Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-17T19:07:47.249Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

7 - The Architecture of the Legal Mind

from II - Ontology and Epistemology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 April 2021

Bartosz Brożek
Affiliation:
Jagiellonian University, Krakow
Jaap Hage
Affiliation:
Universiteit Maastricht, Netherlands
Nicole Vincent
Affiliation:
Macquarie University, Sydney
Get access

Summary

This chapter aims at substantiating three claims: (1) that legal thinking consists in the interaction between three mental mechanisms: intuition (unconscious decision making), imagination (mental simulation), and thinking in language (theory-construction); (2) that legal epistemology has largely neglected the role of imagination in legal thinking, while it is imagination that provides ‘the missing link’ between unconscious decision making and thinking in language; and (3) that the picture of the legal mind which embraces intuition, imagination and language provides an explanation of the enduring and seemingly inconsistent threads in legal epistemology. I begin with a general overview of the existing theories in legal epistemology, distinguishing between formalism, dialecticism, coherentism and intuitivism. Along the way, I highlight the fact that these four philosophical stances offer different and sometimes mutually inconsistent perspectives on legal thinking. Subsequently, I analyse the three mechanisms at play in all types of reflection, including legal thinking: intuition, imagination and thinking in language. I try to explain what stands behind these labels, and argue that a lawyer cannot limit themselves to only some of these mechanisms in their cognitive efforts. Moreover, I venture to depict how the mechanisms in question interact in, and what they contribute to, legal decision making. In this context, I put special emphasis on the role of imagination, explaining how it provides a link between intuition and language.

Type
Chapter
Information
Law and Mind
A Survey of Law and the Cognitive Sciences
, pp. 138 - 164
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alexy, Robert. (1989). A Theory of Legal Argumentation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bargh, J. A., & Morsella, E. (2008). The Unconscious Mind. Perspectives on Psychological Science 3(1), 73–9.Google Scholar
Bergen, Benjamin. (2012). Louder Than Words. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Brożek, Bartosz. (2004). Defeasibility of Legal Reasoning. Kraków: Zakamycze.Google Scholar
Brożek, Bartosz. (2008). Rationality and Discourse: Towards a Normative Model of Applying Law. Warsaw: Wolters Kluwer.Google Scholar
Brożek, Bartosz. (2011). Beyond Interpretation. In Stelmach, J. & Schmidt, R. (eds.), Krakauer-Augsburger Rechtsstudien: Die Grenzen der rechtsdogmatischen Interpretation. Warsaw: Wolters Kluwer, pp. 1928.Google Scholar
Brożek, Bartosz. (2020). The Legal Mind: A New Introduction to Legal Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Byrne, Richard W. (1988). The Early Evolution of Creative Thinking: Evidence from Monkeys and Apes. In Mithen, Steven (ed.), Creativity in Human Evolution and Prehistory. London, Routledge, pp. 110–24.Google Scholar
Clark, Andy. (2005). Word, Niche, and Super-Niche: How Language Makes Minds Matter More. Theoria 54, 255–68.Google Scholar
Damasio, Antonio. (2006). Descartes’ Error. London: Vintage.Google Scholar
Damasio, A. R., Tranel, D., & Damasio, H. (1991). Somatic Markers and the Guidance of Behaviour: Theory and Preliminary Testing. In Levin, H. S., Eisenberg, H. M., Benton, A. L. (eds.), Frontal Lobe Function and Dysfunction. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 217–29.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. (1986). Law’s Empire. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul. (1993). Against Method. London & New York: Verso.Google Scholar
Friedman, Michael. (1974). Explanation and Scientific Understanding. The Journal of Philosophy 71(1), 519.Google Scholar
Guthrie, C., Rachlinski, J. J., & Wistrich, A. J. (2001). Inside the Judicial Mind. Cornell Law Review 86, 778830.Google Scholar
Hage, Jaap. (2000). Dialectical Models in Artificial Intelligence and Law. Artificial Intelligence and Law 8, 137–72.Google Scholar
Hage, Jaap. (2013). Three Kinds of Coherentism. In Araszkiewicz, M., Šavelka, J. (eds.), Coherence: Insights from Philosophy, Jurisprudence and Artificial Intelligence, Law and Philosophy Library, vol. 107. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 132.Google Scholar
Harper, Robert. (1904). The Code of Hammurabi. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hastie, R., Schkade, D. A., & Payne, J. W. (1999). Juror Judgments in Civil Cases: Effects of Plaintiff’s Requests and Plaintiff’s Identity on Punitive Damage Awards. Law and Human Behavior 23, 445–70.Google Scholar
Hutcheson, Joseph C., Jr. (1929). Judgment Intuitive. The Function of the Hunch in Judicial Decisions. Cornell Law Review 14(3), 274–88.Google Scholar
Kahneman, Daniel. (2011). Thinking, Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Kaufmann, Arthur. (1986). Vorüberlegungen zu einer juristischen Logik und Ontologie der Relationen: Grundlegung einer personalen Rechtstheorie. Rechtstheorie 17 (3), 257–76.Google Scholar
Kozhevnikov, Maria. (2007). Cognitive Styles in the Context of Modern Psychology: Toward an Integrated Framework of Cognitive Style. Psychological Bulletin 133(3), 464–81.Google Scholar
Kulesza, Jan. (2007). O pojmowaniu zaniechania w polskiej nauce prawa karnego. Czasopismo Prawa Karnego i Nauk Penalnych XI(2).Google Scholar
Langevoort, Donald C. (1998). Behavioral Theories of Judgment and Decision-Making in Legal Scholarship: A Literature Review. Vanderbilt Law Review 51, 14991540.Google Scholar
Lillard, Angeline. (1998). Ethnopsychologies: Cultural Variations in Theories of Mind. Psychological Bulletin 123, 332.Google Scholar
MacCormick, Neil. (1994). Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Magee, Bryan. (1997). Confessions of a Philosopher. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
McCaffery, E. J., Kahneman, D., & Spitzer, M. L. (1995). Framing the Jury: Cognitive Perspectives on Pain and Suffering Awards. Virginia Law Review 81(1341), 13411420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, M., & Peng, K. (1994). Culture and Cause: American and Chinese Attributions for Social and Physical Events. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 67(6), 949–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
The Oxford English Dictionary. (1989). 2nd edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Paivio, Allan. (2013). Mind and Its Evolution: A Dual Coding Theoretical Approach. New York: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers.Google Scholar
Peer, E., & Gamliel, E. (2013). Heuristics and Biases in Judicial Decisions. Court Review 49(2013), 114–18.Google Scholar
Perelman, Chaïm. (1955). How Do We Apply Reason to Values? Journal of Philosophy 52(26), 797802.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perelman, Chaïm, & Olbrechts-Tyteca, L. (1958). Traite de l’argumentation: La nouvelle rhetorique. Paris: Pressess Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Petrażycki, Leon. (2011). Law and Morality. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Pound, Roscoe. (1908). Mechanical Jurisprudence. Columbia Law Review 8, 605–23.Google Scholar
Prakken, Henry. (1997). Logical Tools for Modelling Legal Argument. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, Willard Orman, Van. (1969). Epistemology Naturalized. In Quine, Willard Van Orman, Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Reyes, R. M., Thompson, W. C., & Bower, G. H. (1980). Judgmental Biases Resulting from Differing Availabilities of Arguments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 3, 212.Google Scholar
Stelmach, Jerzy. (1991). Die Hermeneutische Auffassung der Rechtsphilosophie. Ebelsbach: Verlag Rolf Gremer.Google Scholar
Stelmach, Jerzy. (2003). Kodeks argumentacyjny dla prawników. Kraków: Zakamycze.Google Scholar
Stelmach, Jerzy. (2013). Uporczywe upodobanie. Olszanica, Poland: BOSZ.Google Scholar
Stelmach, J., & Brożek, B. (2006). Methods of Legal Reasoning. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Science 185(4157), 1124–31.Google Scholar
Zoll, Andrzej (ed.). (2016). Kodeks karny. Część szczególna. Tom III. Warsaw: Wolters Kluwer.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×