Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-hgkh8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-28T17:36:40.535Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Legitimate Authority and the Ethics of War: A Map of the Terrain

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 June 2017

Abstract

Despite a recent explosion of interest in the ethics of armed conflict, the traditional just war criterion that war be waged by a “legitimate authority” has received relatively little attention. Moreover, of those theorists who have addressed the criterion, many are deeply skeptical about its moral significance. This article aims to add some clarity and precision to the authority criterion and the debates surrounding it, and to suggest that this skepticism may be too quick. The first section analyzes the authority criterion and reveals that there are at least two distinct moral claims associated with it, each requiring separate evaluation. The second section outlines an increasingly influential “reductivist” approach to just war theory, explaining how this approach grounds powerful objections to the authority criterion. The third section sketches the most promising strategies for providing a qualified defense of authority, while acknowledging the further questions and complications these strategies raise. Importantly, the article aims to rehabilitate the authority criterion from within a broadly reductivist view.

Type
Special Section: Legitimate Authority, War, and the Ethics of Rebellion
Copyright
Copyright © Carnegie Council for Ethics in International Affairs 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

NOTES

1 See Russell, Frederick, The Just War in the Middle Ages (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977)Google Scholar; and Wilson, Heather, International Law and the Use of Force by National Liberation Movements (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988)Google Scholar, ch. 1.

2 For a detailed list of references, see my “Civil War and Revolution,” in Helen Frowe and Seth Lazar, eds., The Oxford Handbook of Ethics of War (Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming). In addition, see Fabre, Cécile, “Cosmopolitanism, Just War Theory and Legitimate Authority,” International Affairs 84, no. 5 (2008), pp. 963–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Yitzhak Benbaji, “Legitimate Authority in War,” in Frowe and Lazar, Oxford Handbook of Ethics of War; Reitberger, Magnus, “License to Kill: Is Legitimate Authority a Requirement for Just War?International Theory 5, no. 1 (2013), pp. 6493 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Heinze, Eric A. and Steele, Brent J., eds., Ethics, Authority, and War (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Lang, Anthony F. Jr., O'Driscoll, Cian, and Williams, John, eds., Just War: Authority, Tradition, and Practice (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2013)Google Scholar; Blair, Robert and Kalmanovitz, Pablo, “On the Rights of Warlords: Legitimate Authority and Basic Protection in War-Torn Societies,” American Political Science Review 110, no. 3 (2016), pp. 428–40;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Stilz, Anna, “Authority, Self-Determination, and Community in Cosmopolitan War,” Law and Philosophy 33, no. 3 (2014) pp. 309–35;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Steinhoff, Uwe, On the Ethics of War and Terrorism (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), ch. 1CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Kutz, Christopher, On War and Democracy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2016), ch. 3Google Scholar.

3 I defend these claims in much more detail in Parry, Jonathan, “Just War Theory, Legitimate Authority, and Irregular Belligerency,” Philosophia 43, no. 1 (2015), pp. 175–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar. In his contribution to this special section, Pål Wrange argues that, as a matter of international law, the notion of authority in war may in fact be much more diverse than I have suggested.

4 For similar interpretations, see Fabre, Cécile, Cosmopolitan War (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), p. 160CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Finlay, ChristopherLegitimacy and Non-State Political Violence,” Journal of Political Philosophy 18, no. 3 (2010), pp. 287312 Google Scholar; and Reitberger, “License to Kill.” See also Coates, A. J., The Ethics of War (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1997), ch. 5Google Scholar.

5 For a recent endorsement, see Brunstetter, Daniel, “ Jus ad Vim: A Rejoinder to Helen Frowe,” Ethics & International Affairs 30, no. 1 (2016), pp. 131–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 See Reichberg, Gregory M., “The Moral Equality of Combatants – A Doctrine in Classical Just War Theory? A Response to Graham Parsons,” Journal of Military Ethics 12, no. 2 (2013), pp. 181–94CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 As George Fletcher points out, “Until the Statute of Henry VIII, passed in 1532 . . . there was no theory of self-defense that rendered a killing fully lawful, justifiable and therefore free of the taint that affected excusable homicide.” Fletcher, George, “Defensive Force as an Act of Rescue,” Social Philosophy and Policy 7, no. 2 (1990), p. 171CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 For discussion, see, Kutz, On War and Democracy, ch. 3.

9 McMahan, Jeff, Killing in War (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Fabre, Cosmopolitan War; and Frowe, Helen, Defensive Killing (New York: Oxford University Press, 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Draper, Kai, War and Individual Rights (New York: Oxford University Press, 2016)Google Scholar.

10 Here I draw on Lazar, Seth, “National Defence, Self-Defence, and the Problem of Political Aggression,” in Fabre, Cécile and Lazar, Seth, eds., The Morality of Defensive War (New York: Oxford University Press, 2014), pp. 1139 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 Glover, Jonathan, Causing Death and Saving Lives (London: Penguin, 1977), pp. 251–52Google Scholar. For an analogue of the continuity thesis applied to the use of force by state officials outside the context of war, see Gardner, John, “Criminals in Uniform,” in Duff, Anthony, Farmer, Lindsay, Marshall, Sandra, Renzo, Massimo, and Tadros, Victor, eds., The Constitution of the Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), pp. 97118 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

12 Lazar, “National Defence, Self-Defence, and the Problem of Political Aggression,” p. 12.

13 See McMahan, Jeff, “War as Self-Defense,” Ethics & International Affairs 18, no. 1 (2004), pp. 7580 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14 See Nickel, James W., “Griffin on Human Rights to Liberty,” in Crisp, Roger, ed., Griffin on Human Rights (New York: Oxford University Press, 2014), p. 200Google Scholar.

15 See Ferzan, Kimberly, “Self-Defense and the State,” Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law 5, no. 2 (2008), pp. 449504 Google Scholar.

16 McMahan, Jeff, “Just War,” in Goodin, Robert E., Pettit, Philip, and Pogge, Thomas, eds., A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, 2nd Edition (Oxford: Blackwell, 2007), p. 671Google Scholar. For further reductivist rejections of the restrictive authority criterion, see Fabre, Cosmopolitan War, chs. 3–4; McMahan, Jeff, “Just Cause for War,” Ethics & International Affairs 19, no. 3 (2005), pp. 121 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, especially p. 4; and Steinhoff, On the Ethics of War and Terrorism, ch. 1.

17 Fabre, Cosmopolitan War, pp. 144–45. See also Steinhoff, On the Ethics of War and Terrorism, p. 20; Steinhoff, Uwe, “What is War?—And Can a Lone Individual Wage One?International Journal of Applied Philosophy 23, no. 1 (2009), pp. 133–50CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Pattison, James, “When Is It Right to Fight? Just War Theory and the Individual-Centric Approach,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 16, no. 1 (2013), pp. 3454 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, especially p. 53.

18 See McMahan, Killing in War.

19 McMahan, Jeff, “War,” in Estlund, David, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), 298315 Google Scholar, at p. 310 (my emphasis).

20 In a talk given at Stockholm University in May 2014, McMahan explicitly labeled this view the “No Extensions Principle.”

21 Finlay, “Legitimacy and Non-State Political Violence”; Finlay, Christopher, Terrorism and the Right to Resist (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Schwenkenbecher, Anne, “Rethinking Legitimate Authority,” in Allhoff, Fritz, Evans, Nicholas G., and Henschke, Adam, eds., Routledge Handbook of Ethics and War (Abingdon: Routledge, 2013), pp. 161–70Google Scholar; Lazar, Seth, “Authorisation and the Morality of War,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 94, no. 2 (2016), pp. 211–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also McPherson, Lionel K., “Is Terrorism Distinctively Wrong?Ethics 117, no. 3 (2007), pp. 524–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

22 For more detailed discussion, see Fabre, Cécile, “Permissible Rescue Killings,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 109 (2009), pp. 149–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Finlay, “Legitimacy and Non-State Political Violence.”

23 See Goodin, Robert E., “Enfranchising All Affected Interests, and its Alternatives,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 35, no. 1 (2007), pp. 4068 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 See Tesón, Fernando, “The Liberal Case for Humanitarian Intervention,” in Holzgrefe, J. L. and Keohane, Robert O., eds., Humanitarian Intervention: Ethical, Legal, and Political Dilemmas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), pp. 93130 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25 Pattison, James, “Representativeness and Humanitarian Intervention,” Journal of Social Philosophy 38, no. 4 (2007), pp. 569–87CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

26 For further discussion, see Buchanan, Allen, “The Internal Legitimacy of Humanitarian Intervention,” Journal of Political Philosophy 7, no. 1 (1999), pp. 7187 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

27 A similar point might also apply to bystanders: If bystanders have a duty to shoulder a certain level of risk, their objections to the use of force may be discounted.

28 See Brighouse, Harry and Fleurbaey, Marc, “Democracy and Proportionality,” Journal of Political Philosophy 18, no. 32 (2010), pp. 137–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

29 For further discussion, see Benbaji, “Legitimate Authority in War.”

30 Based on a case in Altman, Andrew and Wellman, Christopher Heath, “From Humanitarian Intervention to Assassination: Human Rights and Political Violence,” Ethics 118, no. 2 (2008), pp. 228–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar, especially p. 244.

31 Ibid., p. 243.

32 I explore this particular idea at length in Jonathan Parry, “Consent and the Justification of Defensive Harm” (unpublished manuscript).

33 See Shapiro, Scott, “Authority,” in Coleman, Jules and Shapiro, Scott, eds., The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002), pp. 382439 Google Scholar.

34 The following proposal draws on arguments I defend in much greater detail in Jonathan Parry, “Authority and Harm,” in David Sobel, Peter Vallentyne, and Steven Wall, eds., Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, Vol. 3 (forthcoming). For different arguments for a broadly similar conclusion, see Estlund, David, “On Following Orders in an Unjust War,” Journal of Political Philosophy 15, no. 2 (2007), pp. 213–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ryan, Cheyney, “Democratic Duty and the Moral Dilemmas of Soldiers,” Ethics 122, no. 1 (2011), pp. 1042 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Massimo Renzo, “Duties of Citizenship and Just War” (unpublished manuscript).

35 Smith, Matthew Noah, “Political Obligation and the Self,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 86, no. 2 (2013), p. 349CrossRefGoogle Scholar (my emphasis).

36 Raz, Joseph, The Morality of Freedom (New York: Clarendon Press, 1986), chs. 1–4Google Scholar; Raz, Joseph, Between Authority and Interpretation (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009), ch. 5CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37 For a different invocation of a Razian conception of authority in the context of war, see Benbaji, “Legitimate Authority in War.”

38 Raz, Morality of Freedom, p. 53.

39 Raz, Morality of Freedom, pp. 67–69. The preemptive character of commands can also be defended by an argument from double counting. Ibid., pp. 58–59.

40 Raz, Morality of Freedom, p. 71.

41 See, for example, Green, Leslie, The Authority of the State (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988)Google Scholar; Simmons, A. John, “Political Obligation and Authority,” in Simon, Robert L., ed., The Blackwell Guide to Social and Political Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 2002), pp. 1737;CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Raz, Joseph, The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), ch. 12CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

Supplementary material: File

Parry supplementary material

Online Abstract

Download Parry supplementary material(File)
File 12.4 KB