essence of coercion is not here in compelling the individual to comply with any demands under threat, but in performing an action against their will that is to the detriment of that individual and which deprives the individual of their ability to control their person, liberty, property, or some other interest. These are cases of coercion as much as those of coercion-as-extortion.Footnote 228

Or, to turn back to international law, consider the one example of cyber activities that all states (so far) seem to agree are coercive in character and constitute intervention—election interference operations.Footnote 229 There are many types of such operations, ranging from hacking a state's election commission, vote counting infrastructure or voting machines, to disseminating disinformation to target a particular candidate or suppress the vote of a certain category of people. I think it is fair to say that not all states would agree that every such operation constitutes coercion (and thus intervention), but they do seem to agree that some such operations do (and no state has expressed any dissent). At the most extreme end of the spectrum of such activities, a cyber operation that changed the voting tally in an election or referendum and changed the outcome of that process must constitute intervention.Footnote 230

The coerciveness of such operations cannot be explained by the coercion-as-extortion model. Election interference operations are not done pursuant to a demand coupled with a threat, in order to change the decision-making calculus of the coerced state. Rather, the coercing state through such an operation simply deprives the coerced state of control over its internal or external affairs, namely its political system.Footnote 231 In other words, accepting that such operations constitute intervention logically entails accepting the model of coercion as deprivation of the victim state's ability to control its own affairs.Footnote 232 And while thinking of coercion in terms of extortion comes naturally to us, this is not the only way of conceptualizing coercion—the two models are complementary, not mutually exclusive.

In short, coercion-as-control is essentially “a function of the coercer using power to determine what the target will or will not do.”Footnote 233 Coercion-as-control has not clearly been distinguished from coercion-as-extortion in state practice, jurisprudence, or scholarship. Nonetheless, I would argue that it has sufficient support.Footnote 234 First, recall how the Friendly Relations Declaration sets out a universally accepted example of coercion, supporting rebel groups on another state's territory: “no State shall organize, assist, foment, finance, incite or tolerate subversive, terrorist or armed activities directed towards the violent overthrow of the régime of another State, or interfere in civil strife in another State.”Footnote 235 In Nicaragua, the ICJ similarly treated the support of armed groups on another state's territory as a paradigmatic example of intervention.Footnote 236 Yet this type of coercion was not linked by the UNGA or the ICJ to any threats or demands by the coercing state. The mere fact of such support constitutes intervention, since it deprives the victim state of the ability to control its internal affairs and exercise its sovereign authority over its entire territory. This, in other words, is an example of coercion-as-control, not coercion-as-extortion.

Similarly, consider another widely accepted example of intervention—the premature recognition of a separatist entity as an independent state.Footnote 237 According to no less an authority than Hersch Lauterpacht, “[i]t is generally agreed that premature recognition is more than an unfriendly act; it is an act of intervention and an international delinquency.”Footnote 238 If State A recognizes a separatist entity in State B as an independent state when that entity does not meet the international legal criteria for statehood (which of course can be contested), the mere fact of such recognition is regarded as intervention in B's internal affairs, even if A made no demand of or threat to B. This means that the act of recognition as such is in some sense coercive, in that A deprived B of its ability to fully control its reserved domain by denying B's claim of authority over its entire territory.

A similar example is the unlawful exercise of enforcement jurisdiction on another state's territory, e.g., through searches or arrests without that state's consent, which is generally regarded as violating the territorial state's sovereigntyFootnote 239 and (at least in some cases) as violating the prohibition of intervention.Footnote 240 This can only be if by taking such acts the intervening state directly deprived the victim state of its ability to control its internal affairs.

Support for a coercion-as-control approach can also be found in some of the recent state statements on the application of the prohibition of intervention in cyberspace. For example, the United Kingdom's Attorney General not only adopted the Oppenheim definition of coercion, with its reference to deprivation of control, but also added that “we should be ready to consider whether disruptive cyber behaviours are coercive even where it might not be possible to point to a specific course of conduct which a State has been forced into or prevented from taking.”Footnote 241 And this does make sense—coercion-as-control is not about enforcing compliance with a specific demand as in coercion-as-extortion. Further, for Australia:

Coercive means are those that effectively deprive the State of the ability to control, decide upon or govern matters of an inherently sovereign nature. Accordingly, the use by a hostile State of cyber activities to manipulate the electoral system to alter the results of an election in another State, intervention in the fundamental operation of Parliament, or in the stability of States’ financial systems would constitute a violation of the principle of non-intervention.Footnote 242

Similarly, according to New Zealand, a cyber activity will violate the rule of non-intervention if it is “coercive (i.e., there is an intention to deprive the target state of control over matters falling within the scope of its inherently sovereign functions).”Footnote 243 For Canada, coercion comprises state “activities [that] would cause coercive effects that deprive, compel, or impose an outcome on the affected State on matters in which it has free choice.”Footnote 244 And these states and others have in their official pronouncements given examples of coercive activities that do not follow the demand-threat-harm structure of coercion-as-extortion, but can only be explained through a coercion-as-control model.Footnote 245

There is, in short, sufficient support for the proposition that the prohibition of intervention can be violated by certain types of actions that are not coupled with demands and threats. Such actions coerce the victim state directly, by materially depriving it of its ability to control its reserved domain. They do not coerce by exerting pressure on that state so as to change the decisions of its leaders. Coercion-as-control does not lie on the same spectrum as influence, and should carefully be distinguished from coercion-as-extortion. While they share the ultimate intention of the coercing state to produce a change in the behavior of the victim state, they operate differently.Footnote 246 For instance, in coercion-as-extortion the threatened or inflicted harm need not have any connection to the victim state's reserved domain as such. Rather, it is a means toward an end, which is compliance with a demand that does affect the victim state's reserved domain. It is not, for example, the economic measures that the United States has taken against Cuba that as such interfere with Cuba's reserved domain. Rather, such measures are used to compel compliance with U.S. demands about regime and societal change, which do interfere with Cuba's reserved domain. By contrast, in coercion-as-control it is precisely the action being taken by the coercing state, such as a cyber operation, that must, as such, affect the victim's reserved domain.

B. Intent and Knowledge

The question whether coercion must be intentional is of far greater import when it comes to coercion-as-control than regarding coercion-as-extortion. The same goes for any requirement of knowledge on the part of the victim state. As I have explained, in coercion-as-extortion the coercing state invariably intends its actions (demand-threat-harm) to produce a change in the behavior of the coerced state, while the latter will invariably know that it is being coerced.Footnote 247 Whether proving these subjective elements is legally required or not matters little, because proving them will generally be straightforward. But the same is not true of coercion-as-control; the scope of actions that the non-intervention rule would prohibit under this model will depend greatly on how any subjective elements are calibrated.

Consider the following scenarios. State A launches a cyber operation against State B to implant malware into its military command infrastructure. However, the malware also infects the servers of B's election commission and causes substantial disruption to an election taking place in B. In this scenario A did intend to launch the cyber operation in question; in that sense its action was intentional under some minimal description. But A did not act with the intention of disrupting B's election, even though its operation did have this effect. Did A coerce B, i.e., did A intervene in B's internal affairs by disrupting its elections, even though it did not intend to do so? Or, imagine if State A hacked the elections in State B and intended to do so, but the virus it used spreads uncontrollably and also disrupts the elections in State C. Did A coerce not only B, but also C?

On one view, as cogently expressed by the government of New Zealand, coercion requires intention, and with coercion-as-control this would be “an intention to deprive the target state of control over matters falling within the scope of its inherently sovereign functions.”Footnote 248 From a fair-labeling perspective, intention to deprive the victim state of control over its reserved domain would be crucial for delineating intervention from other possible violations of international law, for capturing what is distinctively wrongful about intervention.Footnote 249 This is not to say that coercion would require a particular motive, but that the specific consequence of the coercing state's action that would deprive the victim state of control over its reserved domain needs to be intended by the coercing state.Footnote 250

On the other view, intention to produce a specific effect should not be required for coercion, including coercion-as-control—the effect of depriving the victim state of its ability to control its internal or external should suffice. In the examples above, if State A caused injury to States B and C through its cyber operations (or whatever other activities), it would be normatively undesirable to argue that B and C have no entitlement to reparation from A for the injury caused just because the specific harms were not intended. Moreover, the practical difficulty of proving an intent to deprive the victim state of control over its reserved domain is greater here than with coercion-as-extortion, where inferences of intent are inescapable. While such inferences can reasonably be resorted to in many cases of coercion-as-control, and the difficulties of proving intent should not be exaggerated, they should also not be underestimated. An intent requirement allows the wrongdoing state a plausible way of escaping responsibility by arguing that whatever harm it caused was unintended.Footnote 251

As things stand, it is impossible to provide a definitive answer as to whether coercion-as-control always requires intent or not, pending further evolution in state practice and opinio juris. What can conclusively be said, however, is that without an intent requirement the non-intervention rule would be far broader in scope. Moreover, without such a requirement intervention could, at least in some circumstances, be easier to demonstrate than say violations of sovereignty, even though intervention is generally perceived to carry with it an elevated degree of stigma. Arguing for an intent requirement, as some states have explicitly done, would go a long way to mitigating concerns that the non-intervention rule would be overinclusive.Footnote 252 Consider, for example, a scenario in which State A emits pollution onto the territory of State B, causing B to take various mitigating measures to protect the environment and its population. In terms of the effect alone, one could reasonably say that A interfered with B's internal affairs, causing it to take actions that it would otherwise not have taken. But absent intent I would personally find it difficult to label such a scenario as coercion, even if there is a clear causal relationship between the actions of the two states.Footnote 253

In my view it can also be conclusively said that the subjective elements of coercion-as-control should not include a requirement that the victim state knows that it is being coerced. First, it is generally unusual, and normatively difficult to justify, to require subjective elements from the victim of a wrongdoing, when the wrongdoer is already acting with fault. Second, the intuition that the victim of coercion needs to know that they are being coerced stems from the extortion model, in which coercion works through the exertion of pressure on the victim's will through threatened or inflicted harm, of which the victim will invariably be aware. But that intuition is simply misleading when it comes to coercion-as-control.Footnote 254

Consider, again, the example of cyber operations interfering with elections infrastructure and machinery, on which so many states seem to agree as the paradigmatic example of coercive intervention. Such operations will generally work (at least to their fullest) only if the victim state is unaware that they are being conducted. Were a state to know that its voting or counting systems were compromised it would simply annul the elections and hold them again, or take some other remedial action. It makes no sense to regard the most successful (and therefore most harmful) such operations—those that go undetected—as failing to meet the requirements of intervention. Moreover, the victim state may become aware of such operations at a later date, rather than at the moment of their execution. It again makes no sense to argue that such operations were not intervention at the moment they were being conducted, but that they became intervention weeks, months or years after the fact, once the victim had become aware.

C. Threshold of Coercion

Calibrating the threshold of coercion-as-control is essential for preventing the overinclusiveness of the non-intervention rule. Requiring intention would to some extent mitigate such concerns. But the fact remains that if a control model of coercion is used, the prohibition of intervention can easily become very sweeping.

The first threshold issue is whether coercion-as-control should cover attempted or incomplete coercive acts. Recall that the answer to that question was positive for coercion-as-extortion—it would make little sense to say, for example, that the United States has not intervened against Cuba through economic means simply because Cuba has managed to resist U.S. pressure.Footnote 255 But coercion-as-control operates differently, and the same answer is not necessarily required. Consider, in that regard, the following scenario: State A launches a cyber operation against State B to interfere with B's elections. However, B's intelligence and cyber security agencies discover and neutralize this operation before it had any effects. In this scenario A did act, with the requisite degree of intention, using a tool that could have produced the intended result. But it was ultimately unsuccessful and B did not, in fact, lose its ability to control its reserved domain.

To my mind, coercion-as-control should cover such failed attempts.Footnote 256 Imagine if instead of the cyber scenario State A fomented a coup in State B, inciting and even paying B's high-ranking military officers to overthrow the civilian government—but the coup plot was ultimately exposed and failed. This scenario of the fomenting of a failed coup must be intervention; it simply makes no sense for A to escape liability simply because B managed to resist. The cyber scenario, and any other analogous attempt of coercion-as-control scenario, should therefore be treated in the same way.Footnote 257 That said, the total or partial failure of any coercive action would be taken into account in the duty of the responsible state to provide reparation, because it affects the nature and extent of the injury suffered.Footnote 258

When it comes to setting the threshold of a completed action that deprives the victim state of its ability to control its reserved domain, there are several possible approaches, with many of the same considerations at play as with coercion-as-extortion. First, actions that are characterized as uses of force would, in principle, be coercive, at least if carried out with the necessary intention. Second, instances of coercion-as-control could be determined on a case-by-case basis, if there is general agreement among states on the specific type of action in question (as with supporting rebels, fomenting coups, premature recognition, or arguably some forms of cyber election interference).Footnote 259 But such a casuistic approach is difficult to defend for the reasons I have already given. Third, actions intended to deprive the victim state of ability to control its reserved domain would be coercive if they violated some other rule of international law. But this approach would make it very difficult—and impossible if an intention requirement was rejected—to distinguish violations of the prohibition of intervention from violations of other rules,Footnote 260 even though intervention carries with it an elevated stigma.

Fifth, and finally, coercion-as-control could require a degree of severity in terms of the impacts of the action on the victim state and its ability to control its reserved domain. For example, a cyber operation that consists of hacking a single voting machine is clearly less severe than one that substantially altered voting tallies or suppressed turnout in key areas. To be clear, the wrong with such an operation is not in that somehow, after a successful plot, the leadership of the victim state will change and will make decisions that the intervening state prefers. The wrong is in interfering in the first place. But clearly some forms of interference are (for various reasons) regarded as worse or more severe than others. This is why it will be easier for states to agree that large-scale interference with election infrastructure is coercive, than for them to agree on the coerciveness of spreading disinformation, whose impacts are more difficult to determine. Similarly, it will be easier for states to agree that a coercion-as-control threshold has been crossed when a states uses cyber operations to disrupt the victim state's response to a pandemic (e.g., cripples testing or vaccine distribution databases and systems), than with regard to low-level infiltrations of the health system, even if they require some remedial action.Footnote 261 And it is again crucial to note that in their official positions, some states have already clearly relied on criteria such as scale or severity to define the coercion threshold.Footnote 262

Having said that, while a severity threshold for coercion-as-control is workable in principle, it inevitably leads to gray areas. For example, if we accept that if State A funded rebels on the territory of State B this action would be coercive in character, it is not immediately apparent whether A funding a political party,Footnote 263 a non-governmental or religious organization, or a media outlet in B would also be coercive,Footnote 264 or indeed whether the (lack of) coerciveness should depend on whether the funding is being provided overtly or covertly.Footnote 265 Or, consider the difficult case of the dissemination of disinformation intended to disrupt public confidence in the country's political system, which can undeniably be effective, but where the magnitude of that effect is difficult to measure reliably.Footnote 266 At least in principle, however, a disinformation campaign, cyber or otherwise, can severely impact on the victim state's ability to control its internal affairs, namely its political system.Footnote 267

Similarly, another difficult and particularly cogent case is that of economic measures such as export controls. Consider, for example, the various prohibitions that the United States has implemented on the export of newer microchips to China, with the express purpose of hampering China's ability to develop and produce such microchips. China has labeled these export controls as unlawful under applicable WTO rules—a point on which I express no view.Footnote 268 Assuming arguendo that the measures are not contrary to international trade law, would they nonetheless constitute coercion-as-control, and thus intervention, in China's internal affairs? Developing microchip production is arguably within a state's reserved domain, and the U.S. measures are certainly having a substantial impact on China's ability to develop such production. Is, therefore, this a case of intervention, or do such export controls fall below some minimum level of severity required for coercion-as-control?Footnote 269

In short, a severity approach to coercion-as-control can lead to substantially less certainty than the same approach to coercion-as-extortion. That said, it has been clear at least since Nicaragua that some actions can be coercive and thus constitute intervention even absent the demand-threat-harm dynamic of coercion-as-extortion. In my view, a control model of coercion best explains such cases. Determining the precise contours of that model will require more granular jurisprudence, state practice and opinio juris. Moreover, insisting on intentionality and severity as parts of the coercion-as-control threshold would assist in distinguishing intervention from violations of other rules of international law, and justify the elevated stigma that a breach of this prohibition carries.Footnote 270

VI. Conclusion

My argument in this Article is that coercion, as a constituent element of prohibited intervention, can be understood in two complementary but distinct ways: coercion-as-extortion and coercion-as-control. While similar in their essence and purpose, the two models of coercion operate differently. Conflating them can lead, and has led, to much confusion. Developments in state practice and opinio juris, especially in the cyber context, have enabled us to overcome that confusion. Yet I am not arguing that the two models of coercion are some kind of cyber lex specialis. They are equally valid in the cyber context and outside it, as part of a general rule of non-intervention. The two models I have proposed provide us with an approach that is internally coherent, even if liminal cases remain uncertain and the coercion threshold requires further clarification through state practice. It is fortuitous in that regard that, even outside the cyber context, states have been expressing their views on the lawfulness of coercion, with even Western states, which have traditionally opposed prohibiting economic coercion, now acknowledging that in some cases such measures may violate international law.Footnote 271

I have also argued that state views and scholarly positions on coercion have been shaped structurally by the problem of justification. While intuitively we regard some forms of coercion to be justified, the non-intervention rule is framed categorically, as admitting no exceptions. It has no inbuilt balancing test that could accommodate pressuring other states for good reasons. The prohibition of intervention is a rule that is, by its design, structurally apt at being either overinclusive or underinclusive, thus incentivizing arguments about its scope.

In particular, the tendency of states and some scholars to argue that some forms of state actions, such as economic pressure, are inherently not coercive, is directly shaped by their view that sometimes such measures can be used for good ends. But because they cannot argue that coercion is justified, they are compelled to argue that there is no coercion at all, especially when the measures concerned are otherwise lawful. This is in my view deeply problematic, and inevitably leads to a distorted, moralized understanding of what coercion is or is not.

A more promising approach to the issue of justification—perhaps an imperfect one, but still an improvement—is to argue that undoubtedly coercive measures directed to compelling compliance with existing legal obligations, regarding which the target state enjoys no measure of discretion, do not constitute intervention at all. This is because such measures do not interfere with the target state's internal or external affairs on matters on which international law gives it free choice.Footnote 272 Such coercion does not constitute intervention, although it may violate other rules of international law.Footnote 273 While this understanding of the reserved domain element enables unilateralism to some extent, it does not do so unduly. In these cases it is not for the prohibition of intervention, but for other rules of international law, such as sovereignty, human rights, or WTO law, to regulate any harmful effects of coercion.

I have also examined several possible approaches to the threshold question regarding both coercion-as-extortion and coercion-as-control. One alternative to underinclusive minimalism is to equate coercion with the violation (or threatened violation) of the rights of the target state and its nationals. This would cover cases such as economic measures taken in violation of international trade law or investment law, or those of “hostage diplomacy” that violate the human rights of the state's nationals. Or, we could conceptualize coercion as the threat or infliction of harms (in coercion-as-extortion), or the performance of certain actions that materially deprive the victim state of its ability to control its internal or external affairs (in coercion-as-control), that reach a certain level of severity in terms of their potential or actual impacts. There is much to commend in such an approach, but its inevitable consequence is a higher degree of indeterminacy.

One possible response to my overarching argument would be that coercion should not be regarded as a constituent element of prohibited intervention at all, partly because it may be impossible to come up with a principled approach to defining it.Footnote 274 Pragmatically that seems an unlikely direction of travel. States recently coming out with their formal positions on the application of the prohibition of intervention to cyberspace have all mentioned coercion as an essential element of intervention, often relying on the ICJ's Nicaragua judgment as an authoritative restatement of that principle.Footnote 275 Not a single state has argued in favor of abandoning the coercion requirement, even in some limited category of cases. Discarding coercion for some superior alternative (even if one existed) therefore does not seem feasible, although such an option may become more plausible if states start endorsing it.

As a matter of policy, I would suggest that, in expressing their opinio juris, states could usefully address three sets of issues in any future statements on the non-intervention rule. First, they should clearly distinguish between coercion-as-extortion and coercion-as-control, while affirming the validity and complementarity of the two models of coercion. Second, they should clarify their approach to the threshold of harm in either model. Third, they should also clarify the nature and role of intention in defining coercion. In that regard, while statements mentioning specific examples of prohibited intervention, such as different forms of election interference, are very useful, it would be even more useful for states to elaborate on why any particular examples are regarded as constituting coercion. I have explained what the plausible options on these issues questions are, but it is ultimately only states that can clarify the non-intervention rule further, and today there are ample opportunities to do so.

Footnotes

*

I am grateful to Dapo Akande, Shehzad Charania, Harriet Moynihan, Yuval Shany, Michael Schmitt, Liis Vihul, and Douglas Wilson, as well as the Journal's anonymous referees, for their very helpful comments.

References

1 See, e.g., Oppenheim's International Law – Vol. 1: Peace 429 (Sir Robert Jennings & Sir Arthur Watts eds., 9th ed. 2008) (“That intervention is, as a rule, forbidden by international law there is no doubt. Its prohibition is the corollary of every state's right to sovereignty, territorial integrity and political independence.”).

2 Military and Paramilitary Activities in and Against Nicaragua (Nicar. v. U.S.), Judgment, 1986 ICJ Rep. 14, para. 205 (June 27) [hereinafter Nicaragua]. The Court also noted that it was defining “only those aspects of the principle which appear to be relevant to the resolution of the dispute,” but that caveat really goes solely to whether its definition is a complete one (and it clearly is not).

3 See generally Jamnejad, Maziar & Wood, Michael, The Principle of Non-intervention, 22 Leiden J. Int'l L. 345 (2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. The non-intervention rule has roots going as far back as the XIX century; for an overview of its history, see Helal, Mohamed S., On Coercion in International Law, 52 N.Y.U. J. Int'l L. & Pol. 1, 4954 (2019)Google Scholar.

4 See DOD General Counsel Remarks at U.S. Cyber Command Legal Conference, Apr. 18, 2023, at https://www.defense.gov/News/Speeches/Speech/Article/3369461/dod-general-counsel-remarks-at-us-cyber-command-legal-conference (hereinafter 2023 U.S. DoD General Counsel Statement).

5 See also Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 348.

6 See, e.g., Russia Says Ukraine Talks Hit “Dead End,” Poland Warns of Risk of War, Euractiv (Jan. 14, 2022), at https://www.euractiv.com/section/global-europe/news/russia-says-ukraine-talks-hit-dead-end-poland-warns-of-risk-of-war (providing an account of the negotiations between Russia and Western allies, and quoting a Russian envoy as saying that, unless Moscow received a constructive response, “we will be forced to draw appropriate conclusions and take all necessary measures to ensure strategic balance and eliminate unacceptable threats to our national security. . . . Russia is a peace-loving country. But we do not need peace at any cost. The need to obtain these legally formalised security guarantees for us is unconditional.”).

7 See generally Damrosch, Lori Fisler, Politics Across Borders: Nonintervention and Nonforcible Influence Over Domestic Affairs, 83 AJIL 1 (1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Tzanakopoulos, Antonios, The Right to Be Free from Economic Coercion, 4 Cambridge J. Int'l Comp. L. 616 (2015)Google Scholar.

8 Patrick Wintour, Qatar Given 10 Days to Meet 13 Sweeping Demands by Saudi Arabia, Guardian (June 23, 2017), at https://www.theguardian.com/world/2017/jun/23/close-al-jazeera-saudi-arabia-issues-qatar-with-13-demands-to-end-blockade; Agence France-Presse, Saudi Arabia May Dig Canal to Turn Qatar into an Island, Guardian (Aug. 31, 2018), at https://www.theguardian.com/world/2018/sep/01/saudi-arabia-may-dig-canal-to-turn-qatar-into-an-island.

9 See generally Nigel D. White, The Cuban Embargo Under International Law: El Bloqueo (2015).

10 See generally Damrosch, supra note 7, at 8–10; Ori Pomson, The Prohibition on Intervention Under International Law and Cyber Operations, 99 Int'l L. Stud. 180, 185–200 (2022).

11 Helal, supra note 3, at 56–57.

12 For general discussions of UN General Assembly practice on unilateral coercive measures, see Barber, Rebecca, An Exploration of the General Assembly's Troubled Relationship with Unilateral Sanctions, 70 Int'l & Comp. L. Q. 343 (2021)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hofer, Alexandra, The Developed/Developing Divide on Unilateral Coercive Measures: Legitimate Enforcement or Illegitimate Intervention?, 16 Chinese J. Int'l L. 175 (2017)Google Scholar.

13 See, e.g., Report of the Group of Governmental Experts on Developments in the Field of Information and Telecommunications in the Context of International Security, paras. 19–20, UN Doc. A /68/98 (June 24, 2013); Report of the Group of Governmental Experts on Developments in the Field of Information and Telecommunications in the Context of International Security, para. 28(b), UN Doc. A/70/174 (July 22, 2015); Report of the Group of Governmental Experts on Advancing Responsible State Behaviour in Cyberspace in the Context of International Security, para. 71(c), UN Doc. A/76/135 (July 14, 2021).

14 See, e.g., Government of the Netherlands, Appendix: International Law in Cyberspace (July 2019), at https://www.government.nl/documents/parliamentary-documents/2019/09/26/letter-to-the-parliament-on-the-international-legal-order-in-cyberspace (official English translation) (hereinafter 2019 Netherlands Statement); Declaration of General Staff of the Armed Forces of the Islamic Republic of Iran Regarding International Law Applicable to the Cyberspace, Art. III (July 2020), at https://nournews.ir/En/News/53144/General-Staff-of-Iranian-Armed-Forces-Warns-of-Tough-Reaction-to-Any-Cyber-Threat (hereinafter 2020 Iran Statement); International Law and Cyberspace: Finland's National Positions, at 3–4 (2020), at https://um.fi/documents/35732/0/KyberkannatPDF_EN.pdf/12bbbbde-623b-9f86-b254-07d5af3c6d85?t=1603097522727 (hereinafter 2020 Finland Statement); Roy Schöndorf, Israel's Perspective on Key Legal and Practical Issues Concerning the Application of International Law to Cyber Operations, EJIL:Talk! (Dec. 9, 2020), at https://www.ejiltalk.org/israels-perspective-on-key-legal-and-practical-issues-concerning-the-application-of-international-law-to-cyber-operations (hereinafter 2020 Israel Statement); Italian Ministry for Foreign Affairs and International Cooperation, Italian Position Paper on “International Law and Cyberspace” (2021), at https://www.esteri.it/mae/resource/doc/2021/11/italian_position_paper_on_international_law_and_cyberspace.pdf (hereinafter 2021 Italy Statement); Annex B: Australia's Position on How International Law Applies to State Conduct in Cyberspace (2021), at https://www.internationalcybertech.gov.au/our-work/annexes/annex-b (hereinafter 2020 Australia Statement); Government of New Zealand, The Application of International Law to State Activity in Cyberspace (2020), at https://dpmc.govt.nz/sites/default/files/2020-12/The%20Application%20of%20International%20Law%20to%20State%20Activity%20in%20Cyberspace.pdf (hereinafter 2020 New Zealand Statement); The Republic of Poland's Position on the Application of International Law in Cyberspace (Dec. 29, 2022), at https://www.gov.pl/web/diplomacy/the-republic-of-polands-position-on-the-application-of-international-law-in-cyberspace (hereinafter 2022 Poland Statement); Government of Canada, International Law Applicable in Cyberspace (2022), at https://www.international.gc.ca/world-monde/issues_development-enjeux_developpement/peace_security-paix_securite/cyberspace_law-cyberespace_droit.aspx?lang=eng (hereinafter 2022 Canada Statement); UK Attorney General, International Law in Future Frontiers (2022), at https://www.gov.uk/government/speeches/international-law-in-future-frontiers (hereinafter 2022 UKAG Speech); Contribution of Brazil in UN Doc. A/76/136, at 18–19 (July 13, 2021) (hereinafter 2021 Brazil Statement); Contribution of Estonia in UN Doc. A/76/136, at 25 (hereinafter 2021 Estonian Statement); Contribution of Germany in UN Doc. A/76/136, at 34–35 (hereinafter 2021 Germany Statement); Contribution of Japan in UN Doc. A/76/136, at 46-47 (hereinafter 2021 Japan Statement); Contribution of Norway in UN Doc. A/76/136, at 68–69 (hereinafter 2021 Norway Statement); Contribution of Romania in UN Doc. A/76/136, at 76 (hereinafter 2021 Romania Statement); Contribution of Singapore in UN Doc. A/76/136, at 83 (hereinafter 2021 Singapore Statement); Contribution of Switzerland in UN Doc. A/76/136, at 87–88 (hereinafter 2021 Switzerland Statement); Contribution of the United Kingdom in UN Doc. A/76/136, at 116–17 (hereinafter 2021 UK Statement); Contribution of the United States in UN Doc. A/76/136, at 139–40 (hereinafter 2021 US Statement).

15 Tallinn Manual 2.0 on the International Law Applicable to Cyber Operations (Michael N. Schmitt gen. ed., 2017); see also Harriet Moynihan, The Application of International Law to State Cyberattacks: Sovereignty and Non-intervention (Chatham House Research Paper, 2019).

16 Jennings & Watts, supra note 1, at 434; see also Moynihan, supra note 15, para. 88.

17 See, e.g., 2019 Netherlands Statement, supra note 14, at 3 (“The non-intervention principle, like the sovereignty principle from which it stems, applies only between states.”). See also Sean Watts, Low-Intensity Cyber Operations and the Principle of Non-intervention, in Cyber War: Law and Ethics for Virtual Conflicts 253 (Jens David Ohlin, Kevin Govern & Claire Finkelstein eds., 2015).

18 Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 313–14; see also Moynihan, supra note 15, para. 79.

19 Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 362–64.

20 Jennings & Watts, supra note 1, at 429; Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 312.

21 Article 19 of the OAS Charter as currently in force provides that: “No State or group of States has the right to intervene, directly or indirectly, for any reason whatever, in the internal or external affairs of any other State. The foregoing principle prohibits not only armed force but also any other form of interference or attempted threat against the personality of the State or against its political, economic, and cultural elements.” Article 20 then further provides that: “No State may use or encourage the use of coercive measures of an economic or political character in order to force the sovereign will of another State and obtain from it advantages of any kind.” In the original 1948 version of the Charter (48 UNTS 1952, No. 1609) these were Articles 15 and 16.

22 GA Res. 2625 (XXV), Declaration on Principles of International Law Concerning Friendly Relations and Co-operation Among States in Accordance with the Charter of the United Nations (Oct. 24, 1970).

23 Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 353.

24 See generally Helen Keller, Friendly Relations Declaration (1970), in Max Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law, at https://opil.ouplaw.com/home/mpil. For an overview of UNGA normative action on non-intervention, see Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 349–55. See also Ossoff, William, Hacking the Domaine Réservé: The Rule of Non-intervention and Political Interference in Cyberspace, 62 Harv. Int'l L.J. 295, 298304 (2021)Google Scholar; Helal, supra note 3, at 58–59.

25 Accordance with International Law of the Unilateral Declaration of Independence in Respect of Kosovo, Advisory Opinion, 2010 ICJ Rep. 403, para. 80 (July 22).

26 See UN Doc. A/RES/2625(XXV), supra note 22, at 123.

27 See Nicaragua, supra note 2, para. 205.

28 See id., para. 228.

29 See id., para. 242.

30 See also id., para. 209.

31 See id., para. 251.

32 See Armed Activities on the Territory of the Congo (Dem. Rep. Congo v. Uganda), Judgment, 2005 ICJ Rep. 168, para. 165 (Dec. 19).

33 Jennings & Watts, supra note 1, at 429; Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 348–49; Watts, supra note 17, at 258–59; Gary P. Corn, Covert Deception, Strategic Fraud, and the Rule of Prohibited Intervention, at 6 (Hoover Institution Aegis Series Paper No. 2005, Sept. 18, 2020), at https://www.hoover.org/research/covert-deception-strategic-fraud-and-rule-prohibited-intervention.

34 See also Watts, supra note 17, at 249.

35 See, e.g., 2022 Poland Statement, supra note 14, at 4 (“The threshold for considering a specific operation in cyberspace to be in breach of the principle of non-intervention is higher than in the case of deeming it solely a violation of the principle of sovereignty.”); 2021 Switzerland Statement, supra note 14, at 87–88 (“An infringement of sovereignty and a prohibited intervention are not the same. The latter must be coercive in nature . . . . This means that the threshold for a breach of the non-intervention principle is significantly higher than that for a violation of state sovereignty.”); 2021 Japan Statement, supra note 14, at 46–47; 2021 Romania Statement, supra note 14, at 76; 2020 Finland Statement, supra note 14, at 3.

36 Jennings & Watts, supra note 1, at 428.

37 See also 2022 Poland Statement, supra note 14, at 4.

38 Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 17–27.

39 See more Schmitt, Michael N. & Vihul, Liis, Respect for Sovereignty in Cyberspace, 95 Tex. L. Rev. 1639 (2017)Google Scholar.

40 UK Attorney General, Cyber and International Law in the 21st Century (2018), at https://www.gov.uk/government/speeches/cyber-and-international-law-in-the-21st-century.

41 See more Moynihan, supra note 15; Kevin Jon Heller, In Defense of Pure Sovereignty in Cyberspace, 97 Int'l L. Stud. 1432 (2021)

42 See, e.g., Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 314–17; 2022 Poland Statement, supra note 14, at 4; 2020 New Zealand Statement, supra note 14, para. 9; 2021 Brazil Statement, supra note 14, at 19; 2021 Estonia Statement, supra note 14, at 25; 2021 Germany Statement, supra note 14, at 34; 2021 Norway Statement, supra note 14, at 67; 2021 Romania Statement, supra note 14, at 76; 2021 Switzerland Statement, supra note 14, at 87; 2022 Canada Statement, supra note 14, para. 22; 2021 Italy Statement, supra note 14, at 4–5. For an overview of the terminological issues, see Ossoff, supra note 24, at 305–08.

43 Helal, supra note 3, at 60–61.

44 Barber, supra note 12, at 351.

45 See Nicaragua, supra note 2, para. 205.

46 See id.

47 UN Doc. A/RES/2625(XXV), supra note 22, at 123.

48 See, e.g., 2019 Netherlands Statement, supra note 14, at 3; 2020 Finland Statement, supra note 14, at 3; 2020 Israel Statement, supra note 14; 2020 Iran Statement, supra note 14, Art. III.1; 2020 Australia Statement, supra note 14; 2020 New Zealand Statement, supra note 14, para. 10; 2021 Brazil Statement, supra note 14, at 19; 2022 Canada Statement, supra note 14, para. 24; 2021 Estonia Statement, supra note 14, at 25; 2021 Singapore Statement, supra note 14, at 83; 2022 Poland Statement, supra note 14, at 4; 2021 Germany Statement, supra note 14, at 34–35; 2021 Norway Statement, supra note 14, at 68; 2021 Romania Statement, supra note 14, at 76; 2021 UK Statement, supra note 14, at 116; 2021 U.S. Statement, supra note 14, at 140 (“A cyber operation by a State that interferes with another country's ability to hold an election or that manipulates another country's election results would be a clear violation of the rule of non-intervention.”); see also Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 313.

49 See also Watts, supra note 17, at 263–64; Helal, supra note 3, at 4.

50 Tzanakopoulos, supra note 7, at 623 (coercive intervention “is unlawful because it invades a state's ‘sphere of freedom.’ This sphere of freedom, in turn, is defined by the fact that the state has not assumed any international obligations relating to the matters within the sphere.”); see also Corn, supra note 33, at 9.

51 Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 316.

52 2023 U.S. DoD General Counsel Statement, supra note 4 (“States will want to bear in mind that the parameters of a State's domaine réservé will depend in part on its obligations to other States, which can develop over time. To give one example of particular importance in the cyber context, by becoming parties to the United Nations Charter, all States today have agreed that certain matters are unquestionably matters of international concern that may be regulated by international law, such as the prohibition on the use of force in Article 2(4). Articles 1(3), 55, and 56 of the Charter each commit U.N. Member States to respecting international human rights. This, in turn, has led to the development of human rights treaties. States that are parties to such treaties have consented to legally binding obligations aimed at protecting specific human rights, such as freedom of expression, freedom of association, and the freedom of religion or belief. Under this international human rights regime, excessive regulation of online content, including censorship and access restrictions, cannot be justified as a sovereign prerogative.”).

53 See also Ossoff, supra note 24, at 306–07.

54 Cf. Nationality Decrees Issued in Tunis and Morocco (French Zone) on November 8, 1921 (Gr. Brit. v. Fr.), Advisory Opinion, 1923 PCIJ (ser. B) No. 4, at 24 (Feb. 7) (“The question whether a certain matter is or is not solely within the jurisdiction of a State is an essentially relative question; it depends upon the development of international relations. Thus, in the present state of international law, questions of nationality are, in the opinion of the Court, in principle within this reserved domain. For the purpose of the present opinion, it is enough to observe that it may well happen that, in a matter which, like that of nationality, is not, in principle, regulated by international law, the right of a State to use its discretion is nevertheless restricted by obligations which it may have undertaken towards other States.”).

55 See also Moynihan, supra note 15, paras. 106–07 (with the broadly same argument in substance, although she prefers not using the reserved domain terminology); Corn, supra note 33, at 9.

56 Russia's demands were made both to Ukraine and to the United States and NATO members states, in different formats. See Andrew Roth, Russia Issues List of Demands It Says Must Be Met to Lower Tensions in Europe, Guardian (Dec. 17, 2021), at https://www.theguardian.com/world/2021/dec/17/russia-issues-list-demands-tensions-europe-ukraine-nato; Russian Deputy Foreign Minister Sergei Ryabkov: Russian Security Proposals Not an Ultimatum to the West But a Serious Warning, Interfax (Dec. 21, 2021), at https://interfax.com/newsroom/exclusive-interviews/73435/.

57 For the full list of demands, see Arab States Issue 13 Demands to End Qatar-Gulf Crisis, Al Jazeera (July 12, 2017), at https://www.aljazeera.com/news/2017/7/12/arab-states-issue-13-demands-to-end-qatar-gulf-crisis.

58 See more Alexandra Hofer & Luca Ferro, Sanctioning Qatar: Coercive Interference in the State's Domaine Réservé?, EJIL:Talk! (June 30, 2017), at https://www.ejiltalk.org/sanctioning-qatar-coercive-interference-in-the-states-domaine-reserve.

59 This purpose is in fact enshrined in U.S. law. Under the Cuban Democracy Act of 1992, 22 U.S.C. 69, § 6002 et seq., it should be the policy of the United States “to seek a peaceful transition to democracy and a resumption of economic growth in Cuba through the careful application of sanctions directed at the Castro government and support for the Cuban people . . . [and] to maintain sanctions on the Castro regime so long as it continues to refuse to move toward democratization and greater respect for human rights.”

60 See, e.g., Toby Helm, Pressure from Trump Led to 5G Ban, Britain Tells Huawei, Guardian (July 18, 2020), at https://www.theguardian.com/technology/2020/jul/18/pressure-from-trump-led-to-5g-ban-britain-tells-huawei; Alexander Smith, After Months of U.S. Pressure, U.K. Bans China's Huawei from Its 5G Network, NBC News (July 14, 2020), at https://www.nbcnews.com/news/world/after-months-u-s-pressure-u-k-bans-china-s-n1233752; Laurens Cerulus & Sarah Wheaton, How Washington Chased Huawei Out of Europe, Politico (Nov. 23, 2022), at https://www.politico.eu/article/us-china-huawei-europe-market.

61 See, e.g., Chris Buckley & Katie Benner, To Get Back Arrested Executive, China Uses a Hardball Tactic: Seizing Foreigners, N.Y. Times (Sept. 25, 2021), at https://www.nytimes.com/2021/09/25/world/asia/meng-wanzhou-china.html; James Palmer, Another Win for China's Hostage Diplomacy, For. Pol'y (Sept. 28, 2021), at https://foreignpolicy.com/2021/09/28/meng-wanzhou-michael-kovrig-spavor-release-china-canada-huawei.

62 Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 314; Helal, supra note 3, at 67–68.

63 See 2019 Netherlands Statement, supra note 14, at 3; see also 2022 Poland Statement, supra note 14, at 4.

64 See Nicaragua, supra note 2, para. 205.

65 Id., paras. 205–06; Congo v. Uganda, supra note 32, para. 164.

66 The provision of weapons and training to the rebels constituted both coercion and an indirect use of force. See Nicaragua, supra note 2, para. 228 and discussion in Section II.B above.

67 See id., para. 245.

68 See also Damrosch, supra note 7, at 34.

69 Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 374–75; Helal, supra note 3, at 72–74; Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 318–19.

70 Jennings & Watts, supra note 1, at 432 (“various forms of cooperation, making representations, or lodging a protest against an allegedly wrongful act . . . do not constitute intervention, because they are not forcible or dictatorial”); see also Helal, supra note 3, at 62–63.

71 See generally Pomson, supra note 10.

72 See note 48 supra.

73 See also Helal, supra note 3, at 75–76.

74 The “vehicle in the park” example was first used by H.L.A. Hart, as was the dichotomy between a more certain core and a less determinate penumbra of a rule. See generally H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 Harv. L. Rev. 593, 606–15 (1958), and Fuller's debate with Hart, largely on different lines of argument not relevant here, in Lon L. Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to LawA Reply to Professor Hart, 71 Harv. L. Rev. 630, 661–69 (1958). For a comprehensive treatment, see Frederick Schauer, A Critical Guide to Vehicles in the Park, 83 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1109 (2008).

75 I do not wish to be drawn here into the debate about the “interpretability” of custom (that is, whether customary rules are subjected to interpretative processes broadly similar to treaty rules), on which see generally Orfeas Chasapis Tassinis, Customary International Law: Interpretation from Beginning to End, 31 Eur. J. Int'l L. 235 (2020); Massimo Lando, Identification as the Process to Determine the Content of Customary International Law, 42 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 1040 (2022). Whatever the merits of that debate, there is simply no doubt that the content of some rules—whether based in treaty or custom—is of a general character and cannot be reduced to an enumerated list of specific applications. For example, if the human rights to privacy or freedom of expression exist in custom (as they do), applying them to novel contexts, such as cyberspace, does not require a new inquiry into state practice and opinio juris. Similarly, we can apply the customary principles of distinction or proportionality of the law of armed conflict to novel weapons, and do not need a weapon-specific inquiry into custom whenever a new weapon is developed. There is in principle no difference in such cases between applying the customary or the treaty versions of the rule, i.e., the rule is general in character regardless of its source.

76 See, e.g., 2021 Singapore Statement, supra note 14, at 83 (“intervention necessarily involves an element of coercion”).

77 See, e.g., 2022 Poland Statement, supra note 14, at 4 (“There is no universally acceptable definition of “coercion,” but an unambiguous example of a prohibited intervention is the use of force.”); 2020 Australia Statement, supra note 14 (“Harmful conduct in cyberspace that does not constitute a use of force may still constitute a breach of the duty not to intervene in the internal or external affairs of another State.”).

78 See also Schauer, supra note 74, at 1125–26.

79 See Coercion, Collins Dictionary, at https://www.collinsdictionary.com/dictionary/english/coercion.

80 See Coercing, Merriam-Webster Dictionary, at https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/coercing.

81 See Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 317.

82 For very similarly worded abstract definitions, see also 2021 Estonia Statement, supra note 14, at 25; 2021 Norway Statement, supra note 14, at 68.

83 See 2019 Netherlands Statement, supra note 14, at 3.

84 See generally Scott Anderson, Coercion, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman eds., 2023), at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2023/entries/coercion.

85 For example, the ILC commentary to Article 48 of its Draft Articles on the Law of Treaties (DALT), Y.B. Int'l L. Comm'n, Vol. II, at 246 (1966), which was almost verbatim reproduced as Article 51 VCLT, provides that this notion of coercion is “intended to cover any form of constraint of or threat against a representative affecting him as an individual and not as an organ of his State. It would therefore include not only a threat to his person, but a threat to ruin his career by exposing a private indiscretion, as also a threat to injure a member of the representative's family with a view to coercing the representative” (emphasis added). See also Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties: A Commentary 862–63 (Oliver Dörr & Kirsten Schmalenbach eds., 2012).

86 During its work on the DALT, the ILC expressly decided to limit the notion of coercion to use or threat of force and to exclude lesser forms of compulsion, even though some members of the Commission argued for a lower threshold. See Commentary to Article 49 DALT, supra note 85, at 246 (“Some members of the Commission expressed the view that any other forms of pressure, such as a threat to strangle the economy of a country, ought to be stated in the article as falling within the concept of coercion.”). The reason given for the majority of the Commission rejecting this position and limiting coercion to force was to avoid having a looser rule that could be more open to the possibility of illegitimate attempts to evade treaty obligations. The same issue arose at the Vienna diplomatic conference, but a proposal to expand the notion of coercion in VCLT Article 52 beyond that of force was ultimately not successful. Dörr & Schmalenbach, supra note 85, at 882–86.

87 International Law Commission, Draft Articles on Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts with Commentaries, Art. 18, 56 UN GAOR Supp. No. 10, Art. 2, UN Doc. A/56/10 (2001), reprinted in 2 Y.B. Int'l L. Comm'n 26 (2001), UN Doc. A/CN.4/SER.A/ 2001/Add.1 (Part 2) [hereinafter ILC ASR].

88 See id., Commentary to Art. 18, para. 2.

89 See id., para. 3.

90 See id.

91 Id., Commentary to Art. 23, para. 3.

92 See, e.g., Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 317–18 (discussing cyber examples of intervention, all of which fall under my rubric of coercion-as-extortion).

93 See, e.g., Jennings & Watts, supra note 1, at 430 (“intervention is forcible or dictatorial interference by a state in the affairs of another state, calculated to impose certain conduct or consequences on that other state” (emphasis added)); Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 348 (intervention covers only those acts “that are intended to force a policy change in the target state” (emphasis added)). For various possible descriptions of the intent required, see Moynihan, supra note 15, paras. 90–93.

94 See, e.g., Moynihan, supra note 15, para. 100.

95 See, e.g., Watts, supra note 17, at 268–69.

96 For a more extended discussion, see Milanovic, Marko, Intelligence Sharing in Multinational Military Operations and Complicity Under International Law, 97 Int'l L. Stud. 1269, 1281–84 (2021)Google Scholar.

97 See Application of the Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide (Bosn. & Herz. v. Serb. & Montenegro), Judgment, 2007 ICJ Rep. 43, paras. 242, 296, 373, 376, 413 (Feb. 26) [hereinafter Bosnian Genocide].

98 Milanovic, supra note 96, at 1282–83.

99 ILC ASR, supra note 87, Art. 2 Cmt. para. 3.

100 See UN Doc. A/RES/2625(XXV), supra note 22, at 123.

101 See OAS Charter, Art. 20.

102 Nicaragua, supra note 2, para. 239.

103 Id., para. 240.

104 Id., para. 241.

105 Congo v. Uganda, supra note 32, para. 163.

106 Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 318. Even so all of the experts had previously agreed on a definition of coercion that clearly refers to some level of intent (“an affirmative act designed to deprive another State of its freedom of choice,” id. at 317). There is some uncertainty as to where exactly the disagreement between the majority and the minority of experts actually lied.

107 See 2019 Netherlands Statement, supra note 14, at 3 (emphasis added).

108 See id.; see also 2021 Romania Statement, supra note 14, at 76 (nearly identical formulation).

109 See 2020 Finland Statement, at supra note 14, at 3.

110 See 2020 New Zealand Statement, supra note 14, para. 9.

111 See 2022 Canada Statement, supra note 14, para. 23.

112 See 2021 Switzerland Statement, supra note 14, at 87–88.

113 See 2021 Germany Statement, supra note 14, at 34.

114 See, e.g., 2021 Norway Statement, supra note 14, at 68 (non-intervention rule breached by “carrying out cyber operations with the intent of altering election results in another State” or by “deliberately causing a temporary shutdown of the target State's critical infrastructure”); 2021 Singapore Statement, supra note 14, at 83 (discussing cyber attacks conducted “in an attempt to coerce our government” (emphasis added)).

115 Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 320–21.

116 All actions (as opposed to involuntary movements) of the individuals through whom a state acts are by definition intentional under some description, that is the words we use to describe the action will incorporate some element of intent. For classical philosophical accounts, see G.E.M. Anscombe, Intention (1957), R.A. Duff, Intentions Legal and Philosophical, 9 Oxford J. Leg. Stud. 76 (1989). For a discussion of intention in the state responsibility context, see Milanovic, supra note 96, at 1284–86.

117 See also 2020 New Zealand Statement, supra note 14, para. 9.

118 See also Jennings & Watts, supra note 1, at 430.

119 See generally Martti Koskenniemi, From Apology to Utopia: The Structure of International Legal Argument (2006).

120 See Damrosch, supra note 7, at 34–37.

121 See UN Doc. A/RES/2625(XXV), supra note 22, at 123.

122 See Damrosch, supra note 7, at 10 (emphasis in original).

123 Cf. Tom J. Farer, Political and Economic Coercion in Contemporary International Law, 79 AJIL 405, 406 (1985) (arguing that “every human relationship is some mixture of coercion and cooperation. So to say that a particular relationship is coercive is to say nothing at all about its legitimacy.”).

124 See also Anderson, supra note 84, at 3.1 (cautioning against moralized approaches to defining coercion, which presuppose that coercion is not justified).

125 See also Jennings & Watts, supra note 1, at 435–37.

126 Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 378–79.

127 Section II.C supra.

128 See Nicaragua, supra note 2, para. 205.

129 See also Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 317 (“certain cyber operations intended to compel another State into compliance with its international legal obligations are excluded from the scope of applicability [of the non-intervention rule . . .] because the fact that one State owes an obligation to another State takes the matter out of the realm of domaine réservé”); 2020 Finland Statement, supra note 14, at 3 (distinguishing prohibited intervention from measures “the purpose of which is to compel another State to comply with its international obligations”).

130 See, e.g., Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide, Art. III(c), Dec. 9, 1948, 78 UNTS 277.

131 See also Marcelo Kohen, The Principle of Non-intervention 25 Years After the Nicaragua Judgment, 25 Leiden J. Int'l L. 157, 160–61 (2012) (arguing that requirements imposed on a state to comply with its international obligations do not constitute intervention); Barber, supra note 12, at 352 (arguing that “if measures imposed by one State on another are aimed at ensuring respect for human rights that fall within this established ‘core,’ or for the prohibition of war crimes and crimes against humanity, those measures ought not be regarded as an intervention in matters on which the targeted State may decide freely”).

132 This argument is not about creating something like a human rights exception to the prohibition of intervention. See, e.g., Institute of International Law, Resolution on the Protection of Human Rights and the Principle of Non-intervention in the Internal Affairs of States (1989) (arguing that measures taken against a state that violated human rights were not an interference in its internal affairs); see also Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 376–77. My argument extends to coercive actions done to compel compliance with any relevant rule of international law, which again may be unlawful on some other basis, but do not violate the prohibition of intervention.

133 For a similar argument, see Damrosch, supra note 7, at 38–40.

134 While retorsion is generally regarded as the use of unfriendly measures that are not unlawful, countermeasures are defined as acts in breach of one state's international obligations toward another taken in order to induce the latter state to comply with its own international obligations, including the duty to cease an ongoing internationally wrongful act and to provide reparation for it. ILC ASR, supra note 87, Art. 49.

135 See also Dapo Akande, Payam Akhavan & Eirik Bjorge, Economic Sanctions, International Law, and Crimes Against Humanity: Venezuela's ICC Referral, 115 AJIL 493, 496–98 (2021); Sarah H. Cleveland, Norm Internalization and U.S. Economic Sanctions, 26 Yale J. Int'l L. 1, 52–55 (2001). On UNGA resolutions on unilateral coercive measures, see Barber, supra note 12; and Hofer, supra note 12.

136 ILC ASR, supra note 87, Art. 49 cmt. para. 3 (“A State taking countermeasures acts at its peril, if its view of the question of wrongfulness turns out not to be well founded. A State which resorts to countermeasures based on its unilateral assessment of the situation does so at its own risk and may incur responsibility for its own wrongful conduct in the event of an incorrect assessment.”).

137 For a recent judicial discussion, see Certain Iranian Assets (Iran v. U.S.), Judgment, 2023 ICJ Rep. (Mar. 30, 2023) (sep. op., Robinson, J., paras. 24–36).

138 See generally ILC ASR and commentary supra note 87, Art. 54; Christian J. Tams, Enforcing Obligations Erga Omnes in International Law (2005); Martin Dawidowicz, Third-Party Countermeasures in International Law (2017).

139 ILC ASR, supra note 87, Art. 51.

140 I am very grateful to Dapo Akande for first raising this point with me.

141 Michael Clark, There Is No Paradox of Blackmail, 54 Analysis 54, 55 (1994) (explaining that blackmail is not simply a combination of a demand and a threat, but one done with a particular intention).

142 See also Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 380 (“A state can surely intervene in the affairs of a state in relation to which it is a victim of intervention in order to stop the original intervention.”).

143 Put differently, the same action is intentional under two different descriptions.

144 Anderson, supra note 84, at 2 (contemporary accounts of coercion).

145 See also Helal, supra note 3, at 64–65.

146 I will discuss further below the nature of the threatened or inflicted harm, in particular whether the threat of an otherwise lawful action can constitute coercion-as-extortion.

147 See also 2020 New Zealand Statement, supra note 14, para. 9 (“Coercion can be direct or indirect and may range from dictatorial threats to more subtle means of control.”).

148 See also Ohlin, Jens David, Did Russian Cyber Interference in the 2016 Election Violate International Law?, 95 Tex . L. Rev. 1579, 1588–89 (2017)Google Scholar.

149 This conception of coercion corresponds to how that term is generally understood in international relations scholarship. See, e.g., Robert J. Art & Kelly M. Greenhill, Coercion: An Analytical Overview, in Coercion: The Power to Hurt in International Politics 4–5 (Kelly M. Greenhill & Peter Krause eds., 2017) (“Coercion always involves some cost or pain to the target or explicit threats thereof, with the implied threat to increase the cost or pain if the target does not concede.”).

150 Alexandra Hofer, Sanctioning Qatar: The Finale?, EJIL:Talk! (June 16, 2021), at https://www.ejiltalk.org/sanctioning-qatar-the-finale.

151 See E. Eduardo Castillo, Lavrov: Ukraine Must Demilitarize or Russia Will Do It, AP News (Dec. 27, 2022), at https://apnews.com/article/russia-ukraine-sergey-lavrov-8dae61c0176e1d5c788828f840e1a5a5.

152 See UN Doc. A/RES/2625(XXV), supra note 22, at 123.

153 See ILC, Draft Declaration on Rights and Duties of States, as annexed to General Assembly Resolution 375 (IV) of 6 December 1949, which in Article 1 proclaims that “[e]very State has the right to independence and hence to exercise freely, without dictation by any other State, all its legal powers, including the choice of its own form of government.” Article 3 further provides that “[e]very State has the duty to refrain from intervention in the internal or external affairs of any other State.”

154 Consider, for example, the definition of blackmail in French law. Article 312-10 of the Code pénal (English translation available at https://sherloc.unodc.org/cld/uploads/res/document/french_penal_code_html/french_penal_code.pdf) defines blackmail as “the act of the obtaining either a signature, a commitment or a renunciation, the revelation of a secret, or the handing over of funds, valuables or any asset, by threatening to reveal or to impute facts liable to undermine a person's honour or reputation.” The threat alone suffices to constitute the offense. Article 312-11 then provided for an aggravated form of the offense with elevated penalties where “the blackmailer has put his threat into execution.”

155 Watts, supra note 17, at 268; Corn, supra note 33, at 12.

156 Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 322.

157 See also Hofer & Ferro, supra note 58.

158 See also Moynihan, supra note 15, paras. 101–03.

159 See 2023 U.S. DoD General Counsel Statement, supra note 4.

160 See more Freya Baetens & Marco Bronckers, The EU's Anti-coercion Instrument: A Big Stick for Big Targets, EJIL:Talk! (Jan. 19, 2022), at https://www.ejiltalk.org/the-eus-anti-coercion-instrument-a-big-stick-for-big-targets.

161 Proposal for a Regulation of the European Parliament and of the Council on the Protection of the Union and Its Member States from Economic Coercion by Third Countries, COM(2021) 775 final (Dec. 8, 2021), at https://eur-lex.europa.eu/legal-content/EN/TXT/?uri=celex%3A52021PC0775.

162 Proposal for a Regulation of the European Parliament and of the Council on the Protection of the Union and Its Member States from Economic Coercion by Third Countries, 2021/0406 (COD) (Nov. 16, 2022), at https://data.consilium.europa.eu/doc/document/ST-14837-2022-INIT/en/pdf (hereinafter Council Draft).

163 European Parliament, Report - A9-0246/2022 (Oct. 13, 2022), at https://www.europarl.europa.eu/doceo/document/A-9-2022-0246_EN.html.

164 Council Draft, supra note 162, pmbl. paras. 11–12 (emphasis added).

165 See also Baetens & Bronckers, supra note 160.

166 Report, supra note 163, Amend. 1.

167 Section II.E supra.

168 See, in particular, Derek W. Bowett, Economic Coercion and Reprisals by States, 13 Va. J. Int'l L. 1, 5 (1972) (arguing that otherwise lawful economic measures can become coercive due to an improper purpose).

169 This can for example be the case with the many civil law systems that prescribe intent as the default mode of culpability, without the need to specify mens rea elements for each offense individually. See, e.g., StGB, Sec. 15 (German Criminal Code), at https://www.gesetze-im-internet.de/englisch_stgb (English translation); Codice penale, Art. 42(2) (Italy); Code pénal, Art. 121-3 (France).

170 See Criminal Code of Canada (R.S.C., 1985, c. C-46), Sec. 346 (emphasis added).

171 See Theft Act 1968 (c. 60), Sec. 21 (England and Wales) (emphasis added).

172 See Model Penal Code, Sec. 212.5(1) (United States) (emphasis added).

173 See Criminal Code of Serbia, Arts. 214–15, available at https://www.refworld.org/docid/48ff404a2.html (English translation).

174 See also Helal, supra note 3, at 70.

175 See notes 6, 56 supra.

176 Indeed, English courts will soon decide at trial whether a particular set of loans governed by English law were procured by threat of force by Russia. The Law Debenture Trust Corporation plc v. Ukraine [2023] UKSC 11, paras. 121–22 (an outline of the threatening communications).

177 For a discussion on knowledge, especially in the sense of predicting the future behavior of others, see Milanovic, supra note 96, at 1286–88.

178 See text at note 155 supra.

179 See, e.g., Una Hajdari, How a Name Change Opened the Door to NATO for Macedonia, N.Y. Times (Feb. 6, 2019), at https://www.nytimes.com/2019/02/06/world/europe/macedonia-nato.html; see also Application of the Interim Accord of 13 September 1995 (Maced. v. Greece), Judgment, 2011 ICJ Rep. 644 (Dec. 5).

180 See, e.g., Sweden Says Cannot Fulfil Turkey's Demands for NATO Application, Al Jazeera (Jan. 8, 2023), at https://www.aljazeera.com/news/2023/1/8/sweden-cannot-fulfil-turkeys-demands-for-nato-application-pm; Sweden, Finland Must Send Up to 130 “Terrorists” to Turkey for NATO Bid, Erdogan Says, Reuters (Jan. 16, 2023), at https://www.reuters.com/world/sweden-finland-must-send-up-130-terrorists-turkey-nato-bid-2023-01-16.

181 See note 61 supra and accompanying text.

182 Maryam Sinaee, £400m Funds Released By Britain Received, Being Used: Iran Central Bank, Iran International, Iran Int'l (Apr. 27, 2022), at https://www.iranintl.com/en/202204273789.

183 Note that these two Chinese and Iranian cases of hostage diplomacy would be assessed differently under the argument I developed in Part III above regarding the role of the reserved domain element. Because Iran was exerting pressure on the UK to comply with its (undisputed) legal obligations there would be no interference with the UK's internal and external affairs. Whereas China was influencing decisions that undoubtedly were within Canada's reserved domain, i.e., the extradition of a criminal suspect to another state. For both cases, however, we need to have a consistent answer as to whether such hostage-taking can amount to coercion of the state of nationality. Similarly, in both cases there was clearly a violation of the human rights of the individuals detained.

184 See StGB, supra note 169, Sec. 240(1) (emphasis added).

185 See id., Sec. 240(2).

186 For an overview of the relevant jurisprudence of German courts, see http://www.wiete-strafrecht.de/User/Inhalt/240_StGB.html. See also the offense of extortion in StGB, supra note 169, Sec. 253, which uses similar wording.

187 See Swiss Criminal Code, Art. 181, at https://www.droit-bilingue.ch/rs/lex/1937/00/19370083-a181-en-fr.html (English translation).

188 Model Penal Code, supra note 172, Sec. 212.5(1).

189 See, e.g., Criminal Code of Serbia, supra note 173, Art. 215; Code pénal, supra note 169, Art. 312-10; Theft Act 1968 (c. 60), supra note 171, Sec. 21.

190 See, e.g., Penal Code 1871, Art. 383 (Singapore), and illustrative example (c) therein.

191 See generally James Lindgren, Unravelling the Paradox of Blackmail, 84 Colum. L. Rev. 670 (1984); Clark, supra note 141; Ronald H. Coase, Blackmail (University of Chicago Law Occasional Paper, No. 24, 1988); Walter Block & David Gordon, Blackmail, Extortion and Free Speech: A Reply to Posner, Epstein, Nozick and Lindgren, 19 Loy. L.A. L. Rev. 37 (1985); Mitchell N. Berman, Blackmail, in The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Criminal Law (John Deigh & David Dolinko eds., 2011); Stephen Galoob, Coercion, Fraud, and What Is Wrong with Blackmail, 22 Legal Theory 22 (2016).

192 See generally Rick Bigwood, Exploitative Contracts (2003); David A. Hoffman, Defeating the Empire of Forms, Virg. L. Rev. (forthcoming).

193 For an overview of the philosophical literature distinguishing coercive threats from offers, see Anderson, supra note 84, at 2.4.

194 For an interesting recent English case on the so-called lawful act duress doctrine, which invalidates a contract procured through an illegitimate threat or pressure even if the threatened harm was not unlawful, see Pakistan International Airline Corporation v. Times Travel (UK) Ltd. [2021] UKSC 40. The Supreme Court's approach to illegitimacy was restrictive, rejecting a broader position under which duress could exist whenever there was (lawful) conduct that was morally or socially unacceptable. But, even so, the test of illegitimacy remains a moralized one. The Court subsequently applied this approach in The Law Debenture Trust Corporation plc v. Ukraine [2023] UKSC 11, which concerned loans from Russia taken by Ukraine (and governed by English law) that Ukraine subsequently argued were procured through Russian duress. The Supreme Court held that state-to-state economic measures could not constitute illegitimate duress under English law (id., paras. 149–70), in part because they have been “part of the armoury of the state since classical times” (id., para. 152)—note the parallel to international law debates on whether economic measures can constitute coercion. The Court remanded to trial the issue of whether Russia's alleged threats of use of force, which could constitute duress, rendered the loans voidable.

195 Cf. Model Penal Code, supra note 172, Sec. 223.4(5), defining one type of theft by extortion as threatening to “bring about or continue a strike, boycott or other collective unofficial action, if the property is not demanded or received for the benefit of the group in whose interest the actor purports to act.”

196 See Criminal Code of Canada (R.S.C., 1985, c. C-46), supra note 170, Sec. 346.

197 See StGB, supra note 169, Sec. 240(2).

198 Theft Act 1968 (c. 60), supra note 171, Sec. 21.

199 Model Penal Code, supra note 172, Sec. 212.5(1); see also id., Sec. 223.4 (which has a similar affirmative defense for theft by extortion).

200 Part III supra.

201 Pomson, supra note 10, at 216–18.

202 It is notable in that regard how UNGA resolutions on Cuba reaffirm the principle of non-intervention but do not label the embargo as an example of intervention or coercion. See UNGA Resolution on the Necessity of Ending the Economic, Commercial and Financial Embargo Imposed by the United States of America Against Cuba, pmbl. paras. 2, 4, operative para. 2, UN Doc. A/75/L.97 (June 9, 2021). The resolution was adopted by 184 votes in favor, two against (the United States and Israel), and three abstentions. Taken as a whole, these paragraphs imply that U.S. sanctions are unlawful primarily because of their extraterritorial effects, i.e., an excess of jurisdiction infringing upon the sovereignty of other states, rather than because they are an act of intervention against Cuba. On this issue, see Julia Schmidt, The Legality of Unilateral Extra-territorial Sanctions Under International Law, 27 J. Conf. & Sec. L. 53 (2022).

203 2023 U.S. DoD General Counsel Statement, supra note 4.

204 I would argue that the rights of a state's nationals can be as relevant here as those of the state itself, because the state is generally regarded as having a legal interest in vindicating those rights (e.g., by means of diplomatic protection) and because harm to the state's nationals can systematically be leveraged against the state, for example due to internal political pressure on the state's authorities to assist their nationals.

205 See, e.g., Tzanakopoulos, supra note 7, at 626–27 (arguing that lawful acts can never amount to economic coercion and constitute prohibited intervention).

206 See generally Anna Ventouratou, Litigating Economic Sanctions, 21 L. & Pract. Int’ l Cts. & Tribs. 593 (2022).

207 See more Barber, supra note 12, at 368–69.

208 Helal, supra note 3, at 74 (“to constitute coercion, the coercing state must use unlawful instruments to compel the coerced state to comply with its demands.”); see also id. at 81–89 (arguing that lawful measures can constitute coercion only when they are a part of package that includes unlawful measures).

209 Anderson, supra note 84, at 3.1 (discussing various approaches to the ethics of coercion). A good point of comparison would be the definition of criminal coercion in the U.S .Model Penal Code, which includes the threat of committing any criminal offense. Model Penal Code, supra note 172, Sec. 212.5(1)(a).

210 Thomas M. Franck, Legitimacy in the International System, 82 AJIL 705, 741 (1988).

211 Bowett, supra note 168, at 5.

212 Ohlin, supra note 148, at 1589–93; Pomson, supra note 10, at 209.

213 See Application of the Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide (Croat. v. Serb.), Judgment, 2015 ICJ Rep. 3, para. 474 (Feb. 3).

214 See also Pakistan International Airline Corporation v. Times Travel (UK) Ltd. [2021] UKSC 40 (UK Supreme Court affirming the lawful act duress doctrine, even while keeping it narrowly circumscribed in commercial contexts, allowing for the possibility that illegitimate threats of lawful harms may invalidate a contract).

215 See, e.g., the examples from German and Swiss law discussed at notes 184–187 supra.

216 See Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 330–37; Nicaragua, supra note 2, para. 195.

217 Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, Art. 8bis, July 17, 1998.

218 See, e.g., Moynihan, supra note 15, paras. 64–72.

219 Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 371.

220 See, in that regard, Helal, supra note 3, at 78–79, arguing against a severity threshold precisely because in his view it would be difficult to prove causation. But again, in my view the two should not be conflated; in particular, a state that resists even severe harms should not be penalized simply for its ability to resist.

221 See, e.g., Australia, in UN Doc. A /76/136*, at 9; 2021 Germany Statement, supra note 14, at 34.

222 See id.

223 See Council Draft, supra note 162, pmbl. para. 11.

224 See note 179 supra; see also Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 373–74.

225 See also Barber, supra note 12, at 364 (coercion only constitutes intervention if it is aimed at subordinating a state's sovereign rights).

226 See Jennings & Watts, supra note 1, at 432 (emphasis added).

227 2022 UKAG Speech, supra note 14 (“In essence, an intervention in the affairs of another State will be unlawful if it is forcible, dictatorial, or otherwise coercive, depriving a State of its freedom of control over matters which it is permitted to decide freely by the principle of State sovereignty.”) Clearly, this arguably broad reading of coercion is at least partly influenced by the UK's view that sovereignty is not a rule in the cyber context, but a mere principle. See note 41 supra and accompanying text. That is, a conception of coercion-as-control can to some extent fill the void left by the absence of sovereignty as a rule. But while the UK's position on coercion is undoubtedly self-interested to some extent, that is also true of all states, and does not undermine the point that coercion-as-control can still usefully be seen as a species of coercion.

228 See also Anderson, supra note 84, at 2.1.1.

229 See notes 14, 48, supra.

230 See, e.g., 2022 Canada Statement, supra note 14, para. 24; 2020 Finland Statement, supra note 14, at 3.

231 See also Nicholas Tsagourias, Electoral Cyber Interference, Self-Determination and the Principle of Non-intervention in Cyberspace, EJIL:Talk! (Aug. 26, 2019), at https://www.ejiltalk.org/electoral-cyber-interference-self-determination-and-the-principle-of-non-intervention-in-cyberspace.

232 But see Dan Efrony & Yuval Shany, A Rule Book on the Shelf? Tallinn Manual 2.0 on Cyberoperations and Subsequent State Practice, 112 AJIL 583, 641–43 (2018) (arguing that election interference operations violate the non-intervention rule even though they are not coercive; the basic issue with their argument, however, is that they do not explain what they mean by coercion and why these operations should not therefore be regarded as meeting the relevant criteria). See similarly Ido Kilovaty, The Elephant in the Room: Coercion, 113 AJIL Unbound 87 (2019).

233 See Stephen R. Galoob & Erin Sheley, Reconceiving Coercion-Based Criminal Defenses, 112 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 265, 271 (2022) (relying on the work of the philosopher Scott Anderson). See also Anderson, supra note 84, at 2.1.1; Scott Anderson, The Enforcement Approach to Coercion, 5 J. Eth. & Soc. Phil. 1 (2010).

234 See also Moynihan, supra note 15, para. 98 (“The very inability of the target state to exercise control over its sovereign functions, with the harmful effects that are likely to ensue within the target state as a result, is the outcome that the perpetrating state is seeking to compel.”); Corn, supra note 33, at 13 (conceptualizing coercion as depriving a state of its “free will,” e.g., through deception rather than threats).

235 See UN Doc. A/RES/2625(XXV), supra note 22, at 123.

236 Nicaragua, supra note 2, paras. 205, 228.

237 See Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 373; Helal, supra note 3, at 119; International Law 191, 200 (Malcolm Evans ed., 5th ed. 2018).

238 See Hersch Lauterpacht, Recognition of States in International Law, 53 Yale L.J. 385, 391 (1944).

239 See Moynihan, supra note 15, para. 48.

240 See Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 372.

241 See 2022 UKAG Speech, supra note 14.

242 2020 Australia Statement, supra note 14 (emphasis added).

243 See 2020 New Zealand Statement, supra note 14, para. 9.

244 See 2022 Canada Statement, supra note 14, para. 22.

245 See, e.g., 2020 New Zealand Statement, supra note 14, para. 10 (“Examples of malicious cyber activity that might violate the non-intervention rule include: a cyber operation that deliberately manipulates the vote tally in an election or deprives a significant part of the electorate of the ability to vote; a prolonged and coordinated cyber disinformation operation that significantly undermines a state's public health efforts during a pandemic; and cyber activity deliberately causing significant damage to, or loss of functionality in, a state's critical infrastructure, including—for example—its healthcare system, financial system, or its electricity or telecommunications network.”); 2022 Poland Statement, supra note 14, at 4 (“A cyber operation that adversely affects the functioning and security of the political, economic, military or social system of a state, potentially leading to the state‘s conduct that would not occur otherwise, may be considered a prohibited intervention. In particular, any action in cyberspace that would prevent the filing of tax returns online or any interference with ICT systems that would prevent a reliable and timely conduct of democratic elections would be a violation of international law. Similarly, depriving the parliament working remotely of the possibility of voting online to adopt a law or modifying the outcome of such voting would also be such a violation. It should also be noted that a wide-scale and targeted disinformation campaign may also contravene the principle of non-intervention, in particular when it results in civil unrest that requires specific responses on the part of the state.”); 2022 UKAG Speech, supra note 14 (discussing various examples, including disruption to the state's elections, medical system or electricity supply).

246 See also Galoob & Sheley, supra note 233, at 288–301 (distinguishing between coercion as wrongful pressure and coercive control).

247 Section IV.B supra.

248 See 2020 New Zealand Statement, supra note 14, para. 9; see also 2021 Germany Statement, supra note 14, at 34–35.

249 See also Moynihan, supra note 15, para. 98; Corn, supra note 33, at 18.

250 See also Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 322.

251 Similar issues of intentionality can arise in other contexts, e.g., as to possible violations of territorial sovereignty or the prohibition on the use of force. Consider, for instance, the November 15, 2022 incident in which a Ukrainian missile intended to intercept ongoing Russian attacks landed in Poland in error, while killing two Polish citizens. Marko Milanovic, As Far As We Know, There Has Been No Armed Attack Against Poland, EJIL:Talk! (Nov. 16, 2022), at https://www.ejiltalk.org/as-far-as-we-know-there-has-been-no-armed-attack-against-poland. Violations of sovereignty would generally not require intent. If, for example, the officials of one state unwittingly trespass onto the territory of another, a breach of territorial sovereignty has occurred even absent intent. In the cyber context a sovereignty rule would for that reason also capture more state activities that the prohibition of intervention.

252 See, e.g., 2021 Germany Statement, supra note 14, at 34 (referring to an intent requirement to avoid the non-intervention rule sweeping too broadly).

253 See also Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 321.

254 This likely explains the views of the minority of the Tallinn Manual experts who advocated for a knowledge requirement even while discussing examples, such as cyber election of interference, that involved no demand-threat-harm dynamic of coercion-as-extortion. Id. at 320–21.

255 Part IV.C supra.

256 Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 322.

257 See also Moynihan, supra note 15, paras. 101–03; 2023 U.S. DoD General Counsel Statement, supra note 4.

258 ILC ASR supra note 87, Arts. 34–37 (discussing different forms of reparation).

259 Pomson, supra note 10, at 216–19.

260 See also Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 381.

261 See, e.g., 2021 U.S. Statement, supra note 14, at 140.

262 See, e.g., Australia, in UN Doc. A/76/136, at 9 (“establishing the aforementioned elements of prohibited intervention would depend on the circumstances, including the extent of economic damage and the loss of government control over economic policy”); 2021 Germany Statement, supra note 14, at 34 (“cyber measures may constitute a prohibited intervention under international law if they are comparable in scale and effect to coercion in non-cyber contexts. Coercion implies that a State's internal processes regarding aspects pertaining to its domaine réservé are significantly influenced or thwarted” (emphasis in original).); 2022 UKAG Speech, supra note 14 (“in considering whether the threshold for a prohibited intervention is met, all relevant circumstances, including the overall scale and effect of a cyber operation, need to be considered”); EU Anti-Coercion Instrument, Council Draft, supra note 162, pmbl. para. 11 (referring to “a certain qualitative or quantitative threshold”).

263 For the classical study on this issue, see Damrosch, supra note 7, at 13–28.

264 Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 368 (“The key test remains coercion. Funding a political party where the domestic law of the recipient party prohibits it will usually contravene the principle of non-intervention, as will funding a party with coercive goals. Even absent those factors, the level of support might be of such a magnitude as to be coercive.”); see also id. at 369 (discussing the provision of funding on the eve of elections as a more intrusive or coercive form of interference).

265 See generally Damrosch, supra note 7, at 18–21. If the funding is provided in accordance with B's laws, especially if the laws concern expressly permit for such a possibility, then B can be presumed to have consented to it, thus excluding any possibility of coercion. See also id. at 43–45.

266 See also Jamnejad & Wood, supra note 3, at 374 (arguing that if broadcasting is “deliberately false and intended to produce dissent or encourage insurgents, the non-intervention principle is likely to be breached. If factual and neutral, it is doubtful that the broadcast will constitute intervention, regardless of the effect it may in fact have.”); Tsagourias, supra note 231; Ossoff, supra note 24, at 319–20; Michael N. Schmitt, “Virtual” Disenfranchisement: Cyber Election Meddling in the Grey Zones of International Law, 19 Chi. J. Int'l L. 30, 51 (2018).

267 Moynihan, supra note 15, para. 132.

268 Suranjana Tewari & Jonathan Josephs, US-China Chip War: How the Technology Dispute Is Playing Out, BBC News (Dec. 16, 2022), at https://www.bbc.co.uk/news/business-63995570.

269 To my knowledge the United States is not arguing that these controls are a response to unlawful behavior by China, which would raise the possibility of justifying them as countermeasures, on which see the discussion in Part III above.

270 See also 2023 U.S. DoD General Counsel Statement, supra note 4 (“Other States have adopted a broader view, that any act that deprives a State of freedom of control over elements of its domaine réservé would constitute prohibited intervention. This broader approach may stem from a desire to hold States accountable for seriously disruptive conduct without requiring a target State to show that the conduct was meant to induce a particular act or omission. But focusing solely on deprivation of control, without more, could turn any disruptive cyber activity by a State that affects, even unwittingly, certain elements of another State's activities into an unlawful intervention” (emphasis in original).).

271 See, e.g., G7 Leaders’ Statement on Economic Resilience and Economic Security (May 20, 2023), at https://www.mofa.go.jp/files/100506843.pdf.

272 This is arguably the position adopted in the proposed EU anti-coercion instrument, which counts as prohibited coercion (i.e., intervention) only those measures designed to compel compliance with demands that the target state “is not internationally obliged to perform” and also requires a (somewhat more nebulous) assessments of whether the coercing third state is pursuing “a legitimate cause, because its objective is to uphold a concern that is internationally recognised, such as, among other things, the maintenance of international peace and security, the protection of human rights, the protection of the environment, and the fight against climate change.” Council Draft, supra note 162, pmbl. para. 11; see also id. Art. 2.

273 See also Tallinn Manual 2.0, supra note 15, at 325.

274 See, e.g., Efrony & Shany, supra note 232, at 641–43.

275 See note 14 supra.