Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-cfpbc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T22:30:53.645Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Law Theories

from Part I - Foundations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 July 2017

George Duke
Affiliation:
Deakin University, Victoria
Robert P. George
Affiliation:
Princeton University, New Jersey
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2017

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Works Cited

Alexy, R. 2008. ‘On the Concept and Nature of Law’, Ratio Juris, 21, pp. 281299CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alexy, R. 2010a. The Argument from Injustice. Trans. Paulson, B.L. and Paulson, S.L.. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Alexy, R. 2010b. ‘The Dual Nature of Law’, Ratio Juris, 23, pp. 167182CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aquinas, T. 1948. Summa Theologiae. Trans. Fathers, Dominican. Notre Dame, IN: Ave MariaGoogle Scholar
Austin, J. 1995. The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, L.R. 2004. ‘The Ontology of Artifacts’, Philosophical Explorations, 7, pp. 99112CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, L.R. 2007. The Metaphysics of Everyday Life: An Essay in Practical Realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barton, M.E. and Komatsu, L.K.. 1989. ‘Defining Features of Natural Kinds and Artifacts’, Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, 18, pp. 433447CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bastick, T. 1982. Intuition: How We Think and Act. Chichester: John Wiley and SonsGoogle Scholar
Bloom, P. 1996. ‘Intention, History and Artifact Concepts’, Cognition, 60, pp.129CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Burge, T. 1992. ‘Philosophy of Language and Mind: 1950–1990’, Philosophical Review, 101, pp. 351CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carrara, M. and Vermaas, P.E.. 2009. ‘The Fine-Grained Metaphysics of Artifactual and Biological Functional Kinds’, Synthese, 169, pp. 125143CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chappell, T. 1998. Understanding Human Goods. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chartier, G. 2009. Economic Justice and Natural Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coleman, J. and Simchen, O.. 2003. ‘Law’, Legal Theory, 9, pp. 141Google Scholar
Crowe, J. 2005. ‘Existentialism and Natural Law’, Adelaide Law Review, 26, pp. 5572Google Scholar
Crowe, J. 2011a. ‘Natural Law Beyond Finnis’, Jurisprudence, 2, pp. 293308CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crowe, J. 2011b. ‘Pre-Reflective Law’, in New Waves in Philosophy of Law. Ed. Del Mar, M.. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacmillanGoogle Scholar
Crowe, J. 2012. ‘Clarifying the Natural Law Thesis’, Australian Journal of Legal Philosophy, 37, pp. 159181Google Scholar
Crowe, J. 2014. ‘Law as an Artifact Kind’, Monash University Law Review, 40, pp. 737757Google Scholar
Crowe, J. 2015. ‘Natural Law and Normative Inclinations’, Ratio Juris, 28, pp.5267CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crowe, J. 2016. ‘Natural Law Theories’, Philosophy Compass, 11, pp. 91101CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehrenberg, K. 2009. ‘Defending the Possibility of a Neutral Functional Theory of Law’, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 29, pp. 91113CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehrenberg, K. 2013. ‘Functions in Jurisprudential Methodology’, Philosophy Compass, 8, pp. 447456CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elder, C.L. 2004. Real Natures and Familiar Objects. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elder, C.L. 2007. ‘On the Place of Artifacts in Ontology’, in Creations of the Mind: Theories of Artifacts and their Representation. Eds Margolis, Eric and Laurence, Stephen. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Finnis, J. 1983. Fundamentals of Ethics. Washington, DC: Georgetown University PressGoogle Scholar
Finnis, J. 1998. Aquinas: Moral, Political and Legal Theory. Oxford: Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finnis, J. 2011. Natural Law and Natural Rights. 2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Fortin, E.L. 1982. ‘The New Rights Theory and the Natural Law’, Review of Politics, 44, pp. 590612CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuller, L.L. 1969. The Morality of Law. Revised edn. New Haven, CT: Yale University PressGoogle Scholar
Gardner, J. 2004. ‘The Legality of Law’, Ratio Juris, 17, pp. 168181CrossRefGoogle Scholar
George, R.P. 1988. ‘Recent Criticism of Natural Law Theory’, University of Chicago Law Review, 55, pp. 13711429CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gómez-Lobo, A. 2002. Morality and the Human Goods. Washington, DC: Georgetown University PressGoogle Scholar
Grisez, G. 1965. ‘The First Principle of Practical Reason: A Commentary on the Summa Theologiae, 1–2, Question 94, Article 2’, Natural Law Forum, 10, pp. 168201Google Scholar
Grisez, G. 1983. The Way of the Lord Jesus: Christian Moral Principles. Quincy, IL: Franciscan PressGoogle Scholar
Grisez, G., Boyle, J.M. and Finnis, J.. 1987a. Nuclear Deterrence, Morality and Realism. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Grisez, G., Boyle, J.M. and Finnis, J.. 1987b. ‘Practical Principles, Moral Truth and Ultimate Ends’, American Journal of Jurisprudence, 32, pp. 99151CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H.L.A. 1994. The Concept of Law. 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Hegel, G.W.F. 1977. Phenomenology of Spirit. Trans. Miller, A.V.. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Hilpinen, R. 1993. ‘Authors and Artifacts’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 93, pp. 155178CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hittinger, R. 1987. A Critique of the New Natural Law Theory. Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University PressGoogle Scholar
Kornblith, H. 1980. ‘Referring to Artifacts’, Philosophical Review, 89, pp.109114CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leiter, B. 2011. ‘The Demarcation Problem in Jurisprudence: A New Case for Scepticism’, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 31, pp. 663677CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. 1989. ‘Dispositional Theories of Value’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 63, pp. 113137Google Scholar
Levinson, J. 1979. ‘Defining Art Historically’, British Journal of Aesthetics, 19, pp. 232250CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinson, J. 2007. ‘Artworks as Artifacts’, in Creations of the Mind: Theories of Artifacts and their Representation. Eds Margolis, E. and Laurence, S.. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Lisska, A. 1996. Aquinas’s Theory of Natural Law: An Analytic Reconstruction. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Lumb, R.D. 1959. ‘The Scholastic Doctrine of Natural Law’, Melbourne University Law Review, 2, pp. 205221Google Scholar
Macklem, T. 2013. ‘Ideas of Easy Virtue’, in Reason, Morality and Law: The Philosophy of John Finnis. Eds Keown, J. and George, R.P.. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Maslow, A.H. 1943. ‘A Theory of Human Motivation’, Psychological Review, 50, pp. 370396CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McInerny, R. 1982. Ethica Thomistica. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America PressGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. 1984. Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, M.S. 1992. ‘Law as a Functional Kind’, in Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays. Ed. George, R.P.. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Moore, M.S. 2001. ‘Law as Justice’, Social Philosophy and Policy, 18, pp. 115145CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, M.C. 2001. Natural Law and Practical Rationality. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Murphy, M.C. 2003. ‘Natural Law Jurisprudence’, Legal Theory, 9, pp. 241267CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, M.C. 2006. Natural Law in Jurisprudence and Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, M.C. 2011. ‘Defect and Deviance in Natural Law Jurisprudence’, in Institutional Reason: The Jurisprudence of Robert Alexy. Ed. Klatt, M.. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Murphy, M.C. 2013. ‘The Explanatory Role of the Weak Natural Law Thesis’, in Philosophical Foundations of the Nature of Law. Eds.Waluchow, W. and Sciaraffa, S.. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, State and Utopia. New York: Basic BooksGoogle Scholar
Nozick, R. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Belknap PressGoogle Scholar
Porter, J. 1993. ‘Basic Goods and the Human Good in Recent Catholic Moral Theology’, The Thomist, 57, pp. 2749CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, J. 1979. The Authority of Law. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Searle, J. 1995. The Construction of Social Reality. New York: Free PressGoogle Scholar
Shiner, R.A. 2010. ‘Law and its Normativity’, in A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Ed. Patterson, D.. 2nd edn. Oxford: BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Sloman, S. and Malt, B.. 2002. ‘Artifacts Are Not Ascribed Essences, Nor Are They Treated as Belonging to Kinds’, Language and Cognitive Processes, 18, pp. 563582CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, M. 1994. The Moral Problem. Oxford: BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Thomasson, A.L. 2003. ‘Realism and Human Kinds’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67, pp. 580609CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomasson, A.L. 2007a. ‘Artifacts and Human Concepts’, in Creations of the Mind: Theories of Artifacts and their Representation. Eds Margolis, E. and Laurence, S.. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Thomasson, A.L. 2007b. Ordinary Objects. Oxford: Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Inwagen, P. 1990. Material Beings. Ithaca: Cornell University PressGoogle Scholar
Veatch, H. 1981. ‘Natural Law and the “Is”-“Ought” Question’, Catholic Lawyer, 81, pp. 251265Google Scholar
Vernon, M.D. 1969. Human Motivation. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Wiggins, D. 1980. Sameness and Substance. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wiggins, D. 2001. Sameness and Substance Renewed. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×