Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c4f8m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T06:34:41.181Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Autonomous weapons systems and changing norms in international relations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 February 2018

Ingvild Bode*
Affiliation:
Lecturer, School of Politics and International Relations, University of Kent
Hendrik Huelss*
Affiliation:
Postdoctoral Researcher, School of Politics and International Relations, University of Kent
*
*Correspondence to: Ingvild Bode, School of Politics and International Relations, Rutherford College, University of Kent, Canterbury, CT2 7NX, UK. Author’s email: i.b.bode@kent.ac.uk
**Correspondence to: Hendrik Huelss, School of Politics and International Relations, Rutherford College, University of Kent, Canterbury, CT2 7NX, UK. Author’s email: h.c.huelss@kent.ac.uk
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Autonomous weapons systems (AWS) are emerging as key technologies of future warfare. So far, academic debate concentrates on the legal-ethical implications of AWS but these do not capture how AWS may shape norms through defining diverging standards of appropriateness in practice. In discussing AWS, the article formulates two critiques on constructivist models of norm emergence: first, constructivist approaches privilege the deliberative over the practical emergence of norms; and second, they overemphasise fundamental norms rather than also accounting for procedural norms, which we introduce in this article. Elaborating on these critiques allows us to respond to a significant gap in research: we examine how standards of procedural appropriateness emerging in the development and usage of AWS often contradict fundamental norms and public legitimacy expectations. Normative content may therefore be shaped procedurally, challenging conventional understandings of how norms are constructed and considered as relevant in International Relations. In this, we outline the contours of a research programme on the relationship of norms and AWS, arguing that AWS can have fundamental normative consequences by setting novel standards of appropriate action in international security policy.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted reuse, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© British International Studies Association 2018

Introduction

There is a danger that time is running out – is debate and development of policy even still possible, or is the technological genie already out of the ethical bottle, embarking us all on an incremental and involuntary journey towards a Terminator-like reality.Footnote 1

In the shadow of drone warfare, the autonomy of weapons systems is accelerating largely outside of public and academic attention in the discipline of International Relations (IR).Footnote 2 The US Department of Defense’s ‘Unmanned Systems Integrated Roadmap 2013–2038’ sets out a concrete plan to develop and deploy weapons with ever-increasing autonomy in the air, on land, and at sea in the next twenty years. A defining feature of these autonomous weapons systems (AWS) is precisely their ability to operate autonomously: ‘robotic weapons …, once activated, can select and engage targets without further human intervention’.Footnote 3

Most modern weapons systems are computer-assisted and the tasks assigned to these programmes are ever increasing. Yet the autonomous quality of weapons systems typically refers to their ability to ‘think’ and ‘make decisions’ in the broad, technical sense. This ability is the basis for searching and identifying targets within a set of preprogrammed parameters based on sensor input. While AWS currently in development or use are comparatively ‘stupid from an AI [artificial intelligence] perspective’, fast-moving advances in AI research are very likely to filter into weapons systems.Footnote 4 The robotics industry, supported by states such as the US, the UK, China, South Korea, and Russia, therefore continues developing dual-use technology and more autonomous weapons systems, meaning that their deployment could become a practical fait accompli in the near future. Notwithstanding their future level of technological sophistication, ‘stupid’ autonomous weapons systems clearly require (analytical) attention now.Footnote 5

In principle, a dense network of domestic and international structures, both legal and normative, governs the use of such security instruments. These legal structures provide standards of how and when the deployment of different types of weapons is lawful. International law, enshrined in the United Nations (UN) Charter and various treaties of international humanitarian and human rights law, sets rules for what kinds of weapons are prohibited (for example, nuclear, biological, and chemical weapons, cluster bombs), when the use of force is legal, and how weapons ought to be used. The normative structure comprises domestic and internationally accepted norms, understood as standards of appropriateness in this article, as well as values and ethical concerns, including the question of what is ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ in warfare.Footnote 6

In theoretical terms, law and norms co-constitute each other but are not identical. This point is largely neglected by research that prioritises the regulative qualities of constitutional norms, focusing on whether state practices comply with legal standards that are equated with norms in IR.Footnote 7 The academic debate on AWS illustrates this conventional focus: the deployment and emergence of weapons systems is assessed against existing legal standards and further options for regulation are sounded.Footnote 8 However, the literature fails to consider that practices related to the development, testing, training, or usage of AWS outpace public, governmental, and legal considerations. As we argue, AWS may shape norms in practice by privileging procedural norms that are detached from deliberative processes.Footnote 9 We get to this process by asking: what are the implications of developing and deploying AWS for international norms?

In answering this question, we criticise constructivist norm-emergence models via practice theories in two ways. First, we suggest that norms do not only emerge in deliberative processes, but also in practices. Models of norm emergence and change associated with both the second (late 1990s)Footnote 10 and the third (mid-2000s)Footnote 11 waves of constructivism focus almost exclusively on deliberative processes: norms are the outcome of open, public debate. Constructivist scholars have examined how technologies such as nuclear weapons have eventually triggered the creation of new, fundamental norms after lengthy processes of deliberation and negotiation.Footnote 12 In contrast, we are interested in how norms and associated normative content may emerge in practices, understood as patterned actions in social context.Footnote 13 In our case, these are practices of developing, training, testing, and deploying autonomous weapons systems. In accentuating the constitutive quality of practices as sites of norm emergence and change, we depart from the focus on the regulative qualities of norms prevalent in studies of AWS. Focusing on practices surrounding AWS therefore goes beyond examining how they are governed by norms towards how they create, shape, and define norms.

Second, studying practices necessitates broadening our understanding of which norms are relevant in International Relations. Constructivist research has concentrated on ‘fundamental norms’Footnote 14 such as human rights or non-proliferation, defining standards of legal-public appropriateness.Footnote 15 But a different type of norm may emerge in practices: procedural norms defined as standards of procedural-organisational appropriateness, such as efficiency. The difference between fundamental and procedural norms amounts to whether promoted actions are morally right or functionally suitable. Examining practices around AWS can therefore capture an analytically interesting interplay of procedural and fundamental norms. In this process, procedural norms may affect the content of fundamental norms by either filling them with diverging substance or by pushing forward novel standards of appropriateness that might become dominant as the ‘right’ way of doing things.

In arguing these points, the contribution of this article is threefold: first, it outlines the contours of a new research agenda on the relationship of norms and AWS. Second, it establishes critical connections between practice theories and constructivist research on norm emergence. Third, in conceptualising how AWS may create and challenge norms, it also contributes to the debate on whether they should be pre-emptively banned.Footnote 16 Regardless of the difficulties associated with finding an international, deliberative consensus on defining autonomy, this article shows that the current multitude of practices in developing, testing, and using AWS creates de facto standards of what counts as appropriate.Footnote 17 As this happens outside the public purview, it should be very closely monitored – in particular as it may make the process of agreeing on new binding legal regulation more challenging.

The remainder of the article is structured as follows: a first section presents an overview of the development and deployment of AWS. This justifies why AWS should be examined at this point in time and prepares the ground for analysing the emergence of norms in practices. A second section outlines the current state of research on AWS and its implications for what we aim to achieve. In a third section, we cover our theoretical model on how procedural norms may emerge in practice in more detail. A fourth section discusses how AWS could influence an understanding of procedural-organisational appropriateness that diffuses to the legal-public dimension. We conclude that AWS can have fundamental normative consequences by setting novel standards of appropriate action in international relations and international security policy.

The emergence of autonomous security technologies

The defining aspect of AWS is their varying degree of autonomy – ultimately, independent ‘agency’. On a spectrum comprising a simple reactive mechanism at one end and human intelligence at the other end, AWS are gradually moving towards the latter.Footnote 18 In this sense, AWS are defined as ‘systems that, once activated, can track, identify and attack targets with violent force without further human intervention’.Footnote 19 Hence, AWS qualitatively surpass remote-controlled systems, such as drones, that are currently important security technologies.

How to define the autonomy of weapons systems is a matter of debate in two main ways. First, some scholars refine the conceptual understanding of autonomy by, for example, outlining its characteristic aspects such as independence, cognitive skills, and cognitive architecture.Footnote 20 Heather Roff connects autonomy directly to four functions of weapons systems (trigger, targeting, navigation, mobility), allowing her to evaluate the extent to which weapons operate autonomously to different degrees.Footnote 21 In discussing autonomy, scholars emphasise that it should not be equated with human intelligence or ‘free will’, given the distinct nature of robot decision-making.Footnote 22 A second group of scholars debates levels of appropriate human supervisory control, focusing on human-machine interaction and the extent to which machine autonomy undermines human autonomy.Footnote 23 Here, scholarship worries about the human role moving further and further away from immediate decision-making processes on the use of force, a concern underlined by the prominent image of the control ‘loop’. While humans are still ‘in the loop’, in manual control, with regard to drones, in the context of more autonomous systems, humans are projected to first become ‘on the loop’, only overseeing operations and having the formal ability to override machine’s decision, to eventually ‘out of the loop’, being completely absent from operating systems.Footnote 24 The control loop image has been criticised for offering ‘a crude distinction’, because decision-making can be both immediate, that is, in an individual targeting situation, or a wider concept, that is, associated with programming.Footnote 25

However, where decisions are taking place may be less decisive than what kind of control will be exercised. Humans will most likely keep elements of control and oversight in future targeting decisions of AWS, but will this control be formal rather than meaningful? Even meaningful human control,Footnote 26 a concept that has gained currency in the debate on AWS, can indicate very different things. Noel Sharkey’s five levels of human supervisory control, for example, range from humans deliberating about specific targets before initiating an attack, via humans choosing from a list of targets suggested by a program, to programs selecting targets and allocating humans a time-restricted veto.Footnote 27 The content of meaningful human control as well as the extent to which human decision-making will be replaced or pushed back to the programming stage is debatable and will arguably emerge in practice.

While we do not aim at predicting in what ways AWS will operate in the future and how human-machine interaction will be designed, we maintain that AWS represent qualitatively different weapons systems characterised by the emergence of non-human agency. To quote former UN Special Rapporteur Christof Heyns, a key agenda-setter for the topic at the UN:

their [AWS] deployment would entail not merely an upgrade of the kinds of weapons used, but also a change in the identity of those who use them. With the contemplation of LARs [lethal autonomous robotics], the distinction between weapons and warriors risks becoming blurred, as the former would take autonomous decisions about their own use.Footnote 28

The most controversial issue is the possibility that machines may make and execute the decision to end human life autonomously with severe effects on human dignity, a human right at the heart of contemporary international legal architecture.Footnote 29 This is a crucial, qualitatively different feature of AWS in comparison to drones, for instance. Pressure to remove human decision-making in an immediate sense from target engagement and selection will potentially increase as the speed to which AWS are able to process information and execute actions autonomously grows and begins to represent an operational advantage, compared to the ‘slow’ response time of humans.Footnote 30

The deployment of AWS is not a scenario for the distant future. AWS are currently developed, tested, and deployed by the United States, China, Israel, South Korea, and Russia, to name some key actors.Footnote 31 Since 2013, the international community is discussing AWS under the framework of the UN Convention on Certain Conventional Weapons (CCW). State parties to the CCW have held three informal meetings of experts since 2014. After little initial progress, the state parties agreed to formalise deliberations on AWS by creating a Group of Governmental Experts (GGE) in December 2016. While the GGE only has a discussion mandate, similar mechanisms have in the past eventually led to regulation agreements. Chaired by India, the Group has met for the first time in mid-November 2017, witnessing growing support among the CCW contracting parties for a ‘legally-binding instrument on fully autonomous weapons’.Footnote 32 As of November 2017, 22 countries called for a pre-emptive legal ban on AWS, a group that does not include any of the major actors developing such technologies.Footnote 33 During the CCW’s fifth Review Conference in 2016, China released its first position on AWS, declaring that ‘China supports the development of a legally binding protocol on issues related to the use of AWS, similar to the Protocol on Blinding Laser Weapons, to fill the legal gap in this regard.’Footnote 34 The reference to this Protocol is interesting as it instituted a pre-emptive ban. At the same time, China has not defined AWS, making it difficult to assess the specificity of its position.

This is characteristic of discussions at the CCW, which are hampered by diverging viewpoints on autonomy and the resulting lack of a conceptual consensus on AWS. While some member states lack even a working definition, those put forward by, for example, the US and the UK differ significantly. The US defines an AWS as ‘a weapon that, once activated, can select and engage targets without further intervention by a human operator’Footnote 35 in Department of Defense (DoD) Directive 3000.09 that will be discussed further below. The Directive also includes a contested distinction between so-called semi-autonomous and autonomous weapons: semi-autonomous weapons can ‘employ autonomy’ for a full range of ‘engagement-related functions’ for ‘individual targets or specific target groups that have been selected by a human operator’.Footnote 36 The utility of this distinction is contested as target selection, under-defined in the Directive, becomes the only marker to distinguish semi-autonomous from autonomous weapons systems,Footnote 37 making it ‘a distinction without difference’.Footnote 38

The UK differentiates between an ‘automated’ and an ‘autonomous system’: ‘an automated or automatic system is one that, in response to inputs from one or more sensors, is programmed to logically follow a predefined set of rules in order to provide an outcome. Knowing the set of rules under which it is operating means that its output is predictable.’Footnote 39 In contrast, an autonomous system is defined as

capable of understanding higher-level intent and direction. From this understanding and its perception of its environment, such a system is able to take appropriate action to bring about a desired state. It is capable of deciding a course of action, from a number of alternatives, without depending on human oversight and control, although these may still be present. Although the overall activity of an autonomous unmanned aircraft will be predictable, individual actions may not be.Footnote 40

This definition of autonomous systems departs distinctly from an earlier UK definitionFootnote 41 in including the qualifiers ‘higher-level intent and direction’, thereby arguably ‘defining away’ the challenges associated with short-term AWS.

Domestically, the US Directive 3000.09 ‘lays out guidelines for the development and use of autonomous and semi-autonomous weapon systems’.Footnote 42 The Campaign to Stop Killer Robots, an international NGO coalition advocating for a pre-emptive ban, has welcomed Directive 3000.09 because it represents the first national policy on AWS.Footnote 43 Human Rights Watch has even characterised the policy as ‘the world’s first moratorium on lethal fully autonomous weapons’ due to the its attached ten-year expiration date and the restrictions on what it defines as AWS to use lethal force.Footnote 44

However, as Mark Gubrud points out, this is a misreading:Footnote 45 first, with reference to a DoD spokesperson, ‘the 10-year expiration date is routine for such directives’ rather than representing a moratorium.Footnote 46 Second, Directive 3000.09 also outlines ways of waiving even the restrictions it places on the lethal use of AWS.Footnote 47 It further explicitly notes that widely defined ‘semi-autonomous weapons systems … may be used to apply lethal or non-lethal, kinetic or non-kinetic force’.Footnote 48 Therefore, Directive 3000.09 ‘signals to developers and vendors that the Pentagon is serious about AWS’.Footnote 49 Further, codifying that ‘[a]utonomous and semi-autonomous weapon systems shall be designed to allow commanders and operators to exercise appropriate levels of human judgment over the use of force’ will be ‘ineffective and irrelevant’ with regard to technological advances and operational demands potentially leading to the emergence of fully autonomous weapons systems.Footnote 50

Considering the various research programmes, initiatives, and tests that show to what extent AWS are developed, tested, and already in use, it becomes clear that the emergence of legal regulations lags behind, which increases the importance of moving beyond a legal perspective and considering how norms may emerge in practice.

AWS in action

Although fully autonomous weapons systems, that is, systems with independent target selection, are not yet operational, their research and development is constantly proceeding. AWS can take many different forms, from singular entities to swarms, and they can operate on land, in air, and at sea. Many existing weapons platforms are arguably only a software update away from increasing autonomy. To give a few examples of current systems, in December 2016, the US Office of Naval research released a statement that autonomous unmanned swarming boats successfully performed a testing exercise, noting that

unmanned boats were given a large area of open water to patrol. As an unknown vessel entered the area, the group of swarmboats collaboratively determined which patrol boat would quickly approach the unknown vessel, classify it as harmless or suspicious, and communicate with other swarmboats to assist in tracking and trailing the unknown vessel while others continued to patrol the area.Footnote 51

In January 2017, the US DoD announced the successful test of a large micro-drone swarm in air, consisting of 103 ‘Perdix’ drones: ‘[t]he micro-drones demonstrated advanced swarm behaviors such as collective decision-making, adaptive formation flying, and self-healing.’Footnote 52 In this context, then US Secretary of Defense Ash Carter remarked that ‘[t]his is the kind of cutting-edge innovation that will keep us a step ahead of our adversaries. This demonstration will advance our development of autonomous systems.’Footnote 53 These examples demonstrate that swarms of ‘smaller and smarter … systems would be able to make decisions and coordinate themselves without constant human supervision – perhaps without any contact at all’.Footnote 54

While the above systems are so far mainly designed for defensive, surveillance, or reconnaissance purposes, developments also move towards offensive systems. The US Navy is further developing a submarine-hunting drone ship, the Sea Hunter, which has become operational in late 2016. While the Sea Hunter is still remotely controlled,

the progress of the platform’s technology, and the rapid advancements of algorithms enabling greater levels of autonomy, have inspired the Navy to begin thinking about additional missions … so that it can conduct surface warfare missions, fire weapons and launch electronic attacks.Footnote 55

Developments are not confined to the US. In the 2000s, Israel has developed the Israel Aerospace Industries (IAI) HAROP, a loitering munition that has so far been operated by Israel, India, and Azerbaijan. The IAI note that ‘HAROP searches, finds, identifies, attacks and destroys targets, and performs battle damage assessment’ as an ‘autonomous platform operation’.Footnote 56 HAROP is therefore able to engage targets autonomously and to destroy them via a self-destructing attack. According to media sources, Azerbaijan used HAROP for a deadly attack on a bus during the Nagorno-Karabakh conflict in April 2016.Footnote 57

These examples also point to an important, shared characteristic of these weapons systems: they have different modes of operation, enabling switching between different modes at the interstice of automation and autonomy. South Korea’s SGR-A1, a stationary sentry robot developed in the 2000s that has been used at the Korean Demilitarized Zone, illustrates this observation. As it is equipped with heat and motion sensors and an auto-firing system,Footnote 58 the system can theoretically detect, select, and engage a human target without human intervention. However, to what extent the SGR-A1 could be easily switched to and operated at an autonomous mode remains unclear. Table 1 provides an overview of some current weapons systems that operate without direct human intervention.Footnote 59

Table 1 Sample AWS in development or operation.

Researching AWS: Questions of law and ethics

So far, research has explored AWS alongside two main, often interconnected lines: their (potential) legality and ethical challenges attached to their usage. We summarise these studies first before commenting on gaps in this literature.

First, studies of legality examine the extent to which AWS can or could potentially comply with international (humanitarian and human rights) law. General jus in bello principles governing the use of force, such as distinction, proportionality, and accountability, raise important concerns regarding the implications of increasing autonomy for complex aspects. Scholarly opinion about proportionality differs: while some regard AWS as potentially more precise weapons decreasing human suffering,Footnote 60 as underlined by the benefits of ‘precision-guided homing munitions such as torpedoes’,Footnote 61 others argue that AWS increase the recourse to violent instruments, affecting proportionality negatively and making escalations more likely.Footnote 62 A decision about the proportional use of force requires assessing and processing complex data that might be based on contradictory signals if measured against a preprogrammed set of criteria-action sequences characteristic of autonomous ‘decision-making’. Critics of AWS also point to their inability of meeting requirements of distinction – that is differentiating between civilians and combatants and therefore unlawful and lawful targets in complex environments.Footnote 63 Whether a vehicle is used for combat purposes or not, whether an armed individual is a fighter or a civilian, or whether a group comprising some armed individuals also comprises civilians, are questions of human judgement requiring highly complex reflection processes that pose fundamental challenges for deploying AWS.Footnote 64

With regard to accountability, legitimacy is often linked to public demands of individual and political responsibility when force is used, particularly in cases that challenge norms of humanitarian law.Footnote 65 The increasing autonomy of weapons systems raises the question to what extent different groups of individuals, engineers and programmers, political decision-makers, or military command and operating staff, are accountable for ‘decisions’ undertaken and mistakes committed by AWS.Footnote 66 The less specific aspect of legitimacy through political-democratic accountability concerns the involvement of democratic institutions, such as parliaments, in the control of developing and deploying AWS. The question is whether existing procedures and rules for parliamentary oversight are adequate in future scenarios of large-scale AWS deployment.

Second, ethical studies cover a range of challenges associated with the potential deployment of AWS, centering on the question whether autonomous weapons can ever legitimately end human life.Footnote 67 Many call for a comprehensive ban of AWS due to ethical issues and concerns for human dignity,Footnote 68 while some emphasise the potential of AWS to contribute to a more ‘humane’ warfare as autonomous weapons would not be governed by emotions such as fear, hate, and revenge.Footnote 69 Essentialising AWS as benevolent instruments often comes with highly futuristic scenarios distinct from near-term advances in AI and tends to neglect that even autonomous systems are only as good as the purpose or intentions they are meant to serve.

Contributions in the field are rich and growing but there are two important gaps: first, debates on the legality of AWS and ethical challenges attached to their usage both operate with a fixed, predefined understanding of what is right and appropriate. However, arguably, the defining feature of AWS is their developing and changing characteristics. In this regard, we require a theoretical perspective that accommodates the constitutive qualities of AWS as emerging technologies. We therefore present viewpoints on the flexible constitutions of appropriateness that come along with considering how AWS work through practices.

As is the case with all developing weapons technologies, there is no specific regulation in international law regarding the use of AWS. Further, while remote-controlled weapons such as drones have been used extensively by the US, their usage also remains largely unregulated. States continue to operate drones in a grey zone of international law because drone warfare arguably violates the principles of distinction and proportionality and is not yet covered by specific legal regulations.Footnote 70 Currently, the deployment of AWS remains legally permissible with the added uncertainty that their technological autonomy is unaccounted for.

The most problematic aspect of the legal perspective on AWS is their elusive character. Any type of regulation requires looking towards the future in defining technologies that are constantly evolving. In other words, the technical complexity, the dual-use character, and the variety of deployment scenarios makes it challenging to formulate legal restrictions on technological developments: ‘History works against preventive norm making. States usually react, as technological developments usually outpace political agreements to tackle future potential problems.’Footnote 71

Yet, standards of appropriateness regarding the usage of AWS are already emerging. First, the increasing recourse to drones in the US’s approach to the use of forceFootnote 72 has led to the emergence of practices in the sense of routine ways of ‘how things are done’. These are far from meeting the requirements of customary international law: they do not indicate ‘dense’ (behavioural or verbal) state practice, nor do they exhibit opinio juris, ‘a belief that such practice is required … or allowed as a matter of law’.Footnote 73 Yet, these practices create a status quo that makes it more difficult to challenge the further proliferation and usage of drones. In addition, only a very small number of states deploy or develop the most advanced (precursors to) AWS. This means that the emergence of customary law is even more restrained, despite the existence of practical precedents. The use and spread of the ‘unwilling or unable’ formula by the US as a ‘test’ to inform drone targeting decisions is a case in point.Footnote 74

Accordingly, discussing this issue in the context of (customary) international law does not provide an adequate framework because it does not allow researchers to capture emerging standards of appropriateness attached to AWS. In contrast to considering how norms prevent or regulate, our article therefore studies how norms may emerge outside of deliberative forums and the framework of international law making.

Second, the widely unaccounted development of AWS has impeded deep public discourse on this issue. There has been media attention and civil society organisations or campaigns such as Article 36, the Campaign to Stop Killer Robots, or the International Committee for Robot Arms Control (ICRAC) seek to raise the issue’s profile. But the wider political discourse is not particularly concerned with the most fundamental questions and realities of AWS. Technological advances in this area are often incremental and come with a low political profile. Hence, the important role public acceptance plays in debating and creating dominant understandings of appropriateness is lacking.

Building on this role of the public, the (lacking) discussion on developing AWS should also be seen in the context of overall lowering use of force standards when countering terrorism.Footnote 75 Military efficiency and effectiveness as the main arguments for why drone warfare is appropriate have turned into a public legitimacy source.Footnote 76 The promise of ‘surgical’ strikes and the protection of US troops has turned drones into the most ‘appropriate’ security instrument to counter terrorism abroad. The argument that AWS are ‘considered especially suitable for the casualty-averse risk-transfer war that democracies prefer’Footnote 77 points to the important role AWS may play in democratic systems because they make the use of force appear more legitimate. In the case of drones, their broad acceptance across the military and political-public sphere marginalises their contested legal role. A poll conducted in 2013 showed that 75 per cent of American voters approved drone strikes ‘on people and other targets deemed a threat to the US’.Footnote 78 The constitutive role that this security technology plays for international norms in terms of setting precedents and hence new standards of appropriate use of force is, however, completely out of sight.

To conclude, as the conventional frameworks of law/ethics have difficulties to accommodate flexibility and change for structural reasons, we demonstrated that it is necessary to consider other types of norms that are not accounted for in research on AWS. A purely regulative perspective on AWS risks losing track of current developments and their future implications, in particular their possible role in shaping standards of appropriateness and understandings of the ‘new normal’ in warfare.Footnote 79

Researching the normativity of AWS

Research on law and ethics asks how AWS challenge the implementation of fundamental international norms, to what extent they are governed by these norms, and whether discussions in the CCW will lead to the formulation of new fundamental normsFootnote 80 governing their usage. Constructivist research on norm emergence and change mirrors these questions in two main ways: first, it concentrates almost exclusively on fundamental norms with regulative qualities and second, it only studies how new fundamental norms emerge or are contested in processes of deliberation.

First, fundamental norms are typically conceptualised as closely linked to international law. Second-wave constructivist models were thus concerned with analysing the emergence, internalisation, and effects of human rights as fundamental norms.Footnote 81 In the context of disarmament, Nina Tannenwald prominently analysed the ‘development of a normative prohibition against nuclear weapons’,Footnote 82 identified as one of the strongest, fundamental norms in International Relations. She defines a norm as ‘a shared expectation about behavior, a standard of right or wrong’,Footnote 83 thereby linking norms to what is morally ‘right’. While this is certainly a key quality of norms, we argue for a broader understanding. Norms as standard of appropriateness can also comprise functional aspects such as efficiency and effectiveness in specific settings. A procedural norm in the military, for example, does not necessarily meet universal, public understandings of the morally ‘right’.

Second, the second and third wave of constructivist research focused on how norms emerge in processes of deliberation. In the second wave, actors, such as transnational advocacy networksFootnote 84 or norm entrepreneurs, ‘attempt to convince a critical mass of states (norm leaders) to embrace new norms’.Footnote 85 Third wave constructivist scholars criticise the sequential logic of these models by introducing more complexityFootnote 86 and contestation.Footnote 87 In stating that ‘norms are contested by default’,Footnote 88 they argue for a diversity of normative meaning but these contestations still refer back to a deliberative expression of a shared norm, rather than its reconceptualisation in practice. Comprehensive regulation and stigmatisation of nuclear or chemical weapons only emerged after these weapons had been used in the First and Second World Wars, but the analytical focus of studies remains on public deliberations after usage rather than conceptualising in more detail how perceived ‘appropriate’ ways of using, later contested in deliberation, initially emerged in practices.Footnote 89

Technological advances below and beyond the ‘radar’ of international legal regulation might therefore set de facto norms before debates have unfolded. This also challenges the prevalent constructivist perspective that ‘a norm … exists independently of the behavior that it guides or regulates’.Footnote 90 In contrast, we argue that norms emerge in the context of practices. What kinds of new understandings of appropriateness emerge with the rise of AWS as security technologies in practice? As aforementioned, it is argued that ‘robotic weaponry will lower the psychological barriers to starting new wars’.Footnote 91 AWS may contribute to lowering thresholds for the use of force because they do not put the lives of their operators atFootnote risk.Footnote 93 A ‘logic of consequences’, weighing the tactical-strategic and operational advantages of AWS, could spill into a ‘logic of appropriateness’.Footnote 94 What appears to be useful and efficient in procedural terms and in a specific organisational context could therefore become the new standard of what is normatively ‘right’ and legitimate. These often-conflicting understandings of appropriateness might converge in some cases: protecting the lives of a country’s own troops would not only be considered as efficient, but also, publicly, as normatively appropriate and hence legitimate.

Building on these insights, we define norms broadly as standards of appropriateness for specific practices, resting on an inclusive understanding of norms. Here, Antje Wiener’s distinction between ‘fundamental norms’, ‘organizing principles’, and ‘standardized procedures’ is helpful as it points to what we call procedural norms.Footnote 95 Wiener’s three types of norms are further specified based on three features: generalisation, specification, and contestation on ethical grounds (Table 2). Consequently, fundamental norms are considered as more general, less specific, and also as more contested on ethical grounds than the other types.

Table 2 Typology of norms.Footnote 92

Despite drawing attention to different types of norms, Wiener’s typology is hierarchical and thereby still replicates the overall positive research bias towards fundamental norms in two ways. First, organising principles and/or standardised procedures merely implement fundamental norms. We argue that it is conceptually important to consider a reverse of this sequence through analysing how standardised procedures and/or organising principles may shape or define normativity. Second, the assumption of ‘ethical contestation’, in decreasing from fundamental norms to standardised procedures, suggests that the latter do not contain significant normative substance – an assumption we contest.

To gain an understanding of standardised procedures, what we call procedural norms, we suggest focusing on practices. We assume that these practices can construct new or different standards of appropriateness that turn into procedural norms when becoming widespread. Practices can therefore become decisive for studying both how procedural norms emerge and how these relate to fundamental norms.

Given that such procedural norms are subject to less ethical contestation and hence are also less in the public/academic focus than fundamental norms might make them even more relevant or powerful. Operating AWS is very much based on procedural norms – they are governed by an emerging established ‘way of doing things’. As mentioned previously, the US drone program shows how new standards of ‘appropriate’ warfare may emerge in international relations. These procedural norms are of high ethical, normative importance because overall, they are expected to conform to fundamental norms by implementing, respecting, or protecting them. How fundamental norms such as human rights influence practices, that is, what is procedurally legitimate as a ‘best practice’, is therefore often only defined via procedural norms, where operational standards of appropriateness are established.

A focus on procedural norms opens up a connection to practice theories, a diverse and dynamic theoretical programme in IR.Footnote 96 Understood as patterned actions in social context,Footnote 97 practices can act as sensitising conceptsFootnote 98 to study concrete empirical phenomena, such as the emergence of normative standards. Due to their micro-orientation, practice theory can cast light on how norms may emerge on the procedural level and therefore make the processes constitutive of the wider normative international order visible.

The emergence of a technical, autonomous ‘agency’ that comes with AWS adds another element of complexity to this. Theoretically motivated studies of drones already argue for the emergence of ‘“technological agency” [that] shapes the evolving “field” of legal expertise (who counts as a legal expert and on what basis)’.Footnote 99 The agency of AWS can significantly surpass this technological agency in not only shaping but eventually replacing human decision-making in the immediate sense of the term. In that, the problem emerging from ‘the anthropomorphic logic of technology’ that considers drones ‘as moral agents that can “act” rationally, dispassionately and – at least in principle – ethically’Footnote 100 is intensified in the case of AWS. Varying degrees of autonomy and agency of machines play a significant role in constituting procedural norms that are usually expected to translate or follow preprogrammed parameters supposed to comply with fundamental norms. However, what happens when AWS define standards of procedural appropriateness as constitutive of normative meaning that do not match their programmers’ or decision-makers’ initial intentions? This is in line with general assumptions of actor-network theory and the ‘sociology of translation’,Footnote 101 but the more sophisticated agency of AWS opens a new chapter in this regard. The autonomous agency of AWS can potentially ‘break’ the conventional network of human and technological agency. A deeper theoretical discussion of this matter is beyond the scope of this article. But, in the context of AWS, we must ask whether we move from the co-constitution of a human decision and its material execution, which is based on the assumed prevalence of human control, to a sequence where technologies become the dominant constitutive, decision-making element. Furthermore, the absence of an ethical consciousness of machines in the human sense makes them particularly relevant for ethical contestations because their norm-setting qualities as fully autonomous actors will not be linked to human decisions, as was the case to date.

Based on this discussion, we propose studying AWS in the context of two different, but interrelated normative spheres: the legal-public sphere – the primary realm of fundamental norms; and the procedural-organisational sphere – the primary realm of procedural norms. While these spheres are not independent from each other, we use them to examine a broader notion of appropriateness: (1) legal-public appropriateness, and (2) procedural-organisational appropriateness.

Legal-public appropriateness represents fundamental norms, including public expectations in terms of (political) accountability, lawfulness, or transparency. In contrast, procedural-organisational appropriateness represents procedural norms, considerations of appropriateness in specific organisational settings, such as the armed forces, or in specific situations of warfare. Here, appropriateness is concerned with functional legitimacy, specific regulations, and accountability hierarchies, such as a chain of command. In this sense, appropriateness is linked to following clear procedural structures regardless of their content. In representing different contexts of appropriateness, this model accounts for diverging, interplaying layers of appropriate actions. A comprehensive research framework on the normativity of AWS should therefore consider both legal-public and procedural-organisational appropriateness (Table 3).

Table 3 Normative categories and examples of substance.

In sum, the category of legal-public appropriateness comprises fundamental norms such as human rights, international legal standards (international humanitarian and human rights law, jus ad bellum standards of the UN Charter), principles such as the pacific settlement of disputes and non-intervention, but also legitimacy expectations of the public in terms of political accountability and responsible conduct. This category hence combines legality with legitimacy. Procedural-organisational appropriateness comprises procedural norms relevant for specific organisational settings and practices. These are procedural efficiency, effectiveness, or standards in the military context such as obedience to orders, survival, or defeating the enemy. Table 3 provides examples of norms that might be relevant when studying AWS – however, it is important to emphasise that neither fundamental nor procedural norms are fixed in content. The precise importance of specific norms is only perceivable when analysing practices. In the following section, we consider how different types of appropriateness interrelate in the context of AWS and may lead to the emergence of new normativity.

AWS and procedural norms

Research on AWS provides rich summaries of how their development relates to fundamental norms of legal-public appropriateness (see earlier section on this). Yet norms of procedural-operational appropriateness are constituted by conflicting factors. Procedural norms may emerge around perceived operational advantages associated with practices surrounding AWS.

A main perceived advantage of granting full autonomy to AWS lies in their ‘superior’ ability to process a large quantity of information in contrast to humans who run the risk of facing a ‘potential cognitive overload’.Footnote 102 Furthermore, AWS would have the operational advantage of having agency ‘on the battlefield’, while remote-controlled weapons are steered from a remotely positioned ‘decision-making human’. AWS could therefore collect relevant information much more comprehensively but face a double interaction problem if not used in a fully autonomous mode, that is, with the human out of the immediate decision-making loop. If functioning with a human ‘on the loop’, involved in decision-making in an immediate sense, information that is collected and processed is then transmitted to a human actor. This actor must make a decision and communicate it back to the AWS that executes the command. Both remotely-controlled weapons systems and AWS with a human ‘on the loop’ therefore normally operate at a much lower speed than fighter jets for instance. This makes them vulnerable to countermeasures, while their communication link is also susceptible to interference.Footnote 103 Having a human involved therefore may be perceived to slow down the process not only by separating the decision-making and executing actors, but also by technological restrictions in terms of transmission speed.

As Thomas K. Adams notes:

Humans may retain symbolic authority, but automated systems move too fast and the factors involved are too complex for real human comprehension. When computers are designed and programmed by other computers, the situation will be even further from anything that humans can reasonably expect to understand, much less intervene in successfully.Footnote 104

Not only do we have to question the quality of meaningful human control of humans ‘on the loop’ in this context, but we should also note the pressure towards giving AWS more decision-making agency due to reasons of efficiency and perceived military advantage. As Denise Garcia puts it: ‘The USA is pursuing killer robots because it can.’Footnote 105 In other words, norms of procedural-organisational appropriateness set demands for not falling behind possible adversaries and allies alike, as highlighted by the UK’s Ministry of Defence: ‘Our conceptual thinking lags behind the art of the currently possible, never mind what lies in the future.’Footnote 106 This increases the pressure towards proceeding with research and developing AWS ahead of any legal or political-legitimacy considerations.

Scholars have also cited budget pressures as operational advantages for AWS:Footnote 107 while they require investing considerable financial resources from development to testing and training, they are projected to turn out cheaper than humans in the long run. This may become a future push factor, considering that, for example, the US Department of Veteran Affairs alone has spent an estimated US $213 billion in medical and disability payments during the ‘War on Terror’ (2001–16) and is expected to spend another US $1 trillion until 2053.Footnote 108

Further, if the argument were validated that using AWS could decrease civilian casualties compared to the status quo, they would be perceived as procedurally, organisationally, and legally appropriate. It still remains questionable whether the public would accept AWS deciding about life and death as legitimate. Initial research on public opinion shows that support for AWS differs but may be affected when it comes to protecting the life of own troops and countering the risk of foreign powers developing AWS.Footnote 109 Clearly, we should also consider what kind of normativity emerges here. Although the deadly use of force by AWS is not yet a pervasive reality, the way AWS kill is constructed by some as a norm of ‘humane’ future warfare. We can easily imagine how this implicit definition of appropriateness diffuses from the procedural-organisational to the legal-public dimension.

It could be argued at this point that the norm-setting qualities of AWS are strictly limited because they are designed to execute programmed commands within a narrowly defined operational range. In this sense, the autonomous agency of machines will never equate human consciousness and awareness, typically used as a maximum definition of autonomy by states. However, the phenomenon of agency through emergent behaviour, as noted by AI scholars, questions this assumption. It refers to behaviour that is not programmed but arises out of complexity.Footnote 110 This is also related to the potential misinterpretation of human signals by AWS, both in terms of the person ‘on the loop’ and those that the machine encounters in operational scenarios:

Programs with millions of lines of code are written by teams of programmers, none of whom knows the entire program; hence, no individual can predict the effect of a given command with absolute certainty, since portions of large programs may interact in unexpected, untested ways.Footnote 111

This means that the actions of AWS are unpredictable to a certain extent in unstructured, complex environments and decision situations such as battlefields, a point also highlighted by Noel Sharkey: discussing various AWS under development, he notes that all work with ‘clean’ scenarios, that is, scenarios containing only military targets and no civilian populations, which is far from many real life situations.Footnote 112

We should also note that AWS come with operational disadvantages in procedural terms. As an organisation and albeit not a monolith, the military is structured around control, which makes the idea of ceding it to AWS highly contested. The history of developing AWS in the US military, for example, includes various programs that were cancelled despite considerable investmentFootnote 113 and even lead to identifying ‘a cultural disinclination to turn attack decisions over to software algorithms’.Footnote 114 The targeting software included in AWS exceeds human capacities in processing large datasets and other quantitative tasks, but they are disadvantaged compared to humans when it comes to deliberative reasoning, interpreting qualitative data, or accurately judging complex social situations and interactions.Footnote 115 For example, in identifying targets, AWS would be unable to make qualified judgements based on interpreting facial expressions or body language in the same way humans can. Judging situations also concerns crucial assessments, such as whether an armed attack has occurred. This can be underlined by a famous 1983 incident involving Stanislav Petrov, a Soviet officer who disregarded an incoming nuclear missile strike, actually wrongly identified by the early-warning system, as a false alarm, deciding not to report it to superiors who would have retaliated with a nuclear attack.Footnote 116 An autonomous system working within preprogrammed parameters would have not been able to ‘feel’ that something was suspicious about incoming data points.

Therefore, there are also procedural norms working against AWS on an operational level. Yet we consider that the current development and deployment trajectories point towards AWS with disastrous consequences for use of force thresholds. Further, once introduced by one actor, their (future perceived) procedural advantages will shape new norms of procedural appropriateness, putting pressure on other actors to follow suit.

Conclusion: the normative consequences of AWS

This article addressed the emergence of procedural norms through evolving AWS and resulting challenges to constructivist approaches in IR. It outlined that fundamental norms enshrined in international law are expected to govern the usage of AWS in the same way as other technologies of warfare. But can technologies such as AWS be simply regulated by a set of predefined rules or do standards of appropriateness also emerge in practices? In addressing this question, we criticised first, how constructivist approaches privilege the deliberative over the practical emergence of norms and second, how they overemphasise fundamental norms to the detriment of procedural norms. We argue that procedural norms emanating from practices play an un-examined role in emerging normative structures. Instead of merely focusing on how norms regulate or govern AWS, we therefore suggest reversing the perspective and considering how AWS may construct and define norms in practice. In this, we map out a new programme for research both for constructivist scholars interested in norm emergence and scholars of AWS.

Existing research on AWS asks some central questions: can or do AWS conform to international law? How do AWS affect fundamental norms embedded in international law, such as human rights? How do autonomous technologies relate to expectations of political accountability and responsibility? Should AWS be pre-emptively banned? But research neglects that normativity may already emerge from their development, testing and deployment on the procedural, practical level. How AWS may set novel understandings of appropriate action remains understudied. To capture this dynamic analytically, our theoretical approach differentiates between two sets of norms: fundamental norms that define legal-public appropriateness and procedural norms that define procedural-organisational appropriateness. This understanding stands in contrast to the primary focus on fundamental norms present in constructivist norms research. We argue that understandings of what is procedurally appropriate in a specific organisational environment are often in conflict with expectations of legal-public appropriateness.

This is an important change of perspective as neither specialised literature on AWS, international/domestic law, nor constructivist research on norms has yet developed a substantial normative foundation for assessing the implications of AWS. As a normative consequence of this gap, current practices surrounding the development and usage of AWS effectively define ‘normal’ action in international relations. A similar development is already underway in the deployment and proliferation of drones as major instruments of contemporary counterterrorism. The US drone program has set novel precedents for how ending human life is ‘appropriate’ – not because these practices specifically comply with international law or adhere to domestic norms, but because they satisfy procedural-organisational appropriateness and partly coincide with publicly accepted legitimacy of the ‘War on Terror’. It will be difficult to return to a status quo before this new normality was created because other actors can now potentially exploit this room of maneuver at their discretion.

In this regard, the problem of agreeing on a general, pre-emptive ban of AWS lies in their elusiveness. Scholars continue to debate definitions of autonomy, agency, technical features, operational aspects, and appropriate human supervisory control in the context of AWS. Finding state-based consensus for a definition of AWS at the CCW that could become the basis for negotiating a regulative legal framework proves to hamper the process. Regardless of whether a ban will or will not be imposed, the practice of AWS will already shape understandings of what is appropriate and thereby take the place of a more profound societal-political debate on what is normatively acceptable. We need to be aware of these normative consequences of AWS in order to assess the role they will play in future security policies and international relations in general.

Acknowledgements

The authors would like to thank the members of the Conflict Analysis Research Centre at the University of Kent, participants at the 2017 annual convention of the International Studies Association, as well as two anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments.

References

1 UK Ministry of Defence, ‘The UK Approach to Unmanned Aircraft Systems. Joint Doctrine Note 2/11 (JDN 2/11)’ (2011).

2 There are some notable exceptions: Altmann, Jürgen and Sauer, Frank, ‘Autonomous weapon systems and strategic stability’, Survival, 59:5 (3 September 2017), pp. 117142 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Garcia, Denise, ‘Future arms, technologies, and international law: Preventive security governance’, European Journal of International Security, 1:1 (27 February 2016), pp. 94111 Google Scholar; Carl Haas, Michael and Fischer, Sophie-Charlotte, ‘The evolution of targeted killing practices: Autonomous weapons, future conflict, and the international order’, Contemporary Security Policy, 38:2 (2017), pp. 281306 Google Scholar; Shaw, Ian G. R., ‘Robot wars: US empire and geopolitics in the Robotic Age’, Security Dialogue, 48:5 (2017), pp. 451470 Google Scholar.

3 Heyns, Christof, ‘Autonomous weapons systems: Living a dignified life and dying a dignified death’, in Nehal Bhuta et al. (eds), Autonomous Weapons Systems: Law, Ethics, Policy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2016), pp. 320 (p. 4).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4 Heather Roff, ‘Autonomous or “Semi” Autonomous Weapons? A Distinction Without Difference’, Huffington Post blog (16 January 2015), available at: {http://www.huffingtonpost.com/heather-roff/autonomous-or-semi-autono_b_6487268.html}.

5 Ingvild Bode and Hendrik Huelss, ‘Why “Stupid” Machines Matter: Autonomous Weapons and Shifting Norms’, Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists (12 October 2017), available at: {https://thebulletin.org/why-“stupid”-machines-matter-autonomous-weapons-and-shifting-norms11189}; Toby Walsh, ‘Elon Musk Is Wrong: The AI Singularity Won’t Kill Us All’, Wired (20 September 2017), available at: {http://www.wired.co.uk/article/elon-musk-artificial-intelligence-scaremongering).

6 Leveringhaus, Alex, Ethics and Autonomous Weapons (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Fleischman, William M., ‘Just say “no!” to lethal autonomous robotic weapons’, Journal of Information, Communication and Ethics in Society, 13:3/4 (2015), pp. 299313 Google Scholar; Roff, Heather M., ‘The strategic robot problem: Lethal autonomous weapons in war’, Journal of Military Ethics, 13:3 (3 July 2014), pp. 211227 Google Scholar.

7 Finnemore, Martha and Toope, Stephen J., ‘Alternatives to “legalization”: Richer views of law and politics’, International Organization, 55:3 (2001), pp. 743758 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Sehrawat, Vivek, ‘Autonomous weapon system: Law of armed conflict (LOAC) and other legal challenges’, Computer Law & Security Review, 33:1 (February 2017), pp. 3856 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kastan, Benjamin, ‘Autonomous weapons systems: a coming legal singularity’, Journal of Law, Technology & Policy, 45 (2013), pp. 4582 Google Scholar; Grut, C., ‘The challenge of autonomous lethal robotics to international humanitarian law’, Journal of Conflict and Security Law, 18:1 (1 April 2013), pp. 523 Google Scholar; Husby, Christian, ‘Offensive autonomous weapons: Should we be worried?’, Michigan Journal of International Law, 37 (2015)Google Scholar; Maya Brehm, ‘Defending the Boundary: Constraints and Requirements on the Use of Autonomous Weapons Systems under International Humanitarian and Human Rights Law’, Academy Briefing No. 9 (Geneva Academy, May 2017).

9 See Huelss, Hendrik, ‘After decision-making: the operationalisation of norms in international relations’, International Theory, 9:3 (2017), pp. 381409 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Finnemore, Martha and Sikkink, Kathryn, ‘International norm dynamics and political change’, International Organization, 52:4 (1998), pp. 887917 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Risse, Thomas, Ropp, Stephen, and Sikkink, Kathryn, The Power of Human Rights: International Norms and Domestic Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999)Google Scholar; Elizabeth Keck, Margaret and Sikkink, Kathryn, Activists Beyond Borders: Advocacy Networks in International Politics (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1998)Google Scholar; Risse, Thomas, ‘“Let’s argue!”: Communicative action in world politics’, International Organization, 54:1 (2000), pp. 139 Google Scholar.

11 Wiener, Antje, ‘Contested compliance: Interventions on the normative structure of world politics’, European Journal of International Relations, 10:2 (2004), pp. 189234 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wiener, Antje, ‘Enacting meaning-in-use: Qualitative research on norms and international relations’, Review of International Studies, 35:1 (8 January 2009), pp. 175193 Google Scholar; Zimmermann, Lisbeth, ‘Same same or different? Norm diffusion between resistance, compliance, and localization in post-conflict states’, International Studies Perspectives, 17:1 (2016), pp. 98115 Google Scholar.

12 Tannenwald, Nina, ‘The nuclear taboo: the United States basis of and the normative nuclear non-use’, International Organization, 53:3 (1999), pp. 433468 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Garcia, Denise, Small Arms and Security: New Emerging International Norms (Abingdon: Routledge, 2006)Google Scholar; Lantis, Jeffrey S., Arms and Influence: US Technology Innovations and the Evolution of International Security Norms (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2016)Google Scholar.

13 Leander, Anna, ‘Thinking tools’, in Audie Klotz and Deepa Prakesh (eds), Qualitative Methods in International Relations: A Pluralist Guide (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008), pp. 1127 (p. 18)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14 Wiener, Antje, ‘Contested meanings of norms: a research framework’, Comparative European Politics, 5 (2007), p. 8 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15 Wiener, ‘Contested compliance’.

16 See, for example, Asaro, Peter, ‘On banning autonomous weapon systems: Human rights, automation, and the dehumanization of lethal decision-making’, International Review of the Red Cross, 94:886 (2012), pp. 687709 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Future of Life Institute, ‘Autonomous Weapons: An Open Letter from AI & Robotics Researchers’ (2015), available at: {https://futureoflife.org/open-letter-autonomous-weapons}; Sharkey, Noel E., ‘The evitability of autonomous robot warfare’, International Review of the Red Cross, 94:886 (4 June 2012), pp. 787799 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 As the autonomy of weapons systems evolves along a trajectory encompassing remote-controlled systems such as drones, the article recurs on these instruments to illustrate the impact of emerging standards of appropriateness.

18 See Sparrow, Robert, ‘Robots and respect: Assessing the case against autonomous weapon systems’, Ethics & International Affairs, 30:1 (2016), p. 95 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Noel Sharkey, ‘Staying in the loop: Human supervisory control of weapons’, in Bhuta et al. (eds), Autonomous Weapons Systems, pp. 23–38 (p. 23).

20 Giovanni Sartor and Andrea Omicini, ‘The autonomy of technological systems and responsibilities for their use’, in Bhuta et al. (eds), Autonomous Weapons Systems, pp. 40–57.

21 Roff, ‘Autonomous or “Semi” Autonomous Weapons?’.

22 Sharkey, Noel, ‘Saying “no!” to lethal autonomous targeting’, Journal of Military Ethics, 9:4 (December 2010), p. 377 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

23 Heyns, ‘Autonomous weapons systems’; Sharkey, ‘Staying in the loop’.

24 Williams, John, ‘Democracy and regulating autonomous weapons: Biting the bullet while missing the point?’, Global Policy, 6:3 (2015), p. 183 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Human Rights Watch, ‘Losing Humanity: The Case Against Killer Robots’ (2012), p. 2.

25 Heyns, ‘Autonomous weapons systems’, p. 14.

26 Moyes, Richard, ‘Meaningful human control’, in Robin Geiss and Henning Lahmann (eds), Lethal Autononous Weapons Systems: Technology, Definition, Ethics, Law & Security (Berlin: Federal Foreign Office, 2016), pp. 239249 Google Scholar.

27 Sharkey, ‘Staying in the loop’, pp. 34–7.

28 Christof Heyns, ‘Report of the Special Rapporteur on Extrajudicial, Summary or Arbitrary Executions. A/HRC/23/47’ (Geneva, 2013), pp. 5–6.

29 Heyns, ‘Autonomous weapons systems’, p. 11.

30 For a more detailed discussion, see section entitled ‘AWS and procedural norms’.

31 See Mary Wareham, ‘Banning Killer Robots in 2017’, The Cipher Brief (2017), available at: {https://www.hrw.org/news/2017/01/15/banning-killer-robots-2017}.

32 Campaign to Stop Killer Robots, ‘Support Builds for New International Law on Killer Robots’ (17 November 2017), available at: {https://www.stopkillerrobots.org/2017/11/gge/}.

33 The group calling for a ban comprises (November 2017): Algeria, Argentina, Bolivia, Brazil, Chile, Costa Rica, Cuba, Ecuador, Egypt, Ghana, Guatemala, Holy See, Iraq, Mexico, Nicaragua, Pakistan, Panama, Peru, State of Palestine, Uganda, Venezuela, and Zimbabwe.

34 Chinese Delegation to CCW, ‘The Position Paper Submitted by the Chinese Delegation to CCW 5th Review Conference’ (2016), p. 1.

35 US Department of Defense, ‘Directive 3000.09 on Autonomy in Weapon Systems’ (2012), p. 13.

36 Ibid., p. 14.

37 Mark Gubrud, ‘Semi-Autonomous and on Their Own: Killer Robots in Plato’s Cave’, Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists (12 April 2015), available at: {http://thebulletin.org/semi-autonomous-and-their-own-killer-robots-plato’s-cave8199}.

38 Roff, ‘Autonomous or “Semi” Autonomous Weapons?’.

39 UK Ministry of Defence, ‘Joint Doctrine Publication 0-30.2. Unmanned Aircraft Systems’ (2017), p. 72, available at: {https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/640299/20170706_JDP_0-30.2_final_CM_web.pdf}.

40 Ibid., p. 72.

41 UK Ministry of Defence, ‘The UK Approach to Unmanned Aircraft Systems. Joint Doctrine Note 2/11 (JDN 2/11)’, pp. 2–3.

42 Human Rights Watch, ‘Review of the 2012 US Policy on Autonomy in Weapons Systems: US Policy on Autonomy in Weapons Systems Is First in the World’ (2013), available at: {https://www.hrw.org/news/2013/04/15/review-2012-us-policy-autonomy-weapons-systems}.

43 Campaign to Stop Killer Robots, ‘New US Policy’ (16 April 2013), available at: {https://www.stopkillerrobots.org/2013/04/new-us-policy/}.

44 Human Rights Watch, ‘Review of the 2012 US Policy on Autonomy in Weapons Systems’.

45 We thank an anonymous reviewer for drawing our attention to this point.

46 Mark Gubrud, ‘US Killer Robot Policy: Full Speed Ahead’, Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists (20 September 2013), available at: {http://thebulletin.org/us-killer-robot-policy-full-speed-ahead}.

47 Gubrud, ‘Semi-Autonomous and on Their Own’.

48 US Department of Defense, ‘Directive 3000.09’, p. 3.

49 Gubrud, ‘US Killer Robot Policy’.

50 Dan Saxon, ‘A human touch: Autonomous weapons, DoD Directive 3000.09 and the interpretation of “appropriate levels of human judgment over the use of force”’, in Bhuta et al. (eds), Autonomous Weapons Systems, p. 185.

51 Office of Naval Research, ‘News – Autonomous Swarmboats: New Missions, Safe Harbors’ (2016), available at: {https://www.onr.navy.mil/en/Media-Center/Press-Releases/2016/Autonomous-Swarmboats.aspx}.

52 US Department of Defense, ‘Department of Defense Announces Successful Micro-Drone Demonstration: Press Operations. Release NR-008-17’ (2017), available at: {https://www.defense.gov/News/News-Releases/News-Release-View/Article/1044811/department-of-defense-announces-successful-micro-drone-demonstration}.

53 Ibid.

54 Franz-Stefan Gady, ‘Unmanned “killer robots”: a new weapon in the US Navy’s future arsenal? The US Navy moves unmanned drones to the top of its priorities’, The Diplomat (April 2015), available at: {http://thediplomat.com/2015/04/unmanned-killer-robots-a-new-weapon-in-the-us-navys-future-arsenal/}.

55 Kris Osborn, ‘The US Navy’s Sub-Hunting Drone Ship is Being Upgraded to Launch Offensive Attacks’, Business Insider (2017), available at: {http://www.businessinsider.com/us-navy-actuv-drone-ship-2017-1?IR=T}.

56 Israel Aerospace Industries, ‘HAROP’ (2017), available at: {http://www.iai.co.il/2013/36694-46079-EN/Business_Areas_Land.aspx}.

57 Thomas Gibbons-Neff, ‘Israeli-made kamikaze drone spotted in Nagorno-Karabakh conflict’, The Washington Post (2016), available at: {https://www.washingtonpost.com/news/checkpoint/wp/2016/04/05/israeli-made-kamikaze-drone-spotted-in-nagorno-karabakh-conflict/?utm_term=.6acc4522477c}.

58 Stephen Goose and Mary Wareham, ‘The growing international movement against killer robots’, Harvard International Review, 37:3 (2016), available at: {http://hir.harvard.edu/growing-international-movement-killer-robots/}.

59 This is based on data compiled by: Vincent Boulanin, ‘Mapping the Development of Autonomy in Weapon Systems: A Primer on Autonomy’, SIPRI Working Paper (Stockholm, 2016); Heather M. Roff and Richard Moyes, ‘Dataset. Project: Artificial Intelligence, Autonomous Weapons, and Meaningful Human Control’ (2017), available at: {https://globalsecurity.asu.edu/robotics-autonomy}.

60 Arkin, Ronald C., ‘The case for ethical autonomy in unmanned systems’, Journal of Military Ethics, 9:4 (December 2010), pp. 332341 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

61 Michael C. Horowitz and Paul Scharre, ‘Do Killer Robots Save Lives?’, POLITICO Magazine (19 November 2014), available at: {http://www.politico.com/magazine/story/2014/11/killer-robots-save-lives-113010.html}.

62 Roff, Heather M., ‘Lethal autonomous weapons and jus ad bellum proportionality’, Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law, 47 (2015), pp. 3752 Google Scholar.

63 Sparrow, ‘Robots and respect’.

64 Sharkey, ‘Saying “no!” to lethal autonomous targeting’; Sharkey, ‘The evitability of autonomous robot warfare’.

65 Walsh, J. I., ‘Political accountability and autonomous weapons’, Research & Politics, 2:4 (2015), pp. 16 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

66 Hammond, Daniel N., ‘Autonomous weapons and the problem of state accountability’, Chicago Journal of International Law, 15 (2014), pp. 652687 Google Scholar; Sparrow, Robert, ‘Killer robots’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 24:1 (February 2007), pp. 6277 Google Scholar; Walsh, ‘Political accountability and autonomous weapons’.

67 Johnson, Aaron M. and Axinn, Sidney, ‘The morality of autonomous robots’, Journal of Military Ethics, 12:2 (July 2013), pp. 129141 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Leveringhaus, Ethics and Autonomous Weapons; Sharkey, ‘Saying “no!” to lethal autonomous targeting’; Sparrow, ‘Robots and respect’.

68 Sharkey, ‘Saying “no!” to lethal autonomous targeting’; Sharkey, ‘The evitability of autonomous robot warfare’; Heyns, ‘Autonomous weapons systems’.

69 Arkin, ‘The case for ethical autonomy in unmanned systems’.

70 See Kaag, John and Kreps, Sarah, Drone Warfare (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2014)Google Scholar.

71 Garcia, ‘Future arms, technologies, and international law’, p. 101.

72 See Warren, Aiden and Bode, Ingvild, ‘Altering the playing field: the U.S. redefinition of the use-of-force’, Contemporary Security Policy, 36:2 (4 May 2015), pp. 174199 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

73 International Committee of the Red Cross, ‘Introduction’, ICRC – Customary International Humanitarian Law (2017), available at: {https://ihl-databases.icrc.org/customary-ihl/eng/docs/v1_rul_in_asofcuin}.

74 Bode, Ingvild, ‘“Manifestly failing” and “unable or unwilling” as intervention formulas: a critical analysis’, in Aiden Warren and Damian Grenfell (eds), Rethinking Humanitarian Intervention in the 21st Century (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2017), pp. 164191 Google Scholar.

75 See Ingvild Bode, ‘How the World’s Interventions in Syria Have Normalised the Use of Force’, The Conversation (17 February 2016), available at: {http://theconversation.com/how-the-worlds-interventions-in-syria-have-normalised-the-use-of-force-54505}.

76 Wayne McLean, ‘Drones Are Cheap, Soldiers Are Not: A Cost-Benefit Analysis of War’, The Conversation (2014), available at: {https://theconversation.com/drones-are-cheap-soldiers-are-not-a-cost-benefit-analysis-of-war-27924; Michael W. Lewis, ‘Drones: Actually the Most Humane Form of Warfare Ever’, The Atlantic (2013), available at: {https://www.theatlantic.com/international/archive/2013/08/drones-actually-the-most-humane-form-of-warfare-ever/278746/}.

77 Sauer, Frank and Schörnig, Niklas, ‘Killer drones: the “silver bullet” of democratic warfare?’, Security Dialogue, 43:4 (August 2012), p. 375 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

78 Fairleigh Dickinson University, ‘Public Says It’s Illegal to Target Americans Abroad as Some Question CIA Drone Attacks’ (2013), p. 1, available at: {http://www.publicmind.fdu.edu/2013/drone/}.

79 Singer, Peter W., Wired for War: The Robotics Revolution and Conflict in the 21st Century (New York: Penguin, 2010)Google Scholar.

80 Wiener, ‘Enacting meaning-in-use’.

81 Finnemore and Sikkink, ‘International norm dynamics and political change’; Keck and Sikkink, Activists Beyond Borders; Risse, Ropp, and Sikkink, The Power of Human Rights; Risse, ‘“Let’s argue!”’.

82 Tannenwald, ‘The nuclear taboo’; Jefferson, Catherine, ‘Origins of the norm against chemical weapons’, International Affairs, 90:3 (May 2014), pp. 647661 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

83 Tannenwald, ‘The nuclear taboo’, p. 436.

84 Keck and Sikkink, Activists Beyond Borders; Risse, Ropp, and Sikkink, The Power of Human Rights.

85 Finnemore and Sikkink, ‘International norm dynamics and political change’, p. 895.

86 Garcia, Small Arms and Security.

87 Wiener, Antje, A Theory of Contestation (Berlin: Springer, 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Bloomfield, Alan, ‘Norm antipreneurs and theorising resistance to normative change’, Review of International Studies, 42:2 (2016), pp. 310333 Google Scholar; Zimmermann, ‘Same same or different?’.

88 Wiener, ‘Contested compliance’.

89 Tannenwald, ‘The nuclear taboo’; Jefferson, ‘Origins of the norm against chemical weapons’; Rosert, Elvira et al., ‘Arms control norms and technology’, in Harald Müller and Carmen Wunderlich (eds), Norm Dynamics in Multilateral Arms Control: Interests, Conflicts, and Justice, Studies in Security and International Affairs (Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press, 2013)Google Scholar.

90 Kütt, Moritz and Steffek, Jens, ‘Comprehensive prohibition of nuclear weapons: an emerging international norm?’, The Nonproliferation Review, 22:3–4 (2 October 2015), p. 403 Google Scholar.

91 Wallach, Wendell and Allen, Colin, ‘Framing robot arms control’, Ethics and Information Technology, 15:2 (21 June 2013), pp. 125135 (p. 125)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

92 Based on Wiener, ‘Enacting meaning-in-use’, p. 184.

93 Asaro, Peter, ‘How just could a robot war be?’, in Adam Briggle, Katinka Waelbers, and Philip Brey (eds), Current Issues in Computing and Philosophy, Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence and Applications (Amsterdam, Netherlands ; Washington, DC: IOS Press, 2008), pp. 115 Google Scholar.

94 March, James G. and Olsen, Johan P., Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis of Politics (New York: Free Press, 1989)Google Scholar.

95 Wiener, ‘Enacting meaning-in-use’, p. 184.

96 Bueger, Christian and Gadinger, Frank, ‘The play of international practice’, International Studies Quarterly, 59 (2015), pp. 449460 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Bueger, Christian and Gadinger, Frank, International Practice Theory (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014)Google Scholar.

97 Leander, ‘Thinking tools’.

98 Ingvild Bode, ‘Reflective practices at the Security Council: Children and armed conflict and the three United Nations’, European Journal of International Relations (2017), Online First, p. 2, available at: {doi: 10.1177/1354066117714529}.

99 Leander, Anna, ‘Technological agency in the co-constitution of legal expertise and the US drone program’, Leiden Journal of International Law, 26:4 (8 December 2013), p. 813 Google Scholar.

100 Schwarz, E., ‘Prescription drones: On the techno-biopolitical regimes of contemporary “ethical killing”‘, Security Dialogue, 47:1 (1 February 2016), p. 65 Google Scholar.

101 Best, Jacqueline and Walters, William, ‘“Actor-network theory” and international relationality: Lost (and found) in translation’, International Political Sociology, 7:3 (12 September 2013), pp. 332334 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see Callon, Michel, ‘Some elements of a sociology of translation: Domestication of the scallops and the fishermen of St Brieuc Bay’, The Sociological Review, 32 (May 1984), pp. 196233 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Leander, ‘Technological agency’.

102 Noone, Gregory P. and Noone, Diane C., ‘The debate over autonomous weapons systems’, Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law, 47 (2015), p. 33 Google Scholar; Haas and Fischer, ‘The evolution of targeted killing’, p. 295.

103 See Sparrow, ‘Robots and respect’, p. 96; Horowitz, Michael C., Kreps, Sarah E., and Fuhrmann, Matthew, ‘Separating fact from fiction in the debate over drone proliferation’, International Security, 41:2 (October 2016), p. 26 Google Scholar.

104 Adams, Thomas K., ‘Future warfare and the decline of human decisionmaking’, Parameters, 31:4 (2001), p. 1 Google Scholar.

105 Garcia, Denise, ‘Killer robots: Why the US should lead the ban’, Global Policy, 6:1 (February 2015), pp. 5763 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

106 UK Ministry of Defence, ‘The UK Approach to Unmanned Aircraft Systems’, Conclusion, p. 1.

107 Gubrud, ‘US Killer Robot Policy’.

108 Neta C. Crawford, ‘US Budgetary Costs of Wars through 2016: $4.79 Trillion and Counting. Summary of Costs of the US Wars in Iraq, Syria, Afghanistan and Pakistan and Homeland Security’ (Costs of War Project. Watson Institute of International and Public Affairs. Brown University, September 2016), pp. 2–3.

109 Horowitz, M. C., ‘Public opinion and the politics of the killer robots debate’, Research & Politics, 3:1 (16 February 2016), pp. 18 Google Scholar.

110 Kurzweil, Ray, The Age of Spiritual Machines: When Computers Exceed Human Intelligence (New York, NY: Penguin, 2000)Google Scholar.

111 Marchant, Gary E. et al., ‘International governance of autonomous military robots’, The Columbia Science and Technology Law Review, XII (2011), p. 284 Google Scholar.

112 Sharkey, ‘The evitability of autonomous robot warfare’; Sharkey, ‘Saying “no!” to lethal autonomous targeting’.

113 Gubrud, ‘US Killer Robot Policy’.

114 Watts, Barry D., ‘Six Decades of Guided Munitions and Battle Networks: Progress and Prospects’ (Centre for Strategic and Budgetary Assessments, March 2007), p. 283 Google Scholar.

115 Heyns, ‘A/HRC/23/47’; Sharkey, ‘Staying in the loop’.

116 Paul Aksenov, ‘Stanislav Petrov: the man who may have saved the world’, BBC Russian (26 September 2013), available at: {http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-europe-24280831}.

Figure 0

Table 1 Sample AWS in development or operation.

Figure 1

Table 2 Typology of norms.92

Figure 2

Table 3 Normative categories and examples of substance.