Skip to main content
×
Home
    • Aa
    • Aa
  • Get access
    Check if you have access via personal or institutional login
  • Cited by 13
  • Cited by
    This chapter has been cited by the following publications. This list is generated based on data provided by CrossRef.

    Lebens, Samuel 2017. The life of faith as a work of art: a Rabbinic theology of faith. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 81, Issue. 1-2, p. 61.

    Bueno, Otávio and Zalta, Edward N. 2017. Object Theory and Modal Meinongianism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, p. 1.

    GILL, MARY LOUISE 2014. Design of the Exercise in Plato’s Parmenides. Dialogue, Vol. 53, Issue. 03, p. 495.

    2013. I 1 Euthyphron. p. 191.

    Notomi, Noburu 2012. A Companion to Ancient Philosophy. p. 192.

    Mourelatos, Alexander P. D. 2012. A Companion to Ancient Philosophy. p. 56.

    2010. Die Argumente des Dritten Menschen in Platons Dialog »Parmenides«. p. 397.

    Horn, Christoph Müller, Jörn Söder, Joachim Schriefl, Anna and Weber, Simon 2009. Platon-Handbuch. p. 253.

    Bailey, D. T. J. 2009. The Third Man Argument. Philosophy Compass, Vol. 4, Issue. 4, p. 666.

    Horn, Christoph Müller, Jörn Söder, Joachim Schriefl, Anna and Weber, Simon 2009. Platon-Handbuch. p. 101.

    Horn, Christoph Müller, Jörn Söder, Joachim Schriefl, Anna and Weber, Simon 2009. Platon-Handbuch. p. 61.

    2006. »Dieses« und »So etwas«. p. 321.

    Zalta, Edward N. 2002. A Common Ground and Some Surprising Connections. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 40, Issue. S1, p. 1.

    ×
  • Print publication year: 1992
  • Online publication date: May 2006

12 - Good-bye to the Third Man

Summary

Plato's commitment to what has been called “self-predication” that is, to sentences of the form

Bravery is brave

The Large is large

is one of the most evident and characteristic features of his work. This commitment figures in dialogues of all three periods, and is so far from optional as to be at the foundation of Platonism. Yet these sentences immediately produce negative reactions in us. The first one displayed above, for example, seems clearly false. It seems to be attributing a feature to Bravery that it could not have - we can hardly imagine it performing deeds of valor or bearing up under adversity. The characteristic claim that the Large is large without qualification seems ludicrously to take its subject as another thing like an elephant, only bigger. The presence of claims of this type in Plato's text can make us feel that his way of thinking is not merely foreign to us, but seriously confused as well. Aristotle's rude and dismissive outburst “So good-bye to the Forms. For they are nonsense” seems about right.

Our background suspicion that the Platonic Forms may not really be respectable makes the Parmenides especially intriguing to us. For that dialogue owes its fame to the presence, in its first part, of an exchange between a young Socrates and a venerable Parmenides. The utterances of Socrates are reminiscent of statements that are widely regarded as constituting Plato's theory of Forms, as presented in the Republic and the Phaedo. Yet here, when questioned by Parmenides, Socrates fails repeatedly to uphold his views, and falls into perplexity. This passage has seemed to generations of readers to show a sensitivity to the kinds of problems they themselves associated with Platonism (including but not confined to confusion over self-predication).

Recommend this book

Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this book to your organisation's collection.

The Cambridge Companion to Plato
  • Online ISBN: 9781139000574
  • Book DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CCOL0521430186
Please enter your name
Please enter a valid email address
Who would you like to send this to? *
×