We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
Introduction
Necessity is a touchstone issue in the thought of Charles Peirce, not least because his pragmatist account of meaning relies upon modal terms. In contrast to the highly influential positivist currents in twentieth century philosophy in which “fact-stating” is paramount and put in the indicative mode, Peirce famously advised us to clarify the meaning of our terms using “would-bes,” not “will-bes” (CP 5.453; 5.457, 1905). Peirce's pragmatic maxim is that we must look to the practical effects of our concepts, and the practical effects he is concerned with are those that would occur under certain circumstances, not those that will actually occur. This effectively translates every meaningful term into a set of hypothetical conditionals. Thus, for instance, the fact that a table is hard means (among other things) that if I were to rest a dinner plate on it, the plate would not fall through to the floor (Misak 2013, 29ff; Hookway 1985).
Peirce thought deeply about necessity in all its aspects, and this is one of the areas of his work with as-yet-untapped insights. Discussions of necessity show up from his earliest philosophical writings based on Kant's logic and its table of 12 categories (one row of which is, of course, explicitly modal) to the end of his life, when he was working out a forest of distinctions in semiotics. His thoughts on modality also span a multitude of philosophical areas – informing his work on mathematics, logic, metaphysics, philosophy of science, and ethics.
His views on the topic have some intriguing features. His modal epistemology understands logical form as essentially structural, thus requiring representation by iconic or diagrammatic signs. Peirce made good on this commitment, developing the Existential Graphs, a diagrammatic logical notation, which is still understudied by mainstream logicians. His metaphysics differs from that of many nineteenth century peers in flatly denying “necessitarianism” (determinism) and arguing for real chance. He also distinguished between a kind of necessity that corresponds to the compulsion given by one billiard ball to another (which we might refer to in Peircean terms as a “Secondness Necessity”) and a kind of necessity that corresponds to a real universal (“Thirdness Necessity”), whereas in contemporary philosophy the two are routinely conflated.
Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this to your organisation's collection.