Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-dnltx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T19:23:40.720Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Subjectivity and Substance

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 April 2015

Terry Pinkard*
Affiliation:
Georgetown Universitypinkard1@georgetown.edu
Get access

Abstract

Among the many developments in philosophy in the last several years has been the relatively recent wave of books and articles, especially in ethics, linking Kantianism with Aristotelianism. Hegelians are not surprised at this turn. For Hegel, there was a kind of logic to the key concepts in Aristotle and Kant that inevitably pushed us from one to the other, and something like that thought is behind his notorious summary statement in the Phenomenology that ‘everything hangs on apprehending and expressing the true not merely as substance but also equally as subject.’ Or as we might alternately put it with a narrower scope, everything about our interpretation of Hegel hangs on what in the world we take Hegel to mean by that assertion. Answering that requires us to take a stand on what constitutes Hegel’s idealism and what constitutes his version of naturalism (even on whether there is such a thing as Hegel’s naturalism at all).

Type
Articles
Copyright
© The Hegel Society of Great Britain 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Farrell, F. B. (1994), Subjectivity, realism, and postmodernism: the recovery of the world. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1969), Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Geschichte. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1969), Wissenschaft der Logik II. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1969), Hegel’s Science of logic. London, New York: Allen & Unwin, Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1969), Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften II. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1975), Lectures on the philosophy of world history: introduction, reason in history. Cambridge, England; New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1991), Elements of the philosophy of right. Cambridge, England; New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (2010), Phenomenology of Spirit. T. Pinkard (trans.).Google Scholar
Kukla, R. and Lance, M. N. (2009), ‘Yo!’ and ‘lo!’: the pragmatic topography of the space of reasons. Cambridge, MA; London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Larmore, C. E. (2012), Vernunft und Subjektivität: Frankfurter Vorlesungen. Berlin: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Locke, J. and Macpherson, C. B. (1980), Second treatise of government. Indianapolis, Ind: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Moore, A. W. (2012), The evolution of modern metaphysics: making sense of things. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. B. (2010), Hegel on Self-Consciousness: Desire and Death in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. (unpublished), ‘In What Sense is Hegel’s Philosophy of Right Based in His Science of Logic? Remarks on the Logic Of Justice’.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. (unpublished), ‘Logic and Metaphysics: Hegel’s “Realm of Shadows”’.Google Scholar
Pinkard, T. P. (1988), Hegel’s dialectic: the explanation of possibility. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Rödl, S. (2007), Self-consciousness. Cambridge, MA; London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1953), Philosophical investigations = Philosophische Untersuchungen. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Wittengenstein, L., Anscombe, G. E. M.et al. (1969), Zettel. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar