We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
The chapter focuses on the modern history and character of the problem of the meaning of life and on why it was not posed explicitly in premodern times. It argues for the legitimacy of the modern problem and analyzes its terms: absurdity, meaning, and nihilism.
The chapter explores the biblical and Jewish concept of redemption, weighing the significance and meaning of human agency in achieving an ultimate amelioration of the human condition. It compares this Jewish valuation of agency with philosophical nihilism, which voids agency of value and hence of the possibility of real meaning.
The conclusion underscores the ineluctable dimension of value – and hence of the possibility of meaning – in all aspects of human knowing and doing. It argues against ceding to much authority to the “view from nowhere,” thereby rescuing the human world of ethical life from meaninglessness.
The Introduction analyzes the problem of how meaning in life can be lost using the examples of Tolstoy and Ecclesiastes. It studies how the Jewish tradition has grappled with the absurdist teaching of Ecclesiastes (Kohelet) over the centuries.
The chapter explores the biblical and Jewish concept of revelation as a ground for normative guidance and finds a paradox at the heart of the concept. It goes on to compare the paradox over normativity with contemporary secular philosophy’s discrepant approaches to whether meaning in life is subjectively or objectively grounded.
The chapter explores the biblical and Jewish concept of creation as a fusion of fact and value, underwriting a kind of Jewish-philosophical naturalism. It goes on to compare this to the science-based naturalism of contemporary secular philosophy and asks whether either view offers a sufficient basis for the meaning of life.
There is a lively discussion in contemporary philosophy that explores the meaning of life or, more modestly, meaning in life. Philosophers, for the most part, assume that religion has little to contribute to this inquiry. They believe that the Western religions, such as Judaism, have doctrinaire beliefs which have become implausible and can no longer satisfy the search for meaning. In this book, Alan L. Mittleman argues that this view is misconceived. He offers a presentation of core Jewish beliefs by using classical and contemporary texts that address the question of the meaning of life in a philosophical spirit. That spirit includes profound self-questioning and self-criticism. Such beliefs are not doctrinaire: Jewish sources, such as the biblical Book of Ecclesiastes, are, in fact, open to an absurdist reading. Mittleman demonstrates that both philosophy and Judaism are prone to ineliminable doubts and perplexities. Far from pre-empting a conversation, they promote honest dialogue.
Recommend this
Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this to your organisation's collection.