Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-r6qrq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T17:30:13.607Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

18 - Animals, the environment and global health

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 March 2011

Solomon Benatar
Affiliation:
University of Cape Town
Gillian Brock
Affiliation:
University of Auckland
Get access

Summary

Introduction

When people talk about global health, and the ethics thereof, they almost invariably mean global human health. This is not because it is impossible to have more expansive notions of global health that include other species. Instead it is because most people who are concerned about global health, like most of those who are concerned about local health, are either not concerned at all, or are much less concerned, with the health of other species. Thus global health ethics, although expanding the reach of health ethics geographically, has not extended moral concern to other species within that global space.

This is unfortunate for at least two reasons. First, there is good reason to think that not only humans but also some other animals, the sentient ones, are worthy of moral consideration. That is to say, they are the sorts of beings to which we have moral duties. I shall not argue for this conclusion here, in part because it has been defended extensively elsewhere, but also because overlooking animal welfare in the way that people generally do, poses a considerable threat to global human health. Thus, even those who fail to recognize the moral standing of non-human animals but do recognize the moral standing of humans should be more attentive to animal well-being on account of its instrumental value for human health.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Benatar, D. (2005). Sexist language: alternatives to the alternatives. Public Affairs Quarterly 19, 1–9.Google Scholar
Benatar, D. (2006). Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming Into Existence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benatar, D. (2007). The chickens come home to roost. American Journal of Public Health 97, 1545–1546.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boyd, W. (2001). Making meat: science, technology and American poultry production. Technology and Culture 42, 631–664.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, A. (1990). Justice as reciprocity versus subject-centered justice. Philosophy and Public Affairs 19, 227–252.Google Scholar
Caney, S. (2009). Climate change and the future: discounting for time, wealth and risk. Journal of Social Philosophy 40, 163–186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeGrazia, D. (1996). Taking Animals Seriously. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, J. (1984). Harm to Others. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Feinberg, J. (1992). Wrongful life and the counterfactual element in harming. In Freedom and Fulfilment (pp. 3–36). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gao, F., Bailes, E., Robertson, D. L.et al. (1999). Origin of HIV-1 in the chimpanzeePan troglodytes troglodytes. Nature 397, 436–441.Google ScholarPubMed
Glover, J. (1975). It makes no difference whether or not I do it. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume XLIX, 171–190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guan, Y., Zheng, B. J., He, Y. Q.et al. (2003). Isolation and characterization of viruses related to the SARS coronavirus from animals in Southern China. Science 302, 276–278.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Houghton, J. T., Jenkins, G. J. & Ephraums, J. J. (Eds.) (1990). Climate Change: The IPCC Scientific Assessment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
McMichael, A. J. (1993). Planetary Overload: Global Environmental Change and the Health of the Human Species. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
McMichael, A. (2001). Human Frontiers, Environments and Disease. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Osterholm, M. T. (2005). Preparing for the next pandemic. New England Journal of Medicine 352, 1839–1852.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pachauri, R. K. & Reisinger, A. (Eds.) (2007). Summary for policymakers. In Climate Change 2007: Synthesis Report. A Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (pp. 1–22). Geneva: IPCC.
Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Reagan, T. (1983). The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Scott, M. R., Will, R. G., Ironside, J. et al. (1999). Compelling transgenetic evidence for transmission of bovine spongiform encephalopathy prions to humans. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 96, 15137–15142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shafer-Landau, R. (1994). Vegetarianism, causation and ethical theory. Public Affairs Quarterly 8, 85–100.Google Scholar
Sharp, P., Bailes, E., Chaudhuri, R. R. et al. (2001). The origins of acquired immune deficiency syndrome viruses: where and when?Philosophical Transactions Royal Society London B 356, 867–876.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Singer, P. (1990). Animal Liberation. (2nd edn.) New York, NY: New York Review of Books.Google Scholar
Weber, J. & Alcorn, K. (2000). Origins of HIV and the AIDS epidemic. Medscape General Medicine 2, 1–6.Google Scholar
Webster, R. G. (2004). Wet markets – a continuing source of severe acute respiratory syndrome and influenza. Lancet 365, 234–236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Will, R. G., Ironside, J. W., Zeidler, M. et al. (1996). A new variant of Creutzfeldt-Jakob disease in the UK. Lancet 347, 921–925.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×