Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-t5pn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-16T06:39:17.262Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Occam’s Razor and Non-Voluntarist Accounts of Political Authority

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 March 2017

LUKE MARING*
Affiliation:
Northern Arizona University

Abstract

Certain non-voluntarists have recently defended political authority by advancing views with a two-fold structure. First, they argue that the state, or the law, is best (or uniquely) capable of accomplishing something important. Second, they defend a substantive normative principle on which being so situated is sufficient for de jure authority. Widely accepted tenets undermine all such views.

Certains non-volontaristes ont récemment défendu l’autorité politique en avançant des points de vue en deux parties. D’abord, ils soutiennent que l’état, ou la loi, est la plus (ou la seule) capable d’accomplir quelque chose d’important. Deuxièmement, ils défendent un principe substantif et normatif selon lequel être dans une telle position de pouvoir est suffisant pour l’autorité de jure. Cet article utilise des principes largement acceptés pour montrer que tous ces points de vue échouent.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anscombe, G.E.M. 1990 “On the Source of the Authority of the State,” in Raz, Joseph (ed.), Authority, 142173. NY: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen 2009 “Authority and Second-Personal Reasons for Acting,” in Sobel, David and Wall, Steven (eds.), Reasons for Action, 134154. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen 2010 “Authority and Reasons: Exclusionary and Second-Personal,” Ethics 120 (2): 257278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dobos, Ned 2016 “Political Obligation,” The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ISSN 2161, http://www.iep.utm.edu/poli-obl/#H6.Google Scholar
Durning, Patrick 2003 “Political Legitimacy and the Duty to Obey the Law,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33 (3): 373389.Google Scholar
Edmundson, William A. 1998 “Legitimate Authority Without Political Obligation,” Law and Philosophy, 17 (1): 4360.Google Scholar
Edmundson, William A. 2011 “Consent and Its Cousins,” Ethics, 121 (2): 335353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, David 2014 “Authority and Reason-Giving,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 89 (2): 296332.Google Scholar
Estlund, David 2008 Democratic Authority, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, J.M. 1990 “Authority,” in Raz, Joseph (ed.), Authority, 174202. NY: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Friedman, R. 1990 “On the Concept of Authority in Political Philosophy,” in Raz, Joseph (ed.), Authority, 5691. NY: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Green, Leslie 1988 The Authority of the State. NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Green, Leslie 1996 “Who Believes in Political Obligation,” in Sanders, John T. and Narveson, Jan (eds.), For and Against the State, 301317. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.Google Scholar
Greenawalt, Kent 1999 “Legitimate Authority and the Duty to Obey,” in Edmundson, William A. (ed.), The Duty to Obey the Law, 177192. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.Google Scholar
Himma, Kenneth Einar 2007 “Just ‘Cause You’re Smarter than Me Doesn’t Give You a Right to Tell Me What to Do: Legitimate Authority and the Normal Justification Thesis,” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 27 (1): 121150.Google Scholar
Honoré, Tony 1981 “Must We Obey? Necessity as a Ground of Obligation,” Virginia Law Review 67 (1): 3961.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horton, John 2006 “In Defence of Associative Political Obligations: Part One,” Political Studies 54 (3): 427443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maring, Luke 2016 “What’s the Problem with Political Authority,” Public Affairs Quarterly 30 (3): 239258.Google Scholar
Perry, Stephen 2013 “Political Authority and Political Obligation,” in Green, Leslie and Leiter, Brian (eds.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law, Vol. II, 174. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph 1985 “Authority and Justification,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1): 329.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph 1986 The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph 2006 “The Problem of Authority: Revisiting the Service Conception,” Minnesota Law Review 90 (4): 10031044.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph 2010 “On Respect, Authority, and Neutrality: A Response,” Ethics 120 (2): 279301.Google Scholar
Simmons, A. John 2005 “The Duty to Obey and Our Natural Moral Duties,” in Wellman, Christopher H. and John Simmons, A., Is There a Duty to Obey the Law?, 93196. NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Smart, J.C.C. 1956 “Extreme and Restricted Utilitarianism,” Philosophical Quarterly 6 (25): 344354.Google Scholar
Smith, M.B.E. 1973 “Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?,” The Yale Law Journal 82 (5): 950976.Google Scholar
Soper, Philip 2002 The Ethics of Deference: Learning from the Law’s Morals. NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wellman, Christopher H. 1996 “Liberalism, Samaritanism, and Political Legitimacy,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 25 (3): 211237.Google Scholar
Wellman, Christopher H. 2005 “Samaritanism and the Duty to Obey the Law,” in Wellman, Christopher H. and John Simmons, A., Is There a Duty to Obey the Law?, 389. NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wolff, Robert 1990 “The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy,” in Raz, Joseph (ed.), Authority, 2031. NY: New York University Press.Google Scholar