Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c4f8m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T17:35:43.678Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Abortion, mental health and charges of guilt by association

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2018

David Reardon*
Affiliation:
Elliot Institute, Springfield, Illinois, USA. Email: bmj@mine4ever.net
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Columns
Copyright
Copyright © 2012 The Royal College of Psychiatrists 

Coleman's meta-analysis of abortion and mental health studies Reference Coleman1 was harshly criticised in three letters by five authors (Robinson, Stotland, Nadelson, Coyne, and Littell) who all cited an Ethics & Medicine article Reference Reardon2 I wrote (not Coleman) as evidence that Coleman's study cannot be trusted. My full response Reference Reardon3 is summarised as follows.

First, Robinson's Reference Robinson, Stotland and Nadelson4 assertion that I am Coleman's ‘leader’ is nonsense. We have no institutional, financial or personal entanglements. Second, I gathered data that required the analysis of research psychologists. I am thankful that Coleman agreed to analyse it and help present it in a scientifically accurate and impartial manner. As a biomedical ethicist, I explore the intersections of medicine, science, philosophy, theology, ethics and the law. When writing papers intended for each of these fields, I seek to use the language and tools appropriate to each field.

Third, the cited article was a response to a pro-life philosopher who argued that any evidence of emotional suffering of women following abortion is essentially irrelevant to the moral argument against abortion and counterproductive to pro-life efforts. Reference Beckwith5 The core of my response was that Christians have an obligation to ‘consistently demonstrate as much concern for women as for their unborn children’, and that ‘our advocacy for women must be consistent and unconditional both for those who are facing crisis pregnancies and for those who have had abortions’. I further argued that ‘the harm abortion does to women is just as real as that done to the human fetus’. Reference Reardon2

Fourth, it also reflected my sincere belief that abortion involves substantial dangers to specific subgroups of women. Unfortunately, critics have distorted this into the charge that I seek to scare women with exaggerated risks. Reference Baezlon6 That is untrue. There are real risks, especially for certain higher-risk groups. Reference Burke and Reardon7 Women

should be told of the truth regarding statistically significant findings. These should be neither exaggerated nor minimised.

Finally, women who dare to express emotional trials following an abortion face rejection from people on both sides. A few pro-lifers harshly dismiss these women as ‘sinners’ who deserve a lifetime of grief. Conversely, at least a few pro-choicers dismiss their grief as ‘whining’ or ‘rare’, or suggest that only women mentally unstable prior to their abortions would complain so much. By contrast, the post-abortion healing movement simply asks those on both sides to respect the experiences of women grieving a past abortion. But even this pro-healing position is attacked. Pro-choicers accuse us of manipulating gullible women into falsely blaming unrelated life problems on their abortions. Reference Baezlon6 Some pro-life advocates, meanwhile, accuse us of encouraging an unprincipled, narcissistic worldview that diminishes the moral absolutes regarding the sanctity of life. Reference Beckwith5

To my mind, the question of whether abortion is the sole, direct cause of certain mental illnesses is far less important than the fact that many self-aware women want help coping with a past abortion experience. Reference Burke and Reardon7 Why is it so hard to simply accept their self-assessments and stated needs? Women deserve better.

Declaration of interest

D. R. is Director of the Elliot Institute, USA.

References

1 Coleman, PK. Abortion and mental health: quantitative synthesis and analysis of research published 1995–2009. Br J Psychiatry 2011; 199: 180–6.Google Scholar
2 Reardon, DC. A defense of the neglected rhetorical strategy (NRS). Ethics Med 2002; 18: 2332.Google Scholar
3 Reardon, DC. Abortion and mental health deniers' attack and distract strategy – after abortion. After Abortion, 2011; October 22 (http://afterabortion.org/2011/do–not–publish/).Google Scholar
4 Robinson, GE, Stotland, NL, Nadelson, CC. Re: Abortion and mental health: quantitative synthesis and analysis of research published 1995–2009. (E–letter). Br J Psychiatry 2011; September 22.Google Scholar
5 Beckwith, FJ. Taking abortion seriously: a philosophical critique of the new anti–abortion rhetorical shift. Ethics Med 2001; 17: 155–66.Google ScholarPubMed
6 Baezlon, E. Is there a post–abortion syndrome? New York Times Magazine 2007; January 21.Google Scholar
7 Burke, T, Reardon, DC. Forbidden Grief: The Unspoken Pain of Abortion. Acorn Books, 2002.Google Scholar
Submit a response

eLetters

No eLetters have been published for this article.