Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-mp689 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T08:18:13.296Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Addressing Poverty and Climate Change: The Varieties of Social Engagement

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 July 2012

Abstract

In this article I propose to explore two issues. The first concerns what kinds of contributions academics can make to reducing poverty. I argue that academics can contribute in a number of ways, and I seek to spell out the diversity of the options available. I concentrate on four ways in which these contributions might differ.

My second aim is to outline some norms that should inform any academic involvement in activities that seek to reduce poverty. I set out six proposals. These concern: (1) the need to construct coalitions among people with different ethical frameworks; (2) the value of constructing nonideal theory on the basis of our best understanding of an ideal world; (3) the need for integrated analysis that connects antipoverty initiatives to other areas of moral concern; (4) the vital importance of interdisciplinarity; (5) the need for epistemic modesty and revisability; and (6) the need for accountability.

Type
Academics Stand Against Poverty
Copyright
Copyright © Carnegie Council for Ethics in International Affairs 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

NOTES

1 Auden, W. H., “Musée des Beaux Arts,” in Poems, selected by Fuller, John (London: Faber and Faber, 2000 [1938]), p. 29Google Scholar.

2 For similar, but nonidentical, taxonomy of responses to reform, see Hirschman, Albert O., The Rhetoric of Reaction: Perversity, Futility, Jeopardy (Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press, 1991)Google Scholar.

3 See Luis Cabrera and Thomas Pogge, “Academics Stand Against Poverty: An Idea Whose Time Has Come,” in this issue.

4 Solomon, Susan, Qin, Dahe, and Manning, Martin, “Technical Summary,” in Solomon, Susan et al. , eds., Climate Change 2007: The Physical Science Basis—Contribution of Working Group I to the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), p. 70Google Scholar.

5 Hare, Bill, “Relationship Between Increases in Global Mean Temperature and Impacts on Ecosystems, Food Production, Water and Socio-Economic Systems,” in Schellnhuber, Hans Joachim et al. , eds., Avoiding Dangerous Climate Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), p. 179Google Scholar.

7 See Commission of the European Communities, “Winning the Battle Against Global Climate Change” (issued on February 9, 2005), p. 3; eur-lex.europa.eu/LexUriServ/site/en/com/2005/com2005_0035en01.pdf.

8 Rachel Warren, “Impacts of Global Climate Change at Different Annual Mean Global Temperature Increases,” in Schellnhuber et al., p. 95.

10 See Tickell, Oliver, Kyoto 2: How to Manage the Global Greenhouse (London: Zed Books, 2008)Google Scholar; Barnes, Peter, Who Owns the Sky? Our Common Assets and the Future of Capitalism (Washington, D.C.: Island Press, 2001)Google Scholar; and Barnes, Peter et al. , “Creating an Earth Atmospheric Trust,” Science 319, no. 5864 (2008), p. 724CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

11 See Onora O'Neill's contribution to this special issue, where she argues that academics are not a natural kind and thus raises the question of whether a focus on the role of academics is appropriate.

13 One might also include under this heading campaigns to change the policies of economic corporations as well as governments.

14 For a debate surrounding these issues, see Kuper, Andrew, “More Than Charity: Cosmopolitan Alternatives to the ‘Singer Solution,’Ethics & International Affairs 16, no. 1 (2002), pp. 107–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Singer, Peter, “Poverty, Facts, and Political Philosophies: Response to ‘More Than Charity,’Ethics & International Affairs 16, no. 1 (2002), pp. 121–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kuper, Andrew, “Facts, Theories, and Hard Choices: Reply to Peter Singer,” Ethics & International Affairs 16, no. 1 (2002), pp. 125–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Singer, Peter, “Achieving the Best Outcome: Final Rejoinder,” Ethics & International Affairs 16, no. 1 (2002), pp. 127–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15 For examples, see Benkler, Yochai, The Wealth of Networks: How Social Production Transforms Markets and Freedom (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 2006), chap. 9Google Scholar.

16 Anderson, Kym, “Subsidies and Trade Barriers,” in Lomborg, Bjørn, ed., Global Crises, Global Solutions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), pp. 541–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 For information, see www.un-redd.org/.

18 For discussion of these concerns, see Nuffield Council on Bioethics, Biofuels: Ethical Issues (London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics, 2011), chap. 2, esp. pp. 28–41; www.nuffieldbioethics.org/sites/default/files/Biofuels_ethical_issues_FULL%20REPORT_0.pdf. Disclosure: I am one of the members of the working party that produced this report.

19 Ibid., chap. 4, esp. p. 64.

20 See Tobin, James, “A Proposal for International Monetary Reform,” Eastern Economic Journal 4, nos. 3–4 (1978), pp. 153–59Google Scholar.

21 For the work of Thomas Pogge and his associates on the Health Impact Fund, see www.yale.edu/macmillan/igh/. See, in particular, Thomas Pogge, Hollis, Aidan, and Pogge, Thomas, The Health Impact Fund: Making New Medicines Accessible for All (Incentives for Global Health, 2008)Google Scholar; and Pogge, Thomas, Rimmer, Matthew, and Rubenstein, Kim, eds., Incentives for Global Public Health: Patent Law and Access to Essential Medicines (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Kremer, Michael and Glennerster, Rachel, Strong Medicine: Creating Incentives for Pharmaceutical Research of Neglected Diseases (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2004)Google Scholar.

22 See Wenar, Leif, “Property Rights and the Resource Curse,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 36, no. 1 (2008), pp. 232CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See, more generally, the papers at wenar.info/CleanTrade.html.

23 Collier, Paul, The Bottom Billion: Why the Poorest Countries Are Failing and What Can Be Done About It (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007)Google Scholar. See pp. 38–52 for an analysis of the “natural resources trap.”

24 Ibid., pp. 140–41; compare also pp. 142ff. See also Natural Resource Charter, www.naturalresourcecharter.org/.

25 Reddy, Sanjay G. and Pogge, Thomas, “How Not to Count the Poor,” in Anand, Sudhir, Segal, Paul, and Stiglitz, Joseph E., eds., Debates on the Measurement of Global Poverty (New York: Oxford University Press, 2010), pp. 4285CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

26 Parry, Martin et al. , eds., Climate Change 2007: Impacts, Adaptation and Vulnerability—Contribution of Working Group II to the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007)Google Scholar.

27 I have sought to do this in Caney, Simon, “Climate Change, Human Rights and Moral Thresholds,” in Humphreys, Stephen, ed., Human Rights and Climate Change, with a foreword by Mary Robinson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), pp. 6990Google Scholar. See also International Council on Human Rights Policy, Climate Change and Human Rights: A Rough Guide (Versoix, Switzerland: International Council on Human Rights Policy, 2008); www.ichrp.org/files/reports/45/136_report.pdf. Disclosure: I was an advisor for this report.

28 Archer, David, The Long Thaw: How Humans Are Changing the Next 100,000 Years of Earth's Climate (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2009), p. 1Google Scholar.

29 Ramsey, F. P., “A Mathematical Theory of Saving,” Economic Journal 38, no. 152 (1928), pp. 543–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

30 See Stern, Sir Nicholas, The Economics of Climate Change: The Stern Review (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), p. 52CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; and Nordhaus, William, A Question of Balance: Weighing the Options on Global Warming Policies (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 2008), p. 33Google Scholar.

31 For a helpful discussion of η, see Beckerman, Wilfred and Hepburn, Cameron, “Ethics of the Discount Rate in the Stern Review on the Economics of Climate Change,” World Economics 8, no. 1 (2007), pp. 193ffGoogle Scholar.

32 Benkler, The Wealth of Networks, pp. 329–44 (on food security), and pp. 344–53 (on access to medicines).

33 For discussion, see Barnett, Jon and Campbell, John, Change and Small Island States: Power, Knowledge and the South Pacific (London: Earthscan, 2010)Google Scholar.

34 See Singer, Peter, The Life You Can Save: How to Play Your Part in Ending World Poverty (London: Picador, 2009), chap. 6Google Scholar. See also Keith Horton's contribution to this issue for an excellent discussion of the role that academics can play in evaluating the effectiveness of aid programs.

35 See GiveWell at givewell.org/. For Singer's discussion of GiveWell and its founders, see Singer, The Life You Can Save, pp. 81–93. Note also that Giving What We Can recommends charities (www.givingwhatwecan.org/resources/recommended-charities.php) and that it has drawn on GiveWell, among other organizations (www.givingwhatwecan.org/resources/our-methodology.php). For Wenar's critique, see Wenar, Leif, “Poverty Is No Pond: Challenges for the Affluent,” in Illingworth, Patricia, Pogge, Thomas, and Wenar, Leif, Giving Well: The Ethics of Philanthropy (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011), pp. 124–26Google Scholar.

36 On the problems of assessment, see Wenar, Leif, “What We Owe to Distant Others,” Politics, Philosophy and Economics 2, no. 3 (2003), pp. 291–96, esp. pp. 294 and 296Google Scholar; Wenar, Leif, “Accountability in International Development Aid,” Ethics & International Affairs 20, no. 1 (2006), pp. 1820CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Wenar, “Poverty Is No Pond,” pp. 108–23, esp. pp.118–23. For the role that academics might play, see Wenar, “What We Owe to Distant Others,” p. 297; and Wenar, “Poverty Is No Pond,” p. 128. For a different approach, see Wenar, “Accountability in International Development Aid,” pp. 17–23.

37 Buchanan, Allen, “Social Moral Epistemology,” Social Philosophy and Policy 19, no. 2 (2002), p. 126CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed. See also Buchanan, Allen, “Philosophy and Public Policy: A Role for Social Moral Epistemology,” Journal of Applied Philosophy 26, no. 3 (2009), pp. 276–90CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

38 For the latter, see Singer's overview of the beliefs of Americans concerning how much aid they think Americans donate to overseas aid in Singer, The Life You Can Save, pp. 33–35.

39 This is a point that has often been pressed by Onora O'Neill; see, e.g., her critique of accounts that treat rights as basic in O'Neill, Onora, Towards Justice and Virtue: A Constructive Account of Practical Reasoning (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), esp. pp. 128–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

40 My source of information is Pogge, Thomas, “Shue on Rights and Duties,” in Beitz, Charles and Goodin, Robert, eds., Global Basic Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), p. 125, fn11Google Scholar. Pogge cites Alston, Philip and Tomaševski, Katarina, eds., The Right to Food (Dordrecht, Neth.: Martinus Nijhoff, 1984)Google Scholar; and Eide, Asbjorn, Eide, Wenche Barth, Goonatilake, Susantha, and Gussow, Joan, eds., Food as a Human Right (Tokyo: United Nations University, 1984), pp. 169–74Google Scholar.

41 Shue, Henry, Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy, 2nd ed., with a new afterword (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1996), p. 60Google Scholar.

42 See www.business-humanrights.org/media/documents/ruggie/ruggie-guiding-principles-21-mar-2011.pdf. I am grateful to Leif Wenar for drawing my attention to this.

43 For an example, see Academics for Higher Education & Development, www.ahed-upesed.org/.

44 United Nations Development Programme, Human Development Report 2005: International Cooperation at a Crossroads—Aid, Trade and Security in an Unequal World (New York: Oxford University Press, 2005), p. 146Google Scholar.

45 Roberts, J. Timmons and Parks, Bradley C., A Climate of Injustice: Global Inequality, North-South Politics, and Climate Policy (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2007), pp. 1419Google Scholar.

46 For a similar but nonidentical approach, see David Wiens's instructive discussion in “Toward a Pragmatic Moral Theory of State Sovereignty,” Public Reason blog, November 7, 2008; publicreason.net/2008/11/07/ppps-toward-a-pragmatic-moral-theory-of-state-sovereignty/. In contrast to Wiens, I think that decision-making in nonideal circumstances ought to be informed by an understanding of the ideal. See Wiens, David, “Prescribing Institutions Without Ideal Theory,” Journal of Political Philosophy 20, no. 1 (2012), pp. 4570CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

47 See here ASAP's own initiative along the lines I am canvassing (and the fact that it too uses the idea of an overlapping consensus): asap.betaelements.net/projects/the-global-poverty-consensus-report/.

48 Rawls, John, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), p. 144Google Scholar.

49 Ibid., pp. 147–48.

50 Wright, Erik Olin, Envisioning Real Utopias (London: Verso, 2010), p. 273Google Scholar; compare pt. III.

51 My distinction is similar in spirit to G. A. Cohen's distinction between “rules of regulation” and “fundamental principles.” Cohen, G. A., Rescuing Justice and Equality (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2008), pp. 3, 19–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 253–54, 263–72, 276–79, 283, 285–86, and 323–27. But I think the two distinctions are not coextensive. Normative policy-oriented reasoning is focused on specific policies (e.g., the Tobin tax or reducing tariffs), not rules. It operates at a different level of specificity. The difference is apparent when we recall that Cohen maintains that what the parties in Rawls's Original Position would be choosing are “rules of regulation” (and not principles of justice). However plausible this is (and I am sympathetic to Cohen's claims) it is clear that the parties are not selecting specific policies. Rules of regulation are the rules that should govern social life, whereas policies are the means by which to achieve rules of regulation.

52 Clearly my remarks here bear on the recent debates on the value or otherwise of ideal theory and its relationship to nonideal theory. Space precludes defending my position in full. My views on ideal theory are close to those defended by Estlund, David, Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2008)Google Scholar, chap. XIV; Gilabert, Pablo, “Comparative Assessments of Justice, Political Feasibility, and Ideal Theory,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15, no. 1 (2012), pp. 3956CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Stemplowska, Zofia, “What's Ideal About Ideal Theory?Social Theory and Practice 34, no. 3 (2008), pp. 319–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Swift, Adam, “The Value of Philosophy in Nonideal Circumstances,” Social Theory and Practice 34, no. 3 (2008), pp. 363–87CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

53 Simmons, A. John, “Ideal and Nonideal Theory,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 38, no. 1 (2010), pp. 2122CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 25, and 34–35, esp. p. 21; and Gilabert, “Comparative Assessments,” sect. 4.1, p. 14.

54 For the distinction between “difficulty” and “cost,” see Cohen, G. A., Karl Marx's Theory of History: A Defence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978), pp. 238–40Google Scholar.

55 I am greatly indebted to, and draw here on, Arthur, W. Brian, Increasing Returns and Path Dependence in the Economy (Ann Arbor, Mich.: University of Michigan Press, 1994)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Mahoney, James, “Path Dependence in Historical Sociology,” Theory and Society 29, no. 4 (2000), pp. 507–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar; North, Douglass C., Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990), esp. pp. 93100CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Page, Scott E., “Path Dependence,” Quarterly Journal of Political Science 1, no. 1 (2006), pp. 87115CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Pierson, Paul, Politics in Time: History, Institutions, and Social Analysis (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2004), pp. 1753CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

56 Pierson, Politics in Time, pp. 54–78.

57 For a similar point made in a rather different context, see Gilabert, “Comparative Assessments,” p. 48.

58 See Barrett, Scott, Environment and Statecraft: The Strategy of Environmental Treaty-Making (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), p. 222, fn3CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

59 International Council on Human Rights Policy, Beyond Technology Transfer: Protecting Human Rights in a Climate-Constrained World (Versoix, Che.: International Council on Human Rights Policy, 2011)Google Scholar; www.ichrp.org/files/reports/65/138_ichrp_climate_tech_transfer_report.pdf. Disclosure: I wrote a background paper for this report.

60 On the fallibility of experts, see Tetlock, Philip E., Expert Political Judgment: How Good Is It? How Can We Know? (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2005)Google Scholar.

61 See, e.g., the differences in the explanation of global poverty given by Jeff Sachs and those given by others like Daron Acemoglu and James Robinson or by Dani Rodrik. See, e.g., Gallup, John Luke and Sachs, Jeffrey D., “The Economic Burden of Malaria,” American Journal of Tropical Medicine and Hygiene 64, no. 1, supp. (2001), pp. 8596CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Acemoglu, Daron and Robinson, James A., Why Nations Fail: The Origins of Power, Prosperity and Poverty (London: Profile Books, 2012)Google Scholar; and Rodrik, Dani, One Economics, Many Recipes: Globalization, Institutions, and Economic Growth (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2007), pp. 184–92Google Scholar.

62 Kapur, Devesh, “Philanthropy, Self-Interest, and Accountability: American Universities and Developing Countries,” in Illingworth, , Pogge, , and Wenar, , eds., Giving Well, pp. 264–85Google Scholar.

63 Ibid., p. 281.

64 I owe this point to Tim Kruger, who made this suggestion in a different context (geoengineering research). It is embodied in Steve Rayner et al., “Memorandum submitted by Tim Kruger (GEO 07): Draft Principles for the Conduct of Geoengineering Research,” submitted to House of Commons Science and Technology Committee enquiry into “The Regulation of Geoengineering,” para. 19, principle 3; www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/cm200910/cmselect/cmsctech/221/10011315.htm.