Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-m8qmq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T22:42:46.624Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Craddock and Mynors-Wallis's assault on thinking

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2018

James Rodger
Affiliation:
South Devon CAMHS, Devon Integrated Children's Services, Exeter, email: j.rodger@nhs.net
Sami Timimi
Affiliation:
Lincolnshire Partnership NHS Foundation Trust Child and Family Services Horizons Centre, Lincoln
Joanna Moncrieff
Affiliation:
Department of Mental Health Sciences, University College London, London
Graham Behr
Affiliation:
Central and North West London Foundation NHS Trust, London
Pat Bracken
Affiliation:
Centre for Mental Health Care and Recovery, Bantry General Hospital, Bantry, Ireland
Ivor Browne
Affiliation:
University College Dublin, Dublin, Ireland
Chris Evans
Affiliation:
East London NHS Trust, London
Suman Fernando
Affiliation:
Faculty of Social Sciences & Humanities, London Metropolitan University, London
Rhodri Huws
Affiliation:
Eastglade Community Health Centre, Sheffield
Bob Johnson
Affiliation:
Quay Street Clinic, Isle of Wight
Brian Martindale
Affiliation:
Newcastle upon Tyne
Hugh Middleton
Affiliation:
School of Sociology and Social Policy, University of Nottingham and Nottinghamshire Healthcare NHS Trust, Nottingham
Derek Summerfield
Affiliation:
CASCAID, Maudsley Hospital, London
Philip Thomas
Affiliation:
University of Bradford, Bradford, UK
Jeremy Wallace
Affiliation:
HUS, Peijas Hospital, Vantaa, Finland
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Columns
Copyright
Copyright © Royal College of Psychiatrists, 2014 

The validity and utility of psychiatric diagnoses have long been a bone of contention between and within different professional and patient groups. This was clearly shown by the nearly 70 rapid responses to a 2001 BMJ article that proposed that post-traumatic stress disorder was a social construct with little clinical utility. Reference Summerfield1 The reponses were emotive and polarised, with an equal proportion of patients and professionals in each camp: those who felt diagnoses were important and life-changing, and those who felt outraged and negated by the medicalisation of social suffering. In their recent editorial Craddock and Mynors-Wallis Reference Craddock and Mynors-Wallis2 frame this diagnostic debate in terms of ‘benefits and limitations’; possible ‘disadvantages’ are acknowledged but mention of potential harms is conspicuously absent.

They advocate ‘embracing complexity’, but for the rest of their article this does not ring true. They reel off the standard list of apparent advantages to diagnosis - providing reassurance and reducing blame, shame and stigma - but without reference to research findings. (Nowhere in their paper is any patient-led or collaborative research cited.) Also conspicuously absent in their list is the necessity of a diagnosis to guide treatment. Is this a tacit acknowledgement that there is little evidence to support such a claim and that, in mental healthcare at least, ‘common factors’ linked to the therapeutic alliance, alongside extra-therapeutic factors, explain the majority of treatment variance? Reference Bracken, Thomas, Timimi, Asen, Behr and Beuster3 In spite of this, they then go on to assert ‘there are no issues about diagnosis (or indeed treatments) that are unique to psychiatry’ (for the counter-argument see Bracken et al Reference Bracken, Thomas, Timimi, Asen, Behr and Beuster3 and related correspondence).

Their erroneous linkage between diagnosis and stigma reduction stands out as particularly misleading. There is now an abundance of evidence, including a comprehensive review published last year in this journal, Reference Angermeyer, Holzinger, Carta and Schomerus4 that biomedical framing of mental illness tends to increase personal and social stigma and public desire for distance.

The authors may counter that a diagnosis does not imply biological causality, and they seem to endorse the standard biopsychosocial frame of reference. The problem is, as Roland Littlewood Reference Littlewood5 points out, it is more or less impossible to hold a ‘personalistic’ view of the self as agentic and intentional while at the same time subscribing to a ‘naturalistic’ view of being a product of biology, or even of the environment. One position always elides into the other. If this is true for professionals, it is certainly true for patients. And the dominant cultural understanding of diagnosis is that of biology, as it is with de facto psychiatric practice. Reference Barrett6

Craddock and Mynors-Wallis seem to want to be reasonable; identifying themselves, with other psychiatrists, as ‘reflective and tolerant of strongly opposing views and ideologies’. First, however, they resort to an unsubstantiated moral and emotive appeal to their position: ‘This can be to our patients’ disadvantage if we allow these views [i.e. critical of standard diagnostic practices] to be unopposed by suggesting that our patients are somehow less deserving of a psychiatric diagnosis than a physical diagnosis’. Then, just in case we are still equivocating, using the College’s Good Psychiatric Practice to bring us into line (as if this too was some ahistorical and acultural document), they pronounce: ‘This [use of standardised diagnosis] is not an issue of personal choice for a practitioner. It is a professional responsibility to the patient’. Their penultimate reference (entitled ‘Time to end the distinction between mental and neurological illnesses’) betrays their own ideological foray.

Of course, if diagnosis is understood in the broader sense of a thoroughgoing, descriptive and summative attempt at understanding a patient’s struggles, respectful of personal meaning and unblinded to issues of power and social context (the latter often being harder to change than biology, in which it may then of course be reflected Reference Krieger7 ), then we too might endorse Craddock and Mynors-Wallis’s position. But in terms of a reverence to standardised manuals (whether DSM or ICD) that lack true nosological validity, even by their own standards, and whose utility is at best questionable, Reference Timimi8 and which in effect serve to obscure key psychosocial antecedents, Reference Krieger7 we would also argue that our patients deserve better.

There is little space for wider critique (for this, see Timimi Reference Timimi8 ) and discussion of alternatives here, but if mature science is comfortable with dissent and debate (and indeed sees this as necessary for progression) this editorial seems a misplaced attempt to close down discussion - first through unsubstantiated emotive appeal, then through the threat of professional censure - in order to maintain a façade of professional consensus. While we might wonder what lies behind such a move, we would advocate a more far-reaching attempt at embracing complexity. In particular, as we have argued elsewhere, Reference Bracken, Thomas, Timimi, Asen, Behr and Beuster3 in attending to issues of power, meaning, social context and the therapeutic alliance, alongside but not reduced to biology, we have much to offer the rest of medicine, which is also beginning to grapple with related issues. Reference Das9,Reference Sharpe10

References

1 Summerfield, D. The invention of post-traumatic stress disorder and the social usefulness of a psychiatric category. BMJ 2001; 322: 95–8.Google Scholar
2 Craddock, N, Mynors-Wallis, L. Psychiatric diagnosis: impersonal, imperfect and important. Br J Psychiatry 2014; 204: 93–5.Google Scholar
3 Bracken, P, Thomas, P, Timimi, S, Asen, E, Behr, G, Beuster, C, et al. Psychiatry beyond the current paradigm. Br J Psychiatry 2012; 201: 430–4.Google Scholar
4 Angermeyer, MC, Holzinger, A, Carta, MG, Schomerus, G. Biogenetic explanations and public acceptance of mental illness: systematic review of population studies. Br J Psychiatry 2011; 199: 367–72.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
5 Littlewood, R. Pathologies of the West: An Anthropology of Mental Illness in Europe and America. Continuum International Publishing Group, 2002.Google Scholar
6 Barrett, RJ. The Psychiatric Team and the Social Definition of Schizophrenia: An Anthropological Study of Person and Illness. Cambridge University Press, 1996.Google Scholar
7 Krieger, N. ‘Bodies count', and body counts: social epidemiology and embodying inequality. Epidemiologic Reviews 2004; 26: 92103.Google Scholar
8 Timimi, S. No more psychiatric labels: campaign to abolish psychiatric diagnostic systems such as ICD and DSM. Self & Society 2013; 40: 614.Google Scholar
9 Das, A. The ‘rest of medicine’ and psychiatry: why paradigms would differ. Br J Psychiatry 2013; 202: 463.Google Scholar
10 Sharpe, M. Psychological medicine and the future of psychiatry. Br J Psychiatry 2014; 204: 91–2.Google Scholar
Submit a response

eLetters

No eLetters have been published for this article.