Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-skm99 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T01:22:14.965Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Representation, Bicameralism, Political Equality, and Sortition: Reconstituting the Second Chamber as a Randomly Selected Assembly

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 January 2020

Abstract

The two traditional justifications for bicameralism are that a second legislative chamber serves a legislative-review function (enhancing the quality of legislation) and a balancing function (checking concentrated power and protecting minorities). I furnish here a third justification for bicameralism, with one elected chamber and the second selected by lot, as an institutional compromise between contradictory imperatives facing representative democracy: elections are a mechanism of people’s political agency and of accountability, but run counter to political equality and impartiality, and are insufficient for satisfactory responsiveness; sortition is a mechanism for equality and impartiality, and of enhancing responsiveness, but not of people’s political agency or of holding representatives accountable. Whereas the two traditional justifications initially grew out of anti-egalitarian premises (about the need for elite wisdom and to protect the elite few against the many), the justification advanced here is grounded in egalitarian premises about the need to protect state institutions from capture by the powerful few and to treat all subjects as political equals. Reflecting the “political” turn in political theory, I embed this general argument within the institutional context of Canadian parliamentary federalism, arguing that Canada’s Senate ought to be reconstituted as a randomly selected citizen assembly.

Type
Article
Copyright
© American Political Science Association 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

For comments on previous drafts, I am grateful to John Aldrich, Edie Austin, Edana Beauvais, Eric Cheng, Lisa Disch, Kevin Elliot, David Estlund, Evan Fox-Decent, John Gastil, Raf Geenens, Molly Gerver, Emiliano Grossman, Alex Kirchner, Jacob Levy, Peter Loewen, Paul Massicotte, Brianna McGinnis, Andrew Potter, Will Roberts, Geneviève Rousselière, Stefan Rummens, Christa Scholtz, Richard Schultz, Melissa Schwartzberg, Stuart Soroka, Nazmul Sultan, Lori Turnbull, Pierre-Étienne Vandamme, Daniel Weinstock, James Wilson, Yves Winter, Erik Olin Wright; the editor and referees for this journal; and participants at the following conferences and workshops: Representation, Bicameralism, and Sortition, McGill, December 2016; McGill RGCS Faculty Workshop, February 2017; Real Utopias Project workshop, University of Wisconsin, Madison, September 2017; Political Philosophy Workshop, Brown, November 2017; Crisis of Democracy, Yale University, January 2018; Political Theory Workshop, Duke, April 2018; “Political Theory In/ And/ As Political Science,” McGill, May 2018; APSA, September, 2018; Political Theory Workshop, University of Chicago, November 2018; Ottawa Political Thought Research Network, University of Ottawa, December 2018; Public Ethics Talks Series, Leiden University, February 2019; RIPPLE, KU Leuven, March 2019; and Sciences Po Théorie Politique Seminar, March 2019. Dedicated to the memory of Erik Olin Wright.

References

Achen, Christopher and Bartels, Larry. 2016. Democracy for Realists. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ajzenstat, Janet. 2003. “Bicameralism and Canada’s Founders.” In Protecting Canadian Democracy, ed. Montreal, S. Joyal.: McGill–Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Ancell, Aaron. 2017. “Democracy Isn’t that Smart (but We Can Make It Smarter).” Episteme 14(2): 161–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 2004. “Democracy Is Not Intrinsically Just.” In Justice and Democracy, ed. Dowding, K., Goodin, R., and Pateman, C.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 2015. “Equality of Opportunity.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, E.. Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University, Stanford, CA.Google Scholar
Barnett, Anthony and Carty, Peter. 2008. The Athenian Option. Exeter: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
Beitz, Charles. 1989. Political Equality. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Bouricius, Terrill. 2013. “Democracy Through Multi-Body Sortition.” Journal of Public Deliberation 9(1): 119.Google Scholar
Branham, J. Alexander, Soroka, Stuart, and Wlezien, Christopher. 2017. “When Do the Rich Win?Political Science Quarterly 132(1): 4362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brighouse, Harry. 1996. “Egalitarianism and Equal Availability of Political Influence.” Journal of Political Philosophy 4(2): 118–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, John. 1990. “Fairness.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91(1): 87101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 2002. “Political Legitimacy and Democracy.”Ethics 112(4): 689719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callenbach, Ernest and Phillips, Michael. 2008. A Citizen Legislature. Exeter: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
Caplan, Bryan. 2007. The Myth of the Rational Voter. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Carey, John, Niemi, Richard, and Powell, Lynda. 1998. “The Effects of Term Limits on State Legislatures.”Legislative Studies Quarterly 23(2): 271300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carey, John, Niemi, Richard, Powell, Lynda, and Moncrief, Gary. 2006. “The Effects of Term Limits on State Legislatures: A New Survey of the 50 States.” Legislative Studies Quarterly 31(1): 105–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christiano, Thomas. 2008. The Constitution of Equality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cutler, Fred, Johnston, Richard, Carty, R. Kenneth, Blais, André, and Fournier, Patrick. 2008. “Deliberation, Information, and Trust.” In Designing Deliberative Democracy, ed. Warren, M. and Pearse, H.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dahl, Robert. 1979. “Procedural Democracy.” In Philosophy, Politics, & Society (5th Series), ed. Laslett, P. and Fishkin, J.. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Dasgupta, Partha and Maskin, Eric. 1999. “Democracy and Other Goods.” In Democracy’s Value, ed. Shapiro, I. and Hacker-Cordón, C.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Delannoi, Gil, Dowlen, Oliver, and Stone, Peter. 2013. The Lottery as a Democratic Institution . Dublin: Policy Institute.Google Scholar
Disch, Lisa. 2011. “Toward a Mobilization Conception of Democratic Representation.” American Political Science Review 105(1): 100–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dowlen, Oliver. 2008. The Political Potential of Sortition. Exeter: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
Dowlen, Oliver. 2009. “Sorting Out Sortition.” Political Studies 57(2): 298315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downs, Anthony. 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 2000. Sovereign Virtue. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Elliot, Jonathan, ed. 1845. Debates on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution, in the Convention Held at Philadelphia, in 1787. Revised ed. Vol. V, supplementary to Elliot’s Debates. Washington, DC. (https://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/madison-the-debates-on-the-adoption-of-the-federal-constitution-vol-5).Google Scholar
Engelstad, Fredrik. 1989. “The Assignment of Political Office by Lot.” Social Science Information 28(1): 2350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erikson, Robert, MacKuen, Michael, and Stimson, James. 2002. The Macro Polity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 2009. Democratic Authority. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fearon, James. 1999. “Electoral Accountability and the Control of Politicians.” In Democracy, Accountability, and Representation, ed. Przeworski, A., Stokes, S. and Manin, B.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fishkin, James. 2009. When the People Speak. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fournier, Patrick, Kolk, Henk van der, Kenneth Carty, R., Blais, André, and Rose, Jonathan. 2011. When Citizens Decide. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gastil, John and Wright, Erik Olin. 2019. Legislature by Lot. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Gilens, Martin and Page, Benjamin. 2014. “Testing Theories of American Politics.” Perspectives on Politics 12(3): 564–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodin, Robert. 2008. Innovative Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, Jeffrey. 2011. The Eyes of the People. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Guerrero, Alexander. 2014. “Against Elections.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 42(2): 135–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between Facts and Norms. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamilton, Alexander, Jay, John, and Madison, James. 2001. The Federalist , ed. Carey, G. and McClellan, J.. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Headlam, James. 1891. Election by Lot at Athens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Heard, Andrew. 2009. “Assessing Senate Reform through Bill C-19.” In The Democratic Dilemma, ed. Smith, J.. Montreal: McGill–Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Heller, Agnes. 1982. “Habermas and Marxism.” In Habermas, ed. Thompson, J. and Held, D.. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hong, Lu and Page, Scott. 2004. “Groups of Diverse Problem Solvers Can Outperform Groups of High-Ability Problem Solvers.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 101(46): 16385–89.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ingham, Sean. 2016. “Social Choice and Popular Control.” Journal of Theoretical Politics 28(2): 331–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacobs, Lawrence and Shapiro, Robert. 2000. Politicians Don’t Pander. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
James, Michael. 2008. “Descriptive Representation in the British Columbia Citizens’ Assembly.” In Designing Deliberative Democracy, ed. Warren, M. and Pearse, H.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Janis, Irving. 1972. Victims of Groupthink. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Joyal, Serge. 2003. “Conclusion.” In Protecting Canadian Democracy, ed. Montreal, S. Joyal.: McGill–Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Kolodny, Niko. 2014. “Rule Over None I” and “Rule Over None II.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 42(3-4): 195229, 287–336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kousser, Thad. 2005. Term Limits and the Dismantling of State Legislative Professionalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kuehn, Daniel. 2017. “Diversity, Ability, and Democracy.” Critical Review 29(1): 7287.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Landemore, Hélène. 2012. Democratic Reason. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Le Breton, M. 1987. “On the Core of Voting Games.” Social Choice and Welfare 4: 295305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leydet, Dominique. 2019. “Which Conception of Political Equality Do Deliberative Mini-publics Promote?European Journal of Political Theory 18(3): 349–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lupia, Arthur and McCubbins, Mathew. 1998. The Democratic Dilemma . New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
MacKenzie, Michael. 2016. “A General-Purpose, Randomly Selected Chamber.” In Institutions for Future Generations, ed. González-Ricoy, I. and Gosseries, A.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Manin, Bernard. 1997. The Principles of Representative Government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manin, Bernard, Przeworski, Adam, and Stokes, Susan. 1999. “Elections and Representation.” In Democracy, Accountability, and Representation, ed. Przeworski, A., Stokes, S. and Manin, B.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mansbridge, Jane. 2003. “Rethinking Representation.” American Political Science Review 97(4): 515–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markell, Patchen. 2008. “The Insufficiency of Non-Domination.” Political Theory 36(1): 936.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayhew, David. 2004. Congress. 2nd ed. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
McCormick, John. 2006. “Contain the Wealthy and Patrol the Magistrates.” American Political Science Review 100(02): 147–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKelvey, Richard and Schofield, Norman. 1987. “Generalized Symmetry Conditions at a Core Point.” Econometrica 55(4): 923–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKelvey, Richard and Wendell, Richard. 1976. “Voting Equilibria in Multidimensional Choice Spaces.” Mathematics of Operations Research 1(2): 144–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mendelberg, Tali. 2002. “The Deliberative Citizen.” In Political Decision Making, Deliberation and Participation, ed. Delli Carpini, M., Huddy, L., and Shapiro, R.. Bingley: Emerald.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 1977. Considerations on Representative Government . In The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, J.. 33 vols. Vol. 19. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Miller, Susan, Nicholson-Crotty, Jill, and Nicholson-Crotty, Sean. 2011. “Reexamining the Institutional Effects of Term Limits in U.S. State Legislatures.” Legislative Studies Quarterly 36(1): 7197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mooney, Christopher. 2007. “Lobbyists and Interest Groups.” In Institutional Change in American Politics, ed. Kurtz, K., Cain, B. and Niemi, R.. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Mueller, Dennis, Tollison, Robert, and Willett, Thomas. 1972. “Representative Democracy via Random Selection.” Public Choice 12: 5768.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mulgan, Richard. 1984. “Lot as a Democratic Device of Selection.” Review of Politics 46(04): 539–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mulgan, Richard. 2003. Holding Power to Account. Houndmills: Palgrave.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murray, Lowell. 2003. “Which Criticisms Are Founded?” In Protecting Canadian Democracy, ed. Montreal, S. Joyal.: McGill–Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Neblo, Michael, Esterling, Kevin, and Lazer, David. 2018. Politics with the People. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ober, Josiah. 2007. “Natural Capacities and Democracy as a Good-in-itself.” Philosophical Studies 132(1): 5973.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Leary, Kevin. 2006. Saving Democracy. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Owen, David and Smith, Graham. 2019. “Sortition, Rotation, and Mandate.” In Legislature by Lot, ed. Gastil, J. and Wright, E.. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Page, Benjamin and Shapiro, Robert. 1992. The Rational Public. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Page, Scott. 2007. The Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 2012. On the People’s Terms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pitkin, Hanna. 1967. The Concept of Representation. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plott, Charles. 1967. “A Notion of Equilibrium and Its Possibility Under Majority Rule.” American Economic Review 57(4): 787806.Google Scholar
Pluchino, Alessandro, Garofalo, Cesare, Rapisarda, Andrea, Spagano, Salvatore, and Caserta, Maurizio. 2011. “Accidental Politicians.” Physica A 390(21): 3944–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pourtois, Hervé. 2016. “Les élections sont-elles essentielles à la démocratie?Philosophiques 43(2): 411–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Powell, Richard. 2007. “Executive-Legislative Relations.” In Institutional Change in American Politics, ed. Kurtz, K., Cain, B., and Niemi, R.. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Proksch, Sven-Oliver and Slapin, Jonathan. 2015. The Politics of Parliamentary Debate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Przeworski, Adam. 1999. “Minimalist Conception of Democracy.” In Democracy’s Value, ed. Shapiro, I. and Hacker-Cordón, C.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice. Rev. ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rémillard, Gil. 2003. “Senate Reform.” In Protecting Canadian Democracy, ed. Montreal, S. Joyal.: McGill–Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Richardson, Lilliard, Valentine, David, and Stokes, Shannon. 2005. “Assessing the Impact of Term Limits in Missouri.” State & Local Government Review 37(3): 177–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Riker, William. 1980. Liberalism Against Populism. Long Grove, IL: Waveland Press.Google Scholar
Schofield, Norman. 1983. “Generic Instability of Majority Rule.” Review of Economic Studies 50(4): 695705.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwartzberg, Melissa. 2014. Counting the Many. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1999. “Democracy as a Universal Value.” Journal of Democracy 10(3): 317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simmons, A. John. 1979. Moral Principles and Political Obligation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Simmons, A. John. 2001. Justification and Legitimacy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Singer, Peter. 1974. Democracy & Disobedience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, David. 2003. The Canadian Senate in Bicameral Perspective. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Somin, Ilya. 2013. Democracy and Political Ignorance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Soroka, Stuart and Wlezien, Christopher. 2010. Degrees of Democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Soroka, Stuart, Penner, Erin, and Blidook, Kelly. 2009. “Constituency Influence in Parliament.” Canadian Journal of Political Science 42(3): 563–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steiner, Jürg. 2012. The Foundations of Deliberative Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stilborn, Jack. 2003. “Forty Years of Not Reforming the Senate.” In Protecting Canadian Democracy, ed. Montreal, S. Joyal.: McGill–Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Still, Jonathan. 1981. “Political Equality and Election Systems.” Ethics 91(3): 375–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stone, Peter. 2011. The Luck of the Draw. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan, John and Uslaner, Eric. 1978. “Congressional Behavior and Electoral Marginality.” American Journal of Political Science 22(3): 536–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sunstein, Cass. 2006. Infotopia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sutherland, Keith. 2008. A People’s Parliament. Exeter: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
Thomas, Paul. 2003. “Comparing the Lawmaking Roles of the Senate and the House of Commons.” In Protecting Canadian Democracy, ed. Montreal, S. Joyal.: McGill–Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Thomas, Paul. 2019. Moving Toward a New and Improved Senate. IRPP Study vol. 70. Montreal: Institute for Research on Public Policy.Google Scholar
Thompson, Abigail. 2014. “Does Diversity Trump Ability?Notices of the American Mathematical Society 61(9): 1024–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tsebelis, George and Money, Jeannette. 1997. Bicameralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Uhr, John. 2006. “Bicameralism.” In The Oxford Handbook of Political Institutions, ed. Rhodes, R., Binder, S., and Rockman, B.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Urbinati, Nadia. 2006. Representative Democracy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vandamme, Pierre-Etienne and Verret-Hamelin, Antoine. 2017. “A Randomly Selected Chamber.” Journal of Public Deliberation 13(1): Article 5. (https://www.publicdeliberation.net/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1507&context=jpd).Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 1999. Law and Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 2016. Political Political Theory. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1970. Obligations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Watts, Ronald. 2003. “Bicameralism in Federal Parliamentary Systems.” In Protecting Canadian Democracy, ed. Montreal, S. Joyal.: McGill–Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1964. “The Idea of Equality.” In Philosophy, Politics and Society (Second Series), ed. Laslett, P. and Runciman, W.. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Young, Iris Marion. 1987. “Impartiality and the Civic Public.” In Feminism as Critique, ed. Benhabib, S. and Cornell, D.. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Young, Iris Marion. 1990. Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Zakaras, Alex. 2010. “Lot and Democratic Representation.” Constellations 17(3): 455–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar