Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-zzh7m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T19:33:21.387Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

COMPROMISE AND ORIGINAL ACQUISITION: EXPLAINING RIGHTS TO THE ARCTIC

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 October 2015

Cara Nine*
Affiliation:
Philosophy, University College Cork

Abstract:

Up until now, political philosophy has explained the acquisition of natural resources, in one way or another, through the terms of human settlement. An agent acquires natural resources by moving into the geographic area that contains these resources. Even how we make claims to the ocean floor depends on settlement — claimants must be adjacent to settled land. This essay extends original acquisition theories so that they can respond to cases that do not presuppose any conditions of human settlement. I suggest that resource rights in the deep sea may be created, alternatively, through acts of compromise. Compromise can alleviate conflict, allowing for claimants to move beyond stalemate to acquire goods. It also allows for a large degree of flexibility in the specification of rights, and thereby can explain nontraditional rights over areas of migration. The tricky part of a theory that grants rights through agreement is explaining why external parties, those not part of the agreement, have a duty to respect those rights. A compromise under certain conditions, I argue, places all persons under a duty to respect the rights created by the compromise. Thus, when two parties compromise, they may acquire goods from the commons — creating a duty for all others to respect the parties’ rights over these goods. Importantly, rights created through compromise are constrained by a set of concerns for those excluded.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 United Nations Convention on the Law of the Sea (UNCLOS), December 10, 1982, http://www.un.org/depts/los/convention_agreements/texts/unclos/UNCLOS-TOC.htm, Part VI. A claim to up to 350 miles of seabed from a state's shore is also allowed.

2 Nine, Cara, “Resource Rights,” Political Studies 61, no. 2 (2013): 232–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3 Another limitation of this essay is its lack of engagement with the difference between collective and individual rights. I assume that collectives may be agents with the moral facility to acquire resources from the commons. Raz, Joseph, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Paperbacks, 1986)Google Scholar; Nine, Cara, Global Justice and Territory (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar

4 Locke, John, “The Second Treatise of Government” in Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration, (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2003 Google Scholar [1690]), chap. 5, sec. 27. (Hereafter, Treatise).

5 See a discussion in John Simmons, A., On the Edge of Anarchy: Locke, Consent, and the Limits of Society (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993), 27.Google Scholar

6 John Simmons, A., “On the Territorial Rights of States,” Philosophical Issues: Social, Political and Legal Philosophy 11 (2001): 300326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 Locke, Treatise, chap. 5, sec. 28.

8 Samuel Pufendorf, On The Duty of Man and Citizen According to the Natural Law (1673), ed. James Tully, trans. Michael Silverthorne (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) book ii, chap. 1, passage 11. (Hereafter, De Officio.)

9 Fumurescu, Alin, Compromise: A Political and Philosophical History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 221.

10 Pufendorf, De Officio, i.8.2.

11 Ibid., i.9.2.

12 Pufendorf, Samuel, De Jure Naturae et Gentium Libri Octo [1672], trans. C. H., and Oldfather, W. A. (New York: Oceana Publications, 1964)Google Scholar, iv. 4. 6. (Hereafter, DJNG).

13 Buckle, Stephen, Natural Law and the Theory of Property: Grotius to Hume (New York: Clarendon Oxford University Press, 2002), 102.Google Scholar

14 Pufendorf, DJNG iv.4.6.

15 Ibid., ii.3.15.

16 Pufendorf, De Officio, i.12.6.

17 This case is discussed in Stilz, Anna, “Occupancy Rights and the Wrong of Removal,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 41, no. 4 (2013): 324–56.Google Scholar

18 Kolers, Avery, “Justice, Territory and Natural Resources,” Political Studies 60 (2012): 269–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Moore, Margaret, “Natural Resources, Territorial Rights, and Global Distributive Justice,” Political Theory 40, no. 1 (2012 ): 84107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

19 I mean “productive” here in the literal sense. The land does not produce anything new of value, as would be the case in, for example, agricultural use.

20 Pufendorf, DJNG iv.4.4

21 Fumurescu, ibid., 195.

22 Lepora, Chiara, “On Compromise and Being Compromised,” The Journal of Political Philosophy 20, no. 1 (2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

23 Van Parijs, Philippe, “What Makes a Good Compromise?” Government and Opposition 47, no. 3 (2012): 479.Google Scholar

24 Goodin, Robert and Brennan, Geoffrey, “Bargaining over Beliefs” Ethics 111, no. 2 (2001).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

25 For a discussion of joint agreements and obligations, see Gilbert, Margaret, On Social Facts (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989), 380.Google Scholar

26 Margalit, Avishai, On Compromise and Rotten Compromises (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2010), 61.Google Scholar And, Bellamy, Richard, Liberalism and Pluralism: Towards a Politics of Compromise (New York: Routledge, 1999), 112.Google Scholar

27 Shue, Henry, Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy, second edition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980)Google Scholar; Hassoun, Nicole, Globalization and Global Justice: Shrinking Distance, Expanding Obligations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), 32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

28 Gauthier, David, Morals By Agreement, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), 16.Google Scholar

29 Lepora, ibid.

30 Andrews, J., Tracy, J., “Ecological and Historical Perspectives on Navajo Land Use and Settlement Patterns in Canyons De Chelly and Del Muerto,” Journal of Anthropological Research, vol. 47, no. 1 (1991): 3967.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

31 Nine, Cara, “Territory in a World of Limits: Exploring Claims to Oil and Ice,” in Environmental Philosophy: the Art of Life in a World of Limits . Advances in Environmentalism and Sustainable Justice, ed. Leonard, Liam (Bingley, UK, Emerald Press, 2013): 137–55.Google Scholar