Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-22dnz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T18:06:54.224Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

19 - Essence and existence

from VI - Metaphysics and epistemology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Get access

Summary

First philosophy, divine science, and the science of ‘being as being’

The recovery of Aristotle's Metaphysics by medieval Western thinkers prepared the way for them to concentrate on the science of ‘being as being’ in the high Middle Ages. This work was enhanced by the translation into Latin of Avicenna's Metaphysics in the twelfth century and of Averroes' Commentary on Aristotle's Metaphysics in the early thirteenth century. But as medieval Latin thinkers began to examine Aristotle's text more closely, they encountered a problem of interpretation relating to the very nature of metaphysics.

In Metaphysics IV, c. 1 (1003a21–32), Aristotle speaks of a science which studies being as being and contrasts it with more particular sciences which restrict themselves to investigating the attributes of a portion of being. But in Metaphysics VI, c. 1 (1026a23–32), after referring to his investigation of ‘beings as beings’ and presumably, therefore, to his science of being as being, Aristotle distinguishes three theoretical sciences – physics, mathematics, and first philosophy or ‘divine science’ – and then seems to justify the viability of the last-mentioned one only insofar as it concerns itself with separate and immobile entities. One might wonder whether this first philosophy or divine science can be identified with Aristotle's general science of being as being, a difficulty which he himself recognises. He concludes the discussion by asserting that if there were no separate and immobile entity, then physics would be the first science.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy
From the Rediscovery of Aristotle to the Disintegration of Scholasticism, 1100–1600
, pp. 383 - 410
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Albert, the Great (1890–9C). Liber de causis et processu universitatis (vol. 10), VivèsGoogle Scholar
Alluntis, F. (1965). ‘Demonstrability and Demonstration of the Existence of God’, in Ryan, J. K. and Bonansea, B. M. (eds.) John Duns Scotus 1263–1065, Catholic University of AmericaGoogle Scholar
Alluntis, F., and Wolter, A. (1975). John Duns Scotus. God and Creatures: The Quodlibetal Questions, Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Averroes, (1562–74C). Media expositio Topicorum Aristotelis (Aristotelis opera cum Averrois commentariis, 1.3), VeniceGoogle Scholar
Averroes, (1562–74d). Commentary on the Physics (Aristotelis opera cum Averrois commentariis, IV), VeniceGoogle Scholar
Averroes, (1562–74f). Commentary on the Metaphysics (Aristotelis opera cum Averrois commentariis, VIII), VeniceGoogle Scholar
Barth, T. (1939). ‘De fundamento univocationis apud Joannem Duns Scotum’, Antonianum 14:.Google Scholar
Barth, T. (1953). ‘De univocationis entis scotisticae intentione principali necnon valore critico’, Antonianum 28:.Google Scholar
Boehner, Philotheus (1958). Collected Articles on Ockham, ed. Buytaert, E. M. (Franciscan Institute Publications, Philosophy Series, 12), The Franciscan InstituteGoogle Scholar
Bonaventure, (1882-1902a). Commentarius in quattuor libros Sententiarum Petri Lomhardi (Operaomnia, I-IV),Collegium S. BonaventuraeGoogle Scholar
Brosch, H.J. (1931). Der Seinsbegriff bei Boethius, mit besonderer Berücksichtigung der Beziehung von Sosein und Dasein (Philosophie und Grenzwissenschaften 4, pt. 1: RauchGoogle Scholar
Brown, Stephen F. (1965). ‘Avicenna and the Unity of the Concept of Being’, Franciscan Studies 25:.Google Scholar
Bruder, K. (1928). Die philosophischen Elemente in den Opuscula sacra des Boethius, MeinarGoogle Scholar
Carlo, William (1966a). ‘Idea and Concept: A Key to Epistemology’ in Adelmann, Frederick J. (ed.) The Quest for the Absolute (Boston College Studies in Philosophy, No. 1), Boston College and Martinus NijhoffGoogle Scholar
Chossat, M. (1932). ‘L'Averroisme de saint Thomas. Notes sur la distinction d'essence et d'existence à la fin du XIIIe siecle’, Archives de philosophie 9:129 –177Google Scholar
Chossat, M. (1939). ‘Dieu’, Dictionnaire de theologie catholique 4:Google Scholar
Clarke, W. N. (1952a). ‘The Limitation of Act by Potency: Aristotelianism or Neoplatonism?‘, The New Scholasticism 26:Google Scholar
Clarke, W. N. (1952b). ‘The Meaning of Participation in St Thomas’, Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 26:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, J. (1947). The Thomistic Philosophy of the Angels, The Catholic University of AmericaGoogle Scholar
Crowley, T. (1950). Roger Bacon. The problem of the Soul in his Philosophical Commentaries, DuffyGoogle Scholar
Cunningham, F. (1962). ‘Distinction According to St Thomas’, The New Scholasticism 36:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cunningham, F. (1964). ‘Textos de Santo Tomas sobre el esse y esencia’, Pensamiento 20:Google Scholar
Cunningham, F. (1970). ‘The “Real Distinction” in John Quidort’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 8:CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Day, S. (1947). Intuitive Cognition: A Key to the Significance of the Later Scholastics, The Franciscan InstituteGoogle Scholar
Doig, J. (1965). ‘Science première et science universelle dans le “Commentaire de la métaphysique” de saint Thomas d'Aquin’, Revue philosophique de Louvain 63:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doig, J. (1972). Aquinas on Metaphysics. A historico-doctrinal study of the Commentary on the Metaphysics, Martinus NijhoffGoogle Scholar
Düring, I. (1966). Aristoteles. Darstellung und Interpretation seines Denkens, WinterGoogle Scholar
Fabro, Cornelio (1939). la nozione metafisca di partecipazione secondo san tommaso d'aquino, vita e pensieroGoogle Scholar
Fabro, Cornelio (1950). la nozione metafisica di partecipazione secondo s. tommaso d'aquino (2nd ed.), società editrice internazionaleGoogle Scholar
Fabro, Cornelio (1960). partecipazione e causalità secondo san tommaso, società editrice internazionalGoogle Scholar
Fabro, Cornelio (1961). participation et causalité, publications universitaires de louvainGoogle Scholar
Finance, J. (1960). étre et agir, librairie éditrice de l'université grégorienneGoogle Scholar
Forest, A. (1956). la structure méaphysique du concret selon saint thomas d'aquin (2nd ed.), j-vrinGoogle Scholar
Geiger, L. (1942). La participation dans la philosophie de saint Thomas d'Aquin, J. VrinGoogle Scholar
Geyer, B. (1963). ‘Albertus Magnus und die Entwicklung der Scholastischen Metaphysik’, in Wilpert, P. (ed.) Die Metaphysik im Mittelalter (Miscellanea Mediaevalia, 2), De GruyterGoogle Scholar
Giles, Rome (1481). De Corpore Christi Theoremata, BolognaGoogle Scholar
Giles, Rome (1503). Egidius Romanus de esse et essentia, de mensura angelorum, et de cognitione angelorum, Venice (Reprinted Minerva 1968)Google Scholar
Giles, Rome (1521). In Primum Sententiarum, Venice (Reprinted Minerva 1968)Google Scholar
Gilson, Étienne (1927). ‘Avicenne et le point de départ de Duns Scot’, Archives d'histoire doctrinale et littéraire du moyen âge 2:.Google Scholar
Gilson, Étienne (1948b). ‘L'Objet de la Metaphysique selon Duns Scot’, Mediaeval Studies 10:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilson, Étienne (1950). ‘La preuve du De ente et essentia’, Acta III Congressus Thomistici Internationalis: Doctor Communis 3:.Google Scholar
Gilson, Étienne (1952a). Being and some Philosophers, Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval StudiesGoogle Scholar
Gilson, Étienne (1953). La philosophie de saint Bonaventure, J. VrinGoogle Scholar
Gilson, Étienne (1955). History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages, Random HouseGoogle Scholar
Gilson, Étienne (1961a). The Christian Philosophy of St Thomas Aquinas (With a Catalogue of St Thomas' Works by Eschmann, I. T.), tr. Shook, L. K., Victor GollanczGoogle Scholar
Gilson, Étienne (1968). ‘Sur la composition fondamentale de l'être fini’, in De doclrina Ioannis Duns Scoti. Acta Congressus Scotistici Internationalis Oxonii et Edimburgi 11–17 sept. 1966 celebrati. V. II: Problemata Philosophica, Cura Commissionis ScotisticaeGoogle Scholar
Glorieux, P. (1925). ‘La littérature quodlibétique de 1260 à 1320’, Revue des sciences philosophiques et théologiques 14Google Scholar
Godfrey, Fontaines (1904–37). Les Quodlibets de Godefroid de Fontaines, ed. Wulf, M. and Hoffmans, J. (Les Philosophes Belges), Institut supérieur de Philosophic de l'Université de LouvainGoogle Scholar
Godfrey, Fontaines (1973). ‘Godfrey of Fontaines: Disputed Questions 9, 10 and 12’, ed. Wippel, J. F., Franciscan Studies 33 :Google Scholar
Goichon, A.-M. (1937). La distinction de l'essence et de l'existence d'après îbn Sīnā, Desclée de BrouwerGoogle Scholar
GÓMez, Caffarena J. (1957). ‘Cronología de la “Suma” de Enrique de Gante por relation a sus “Quodlibetos”’, Gregorianum 38:.Google Scholar
GÓMez, Caffarena J. (1958). Ser participado y ser subsistente en la metafisica de Enrique de Gante, Apud Aedes Universitatis GregorianaeGoogle Scholar
Gonsalvus, Spain (1935). Fr. Gonsalvi Hispani O.F.M. Quaestiones disputatae et de Quodlibet, ed. Leo AmorÓS, O.F.M. (Bibliotheca Franciscana Scholastica Medii Aevi, IX), Collegium S. BonaventuraeGoogle Scholar
Grabmann, Martin (1924a). Neu aufgefundene Werke des Siger von Brabant und Boetius von Dacien (Sitzungsberichte der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Philosophisch-historische Abteilung, 1924, No. 2)Google Scholar
Guelluy, R. (1947). Philosophie et Théologie chez Guillaume d'Ockham, NauwelaertsGoogle Scholar
Hadot, Pierre (1970). ‘Forma Essendi: Interprétation philologique et interprétation philosophique d'une formule de Boèce’, Les Études classiques 38:.Google Scholar
Henry, Ghent (1518). Quodlibeta magistri Henrici Goethals a Gandavo doctoris solemnis (2 vols.), Paris (Reprinted Bibliothèque S.J. de Louvain 1961)Google Scholar
Henry, Ghent (1520). Summa quaestionum ordinariarum (2 vols.), Paris (Reprinted Franciscan Institute 1953)Google Scholar
Hocedez, E. (1925). Richard de Middleton. Sa vie, ses oeuvres, sa doctrine, Spicilegium Sacrum LovanienseGoogle Scholar
Hocedez, E. (1927). ‘Gilles de Rome et Henri de Gand sur la distinction réelle (1276–1287)’, Gregorianum 8:.Google Scholar
Hocedez, E. (1928). ‘Le premier Quodlibet d'Henri de Gand (1276)’, Gregorianum 9:.Google Scholar
Hocedez, E. (1930). Aegidii Romani Theoremata de esse et essentia. Texte précédé d'une introduction historique et critique, Museum LessianumGoogle Scholar
Hoeres, W. (1965). ‘Wesen und Dasein bei Heinrich von Gent und Duns Scotus’, Franziskanische Studien 47:.Google Scholar
James, Viterbo (1968). Jacobi de Viterbio O.E.S.A. Disputatio prima de quolibet, ed. Ypma, E., Augustinus-VerlagGoogle Scholar
John, Duns Scotus (1891–5). Opera omnia. Editio nova juxta editionem Waddingi XII tomos con-tinentem a patribus Franciscanis de observantia accurate recognita (26 vols, in 13), VivèsGoogle Scholar
John, Duns Scotus (1950–). Opera omnia, ed. BaliĆ, C. et al., Vatican Scotistic CommissionGoogle Scholar
John, Peckham (1948). Tractatus de anima loannis Pecham, ed. Melani, G., Edizioni ‘Studi Francescani’ s. FrancescoGoogle Scholar
Kleineidam, E. (1973). ‘Geschichte der Wissenschaft im mittelalterlichen Erfurt’. Geschichte Thüringens II 2: BöhlauGoogle Scholar
Klubertanz, George P. (1954a). ‘St Thomas on Learning Metaphysics’, Gregorianum 35 :Google Scholar
KöNig, E. (1970). ‘Aristoteles' erste Philosophie als universale Wissenschaft von den APXAI’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 52:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
La Mare, William (1927). ‘Le Correctorium Corruptorii “Quare”‘, ed. Glorieux, P. in Les premiùres polémiques thomistes, KainGoogle Scholar
Leff, Gordon (1975). William of Ockham: The Metamorphosis of Scholastic Discourse, Manchester University PressGoogle Scholar
Little, A. (1949). The Platonic Heritage of Thomism, Golden Eagle Books Limited, Standard HouseGoogle Scholar
Lottin, O. (1932). ‘La composition hylémorphique des substances spirituelles’, Revue Néoscolastique de Philosophic 34:.Google Scholar
Macken, R. (1976a). ‘Le statut de la matière première chez Bonaventure’, Franziskanische Forschungen 28:.Google Scholar
Marlasca, Antonio (1972). Les Quaestiones super librum de causis de Siger de Brabant, Publications Universi– taires de LouvainGoogle Scholar
Maurer, Armand (1946). ‘Esse and Essentia in the Metaphysics of Siger of Brabant’, Mediaeval Studies 8:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maurer, Armand (1958). ‘Ockham's Conception of the Unity of Science’, Mediaeval Studies 20:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maurer, Armand (1976). ‘Some Aspects of Fourteenth-Century Philosophy’, Medieualia et Humanistica, n.s. 7:Google Scholar
Mclnerny, R. (1974). ‘Boethius and Saint Thomas Aquinas’, Rivista di Filosofia neo-scolastica 66:Google Scholar
Menges, M. C. (1952). The Concept of Univocity Regarding the Predication of God and Creature According to William Ockham, The Franciscan InstituteGoogle Scholar
Moreno, A. (1966). ‘The Nature of Metaphysics’, Thomist 30:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nash, P. (1950). ‘Giles of Rome on Boethius’ “Diversum est esse et id quod est”’, Mediaeval Studies 12:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nash, P. (1950–1). ‘Giles of Rome, Auditor and Critic of St. Thomas’, The Modern Schoolman 28:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nash, P. (1957) ‘The Accidentality of Esse According to Giles of Rome’, Gregorianum 38:.Google Scholar
Nash, P. (1967). ‘Giles of Rome’, New Catholic Encyclopedia 6:.Google Scholar
Nicolas, J.-H. (1948). ‘Chronique de Philosophic’. Revue Thomiste 48:Google Scholar
O'Brien, A.J. (1964). ‘Duns Scotus’ Teaching on the Distinction Between Essence and Existence’, The New Scholasticism 38:.Google Scholar
O'Brien, T. C. (1960). Metaphysics and the Existence of God, The Thomist PressGoogle Scholar
Owens, Joseph (1953). ‘The Conclusion of the Prima Via’, The Modem Schoolman 30:.Google Scholar
Owens, Joseph (1965). ‘Quiddity and Real Distinction in St. Thomas Aquinas’, Mediaeval Studies 27:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owens, Joseph (1966). ‘Aquinas and the Proof from the “Physics”’, Mediaeval Studies 28:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owens, Joseph (1978). The Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian ‘Metaphysics’, A Study in the Creek Background of Mediaeval Thought, 3rd ed., Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval StudiesGoogle Scholar
Pattin, A. (1953). ‘Gilles de Rome, O.E.S.A. (ca. 1243–1316) et la distinction réelle de l'essence et de l'existence’, Revue de I'Université d'Ottawa 23:Google Scholar
Paulus, J. (1933). ‘La théorie du Premier Moteur chez Aristote’, Revue de philosophic n.s. 4: ;Google Scholar
Paulus, J. (1938). Henri de Gand. Essai sur les tendances de sa métaphysique, J. VrinGoogle Scholar
Paulus, J. (1940–2). ‘Les disputes d'Henri de Gand et de Gilles de Rome sur la distinction de l'essence et de l'existence’, Archives d'Histoire doctrinale et littéraire du Moyen Âge 13:.Google Scholar
Pegis, Anton C. (1973). ‘St Thomas and the Coherence of the Aristotelian Theology’, Mediaeval Studies 35:CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peter, John Olivi (1922–6). Quaestiones in secundum librum Sententiarum, ed. Jansen, B. (3 vols.), Bibliotheca Franciscana Scholastica Medii Aevi, Collegium S. BonaventuraeGoogle Scholar
Proclus, (1951). ‘Procli Elementatio theologica translata a Guilelmo de Moerbeke’, ed. Vansteenkiste, C., Tijdschrift voor Philosophie, 13: ;Google Scholar
Quinn, J. F. (1973). The Historical Constitution of St Bonaventure's Philosophy, Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval StudiesGoogle Scholar
Raeymaeker, L. (1954). The Philosophy of Being, HerderGoogle Scholar
Rahman, F. (1958). ‘Essence and Existence in Avicenna’, Mediaeval and Renaissance Studies 4:.Google Scholar
Rahman, F. (1963). ‘Ibn Sīna’ in Sharif, M. M. (ed.) A History of Muslim Philosophy, v. 1, Otto HarrassowitzGoogle Scholar
Renard, H. (1956). ‘What is St Thomas' Approach to Metaphysics?The New Scholasticism 30:Google Scholar
Roos, H. (1977). ‘Henrici Roos in Memoriam. Nachgelassene Papiere’, CIMAGL 24:.Google Scholar
Schrimpf, G. (1966). Die Axiomenschrift des Boethius (De Hebdomadibus) als Philosophisches Lehrbuch des Mittelalters, BrillGoogle Scholar
Siematkowska, Z. K. (1960). ‘Avant l'exil de Gilles de Rome: Au sujet d'une dispute sur les “Theoremata de esse et essentia” de Gilles de Rome’, Mediaevalia Philosophica Polonorum 7:Google Scholar
Siger, Brabant (1948). Siger de Brabant. Questions sur la métaphysique (Quaestiones in Metaphysicam), ed. Graiff, C. A., Éditions de l'lnstitut Supérieur de Philosophie de LouvainGoogle Scholar
Siger, Brabant (1966). Die Questiones metaphysice tres des Siger von Brabant', ed. Vennebusch, J., Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 48:Google Scholar
Smith, V. (1954). ‘Prime Mover, Physical and Metaphysical Considerations’, Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 28:.Google Scholar
Smith, V. (1958). The General Science of Nature, BruceGoogle Scholar
Steenberghen, F. (1966). La Philosophie au XIIIe sièle (Philosophes médiévaux 9), Publications universitaires de Louvain Béatrice-NauwelaertsGoogle Scholar
Steenberghen, F. (1977). Maître Siger de Brabant (Philosophes médiévaux, No. 21), Publications UniversitairesGoogle Scholar
Suarez, G. (1948). ‘El pensamiento de Egidio Romano en torno a la distinción de esencia y existencia’, La Ciencia Tomista 75:.;Google Scholar
Südhoff, K. (1914). ‘Die kurze “Vita” und das Verzeichnis der Arbeiten Gerhards von Cremona’, Archiv für Geschichte der Medizin 8:.Google Scholar
Sweeney, Leo (1963). ‘Existence/Essence in Thomas Aquinas's Early Writings’, Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 37:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Aquinas (1950b). In librum beati Dionysii De divinis nominibus expositio, ed. Pera, C., MariettiGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Aquinas (1953b). Quaestiones disputatae de potentia, in Aquinas, Thomas 1953aGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Aquinas (1953c). Quaeslio disputata de spiritualibus creaturis in Aquinas, Thomas 1953aGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Aquinas (1954b). De ente et essentia in Aquinas, Thomas 1954aGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Aquinas (1954c). De regimine principum ad regent Cypri in Aquinas, Thomas 1954aGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Aquinas (1955). Expositio super librum Boethii De Trinitate, ed. Decker, B. (Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters, 4), BrillGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Aquinas (1956). Quaestiones quodlibetales, ed. Spiazzi, R. M. (9th rev. edn.), MariettiGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Aquinas (1963). Treatise on Separate Substances (Tractatus de Subslantiis Separatis), ed. and tr. Lescoe, F.J., Saint Joseph College, West Hartford, Conn.Google Scholar
Thomas, Aquinas (1971b). In duodecim libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis expositio, ed. Cathala, M. R. and Spiazzi, R. M. (2nd edn.), MariettiGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Aquinas (1954d). Sancti Thomae de Aquino super Librum de Causis Expositio, ed. Saffrey, H. D., Société PhilosophiqueGoogle Scholar
Trapé, G. (1964). ‘Il Platonismo di Egidio Romano’, Aquinas 7:.Google Scholar
Trapé, G. (1966). ‘Il Neoplatonismo di Egidio Romano nel commento al “De causis”’, Aquinas 9:.Google Scholar
Trapé, G. (1967). ‘La dottrina della partecipazione in Egidio Romano’, Aquinas 10:.Google Scholar
Trapé, G. (1968). ‘Caratteristiche dell' “esse” partecipato in Egidio Romano’, Lateranum 34:.Google Scholar
Trapé, G. (1969). ‘L' “esse” partecipato e distinzione reale in Egidio Romano’, Aquinas 12:.Google Scholar
Vennebusch, J. (1966). ‘Die Questiones metaphysice tres des Siger von Brabant’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 48:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verbeke, Gérard (1977). ‘Introduction doctrinale’ in Avicenna Latinus: Liber de Philosophia Prima sive Scientia Divina I–IV, E. PeetersGoogle Scholar
Weinberg, Julius R. (1964). A Short History of Medieval Philosophy, Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Weisheipl, James A. (1965a). ‘The Concept of Matter in Fourteenth Century Science’ in McMullin, E. (ed.) The Concept of Matter in Creek and Medieval Philosophy, University of Notre Dame PressGoogle Scholar
Weisheipl, James A. (1976). ‘The Relationship of Medieval Natural Philosophy to Modern Science: The Contribution of Thomas Aquinas to its Understanding’, Manuscripta 20:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
William, Ockham (1483). Quaestiones et decisiones in primum libarum Sententiarum, Urach (1491). Quodlibeta septem, Strasbourg (Reprinted Éditions de la Bibliothèque S.J.Louvain 1962)Google Scholar
William, Ockham (1957b). Expositio super viii libros Physicorum, Prologus in Ockham, William 1957aGoogle Scholar
William, Ockham (1967). Opera theobgica [OT] I: Scriptum in librum primum Sententiarum, Ordinatio, Probgus et Distinctio prima, ed. Gál, G. and Brown, S. in Ockham, William 1967–Google Scholar
William, Ockham (1974a). Opera philosophica [OP] I: Summa logicae, ed. Boehner, P., Gál, G., and Brown, S., in Ockham, William 1967–Google Scholar
Wippel, J. F. (1964). ‘Godfrey of Fontaines and the Real Distinction Between Essence and Existence’, Traditio 20:.Google Scholar
Wippel, J. F. (1973). ‘Commentary on BoethiusDe trinitate' The Thomist 37:Google Scholar
Wippel, J. F. (1974a). ‘The Dating of James of Viterbo–s Quodlibet 1 and Godfrey of Fontaines' Quodlibet VIII’, Augustiniana 24:.Google Scholar
Wippel, J. F. (1974b). ‘Godfrey of Fontaines and Henry of Ghent's Theory of Intentional Distinction Between Essence and Existence’ in Köhler, T. W. (ed.) Sapientiae Procerum Amore. Mélanges Médiévistes offerts à Dom fean-Pierre Müller O.S.B (Studia Anselmiana, 63), HerderGoogle Scholar
Wippel, J. F. (1978). ‘Metaphysics and Separatio According to Thomas Aquinas’, The Review of Metaphysics 31:.Google Scholar
Wippel, J. F. (1979). ‘Aquinas's Route to the Real Distinction: A Note on De ente et essentia’, The Thomist 43:CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolter, A. B. (1946). The Transcendentals and their Function in the Metaphysics of Duns Scotus, The Catholic University of AmericaGoogle Scholar
Wolter, A. B. (1965a). ‘The Ockhamist Critique’ in McMullin, E. (ed.) The Concept of Matter in Greek and Medieval Philosophy, University of Notre Dame PressGoogle Scholar
Wolter, A. B. (1965b). ‘The Formal Distinction’, in Ryan, J. K. and Bonansea, B. M. (eds.) John Duns Scotus, 1265–1065, The Catholic University of AmericaGoogle Scholar
Ypma, E. (1975)– ‘Recherches sur la productivite litteraire de Jacques de Viterbe jusqu'à 1300’, Augustiniana 25:Google Scholar
Zavalloni, R. (1951). Richard de Mediavilla et la controverse sur la pluralité des formes, Éditions de l'lnstitut Supérieur de Philosophic de LouvainGoogle Scholar
Zimmermann, A. (1965). Ontologie oder Metaphysik? Die Diskussion iiber den Gegenstand der Metaphysik im 13. und 14. Jahrhundert, BrillGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×