Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-02T07:49:39.620Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

P.HERC. 1384: A BOOK OF CHRYSIPPUS’ ON WAYS OF LIFE?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 August 2022

Graziano Ranocchia*
Affiliation:
Università di Pisa, Dipartimento di Filologia Letteratura e Linguistica (Pisa)/CNR-Istituto di Scienze del Patrimonio Culturale (Naples), Italy
*
*Corresponding author. Email: graziano.ranocchia@unipi.it
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

P.Herc. 1384 preserves an ethical work focusing on the wise man's lifestyle. This work, which had formerly been attributed to the Epicurean Philodemus, has recently been proven to be Stoic instead, and has been assigned to either an early or a second-century BC Cynicising Stoic philosopher. This article, while confirming the Stoic authorship of P.Herc. 1384, shows that it can only belong to Chrysippus or one of his immediate successors and brings forward new evidence in favour of Chrysippus himself. In particular, several arguments allow us to advance an identification with book 1 of his lost Peri biōn.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Cambridge Philological Society

P.Herc. 1384 is the upper part of a bookroll, which was unrolled using Piaggio's machine between 16 April and 15 May 1804. It consists of thirteen dark-grey and partially layered fragments of different sizes (max. 10.7 cm in height × max. 34.2 cm in length for a total extension of 2.39 m), which are distributed across five frames stored in the Officina dei Papiri Ercolanesi of the ‘Vittorio Emanuele III’ National Library of Naples.Footnote 1 It preserves the upper portion of fifty-one columns of text and contains – as far as we can judge – an ethical work having the wise man as its protagonist and focusing on whether he can become mad and angry, on whether he can fall in love, get drunk and engage in politics, and, finally, on his educational mission. In particular, the wise man is said to be exempt from madness (col. 1 Antoni) and (presumably) other irrational states such as dream delirium, drunkenness and unregulated love (cols. 2–5), to which consciousness and temperance are opposed (col. 4); political courage and audacity are commended (cols. 6–7); and the author praises the wise man's love for those making moral progress and distinguishes it from vulgar and shameful love (cols. 22–4). From col. 31 on we have an abrupt change of subject: the wise man's engagement in politics is described, with a focus on his rejection of trickery (col. 31) and his austerity (col. 32), his abnegation (cols. 32–3), his social and political virtues (cols. 36–7), his concern for future generations (cols. 40–1) and the philosophical education of youths (cols. 42–9). In this last regard, the usefulness of dialectic and physics, but also of medicine, geometry and poetry, is discussed (col. 44) and an enigmatic sharing of profits and goods (possibly between the master and his disciples) is alluded to (col. 45). The book closes with a quotation from Zeno of Citium consisting in the reworking of a famous Hesiodean passage (Op. 293–5), by which this philosopher highlights the superiority of learning from a good master over self-learning (col. 50).

Until the first comprehensive edition of the papyrus was published in 2012,Footnote 2 only fifteen columns of it (cols. 18–32) were known to scholarsFootnote 3 and only one column (col. 22) had been edited.Footnote 4 On the basis of the content of just this limited portion of the text, Wilhelm Crönert proposed to identify P.Herc. 1384 as Philodemus’ On Love (Περὶ ἔρωτος).Footnote 5 This identification, which endured among scholars until recently, was successfully questioned by the last editor of the papyrus, Agathe Antoni, who first suggested ascribing it to other works by the same authorFootnote 6 and then, in a subsequent contribution, proposed on various grounds to assign it to a Stoic author.Footnote 7 In particular, Gilles Dorival, who has co-authored the latter essay with Antoni, argued for the attribution of P.Herc. 1384 to Chrysippus on the basis of the occurrence in it (col. 38.1–5 Antoni) of a doxa (actually a chreia)Footnote 8 also reported by Stobaeus, according to which this philosopher, ‘when he was asked why he did not engage in politics, replied: “because if one does so badly, he displeases the gods; if [one does so] well, he displeases the citizens”’.Footnote 9 More specifically, since according to him a similar refusal to engage in politics was voiced in Chrysippus’ On Ways of Life (Περὶ βίων)Footnote 10 and On Things Which Are Chosen in Themselves (Περὶ τῶν δι’ αὑτὰ αἱρετῶν),Footnote 11 Dorival went so far as to advance a possible identification of P.Herc. 1384 with either of these works.Footnote 12 Finally, Antoni herself, in the framework of her critical edition of the whole papyrus, confirmed the Stoic inspiration of the work contained in it, which she identified as an ethical–political treatise – whose fil rouge would be the education of morally promising youths by the wise man – by either an early Stoic thinker such as Chrysippus or a second-century BC Cynicising Stoic philosopher, or otherwise someone standing halfway between the two.Footnote 13 However, in this last contribution, Antoni's former confidence in assigning P.Herc. 1384 to Chrysippus himself appears mitigated and, surprisingly, Dorival's hypothesis of its identification as a specific work by this philosopher is not taken up or even mentioned. We shall see below why.

Now, the arguments which, according to Antoni, would lead us to exclude an Epicurean and a Philodemean authorship for P.Herc. 1384 can be summarised as follows:

(a) in the book there is no trace of the structure typical of an anti-commentary, namely a summary and rebuttal of one's opponents’ views, of the sort characteristic of Philodemus’ and other Epicureans’ doctrinal treatises;Footnote 14

(b) there is no polemical approach or reference to opponents or opposing doctrines. As is widely known, the Epicureans were considered inveterate polemicists and philosophical polemic was seen as typical of their school.Footnote 15 In particular, the systematic refutation of the views of one's opponents as a dialectical means to build one's own philosophical position had been a well-known tool of the Epicurean argumentative method ever since Epicurus’ On Nature;Footnote 16

(c) the only exception to point (b) is represented by the polemical allusion to ‘those who [regard] pleasure as the end’ (col. 32.8–9). If these philosophers are to be identified as Epicureans, as seems likely, then the author of the book cannot be an Epicurean philosopher himself;Footnote 17

(d) there is no reference at all to any Epicurean authorities or doctrines, whereas in Philodemus the opposite is normally the case;Footnote 18

(e) the philosophical vocabulary is not specifically Epicurean or Philodemean, with the exception of certain words and expressions belonging to the Hellenistic philosophical lingua franca;Footnote 19

(f) the extensive use and range of the poetic authors quoted appear to be distant from the Epicurean and Philodemean usage;Footnote 20

(g) from a stylistic point of view, the author would not appear to be concerned with avoiding hiatus, in contrast to Philodemus, who notoriously makes a systematic effort to avoid it.Footnote 21

Conversely, among those features which, according to Antoni, hint at a Stoic and Chrysippean authorship for P.Herc. 1384, we may cite the following:

(i) the technical philosophical vocabulary, which appears to be Stoic and, more specifically, Chrysippean. Among the relevant lexemes, Antoni mentions ὁ νοῦν ἔχων (col. 24.3), one of the Stoic designations of the wise man, περιστάσεις or ‘circumstances’ (col. 1.5–6),Footnote 22 ἐπιστροφή or ‘attention’ (col. 3.5–6),Footnote 23 ἀναστροφή or ‘conduct’ (col. 4.2),Footnote 24 προκόπτοντες or ‘those making moral progress’ (col. 24.6–7),Footnote 25 καθήκουσα or ‘appropriate’ (col. 25.5),Footnote 26 κοινὸς λόγος or ‘common reason’ (col. 27.9),Footnote 27 ἀκολουθητικοί or ‘capable of following’ (col. 42.4–5),Footnote 28 ὀρθὸς νόμος or ‘right law’ (col. 42.4–5 – for Antoni a possible combination of κοινὸς νόμος ‘universal law’ and ὀρθὸς λόγος ‘right reason’),Footnote 29 πρόνοια or ‘providence’ (col. 42.6)Footnote 30 and ἀφιλοτίμως or ‘without ambition’ (col. 46.2).Footnote 31

(ii) the extensive use and specific choice of the literary authors quoted (from Hesiod to Euripides via Solon and Ibycus), which fit in particularly well with Chrysippus’ literary usage. According to our sources, this philosopher's works, differently from Epicurus’, were full of poetic quotations, particularly from Euripides, an author who played a distinctive role in the works of early Stoic thinkers, and especially of Chrysippus himself;Footnote 32

(iii) the commendatory quotation from the Stoic Zeno of Citium, reported by both Diogenes Laertius (7.25–6 = Zeno Cit. fr. 1.5 SVF) and Proclus (ad Hes. Op. 291 = fr. 1.235 SVF), which closes the book (col. 50);Footnote 33

(iv) the reference to mythical exempla such as Odysseus and Philoctetes – two Stoic ‘heroes’ – (cols. 31–2) and, above all, the moral idealisation of Heracles, the patron saint of the Cynics, who also played a central role in early Stoicism (col. 30);Footnote 34

(v) the exaltation of πόνος (cols. 6.3, 32.3, 34.2)Footnote 35 and the praise of ἔρως as an element of social cohesion (col. A), which are typical of Stoicism;Footnote 36

(vi) some stylistic features such as the frequent use of the syntagm τὰ παραπλήσια governing a demonstrative pronoun in the dative (cols. 1.10, 26.2 and 8, 41.1) and sequences of adverbs such as φρον]ί̣μως | [κ]αὶ εὐλαβῶ[ς οὐδὲ] πο|λεμικῶς (col. 7.2–4), which were typical of Chrysippus;Footnote 37

(vii) the likeness of the hand which drafted P.Herc. 1384 to that of P.Herc. 1020, which contains a Stoic text devoted to dialectics and centred on the wise man;Footnote 38

(viii) the intriguing thematic and stylistic similarities with P.Herc. 1158, a likely Stoic text;Footnote 39

(ix) the occurrence of a Chrysippean chreia concerning the refusal to engage in politics, also reported by Stobaeus (Flor. 4.4.29 Hense = Chrysippus fr. 3.694 SVF) and mentioned above (col. 38.1–5);Footnote 40

(x) the presence in the Herculanean collection of a small nucleus of Stoic and specifically Chrysippean papyri such as P.Herc. 1020, 307, 1421, 1038 and 1380.Footnote 41

From the above arguments Antoni draws a first, provisional, conclusion (1): ‘Since there are undoubtedly Stoic elements in P.Herc. 1384 which are proper to Chrysippus, it now seems much more plausible that the author of the roll was an adherent of the Stoa, who was contemporary with, or later than, Chrysippus.’Footnote 42 To that effect, she resumes as a main argument point (ix) above, viz. the presence in the papyrus of a Chrysippean chreia (col. 38). However, given the rejection later in the text of physics and dialectics as useless (col. 44) – an assertion which is patently incompatible with Chrysippus’ teachingFootnote 43 – Antoni immediately reconsiders her initial conclusion by suggesting (2) that ‘a similar refusal would fit better with second-century BC Stoicism, which recovered the Cynic heritage and maybe also the criticism of “encyclopaedic” culture and those disciplines not directly related to the moral good’.Footnote 44 For Antoni, second-century BC Stoic thinkers rediscovered Cynic moral teaching (and, in particular, the praise of πόνος it entailed), taking it as the most authentic foundation of Stoic ethics.Footnote 45 Finally, in order to fit (1) with (2), she advances the hybrid conclusion (3) that ‘the author of the treatise preserved by P.Herc. 1384 might be a Stoic author …, who by retrieving Chrysippean elements, incorporated therein elements of Socratic and Cynic inspiration’.Footnote 46

Antoni's argumentation, as summarised above, is intriguing and challenging. To be sure, some arguments (points a–b, d–f and iv–vi above) are not as compelling as others. Besides, other points could have been argued better.Footnote 47 Finally, further evidence can possibly be added to points (i) and (vi).Footnote 48 Instead, what is almost completely missing in Antoni's account (except for the exaltation of πόνος and the praise of ἔρως as an element of social cohesion – two typically Stoic commonplaces highlighted at point v) is a philosophical comparison between P.Herc. 1384 and the Stoic sources concerning the wise man's behaviour and lifestyle.Footnote 49 But, in principle, points (c) (the critical allusion to ‘those who [regard] pleasure as the end’ – col. 32.8–9 – and who must be identified as hedonistic philosophers)Footnote 50, (i) (the philosophical vocabulary) and (iii) (the laudatory quotation from Zeno of Citium, which closes the book – col. 50) alone are enough to exclude an Epicurean authorship for P.Herc. 1384. Yet even points (i) and (iii) on their own are sufficient to prove a Stoic authorship. As far as the former is concerned, maybe none of the philosophically significant lexemes detectable in the papyrus, taken alone, can stricto sensu be regarded as exclusively Stoic, even though several of them were mostly used by Stoic authors with a technical meaning, while others (for instance, ἀκολουθητικός + dative and ἀξίωμα) were only employed among philosophers by Aristotle and the Stoics. However, their mutual combination in an intrinsically coherent lexical system identifies a well-defined language which can only be Stoic. So, there can be no doubt about the Stoic authorship of P.Herc. 1384.

As for Antoni's conclusions, these are questionable for a number of reasons. First, the presence in the papyrus of a chreia explicitly attributed to Chrysippus by Stobaeus (col. 38.1–5)Footnote 51 is not sufficient per se to argue that P.Herc. 1384 was authored precisely by this Stoic philosopher. The surviving text of the column does not allow us to say with certainty whether the chreia is here advanced in the first person by the author himself, or whether it is a quotation from Chrysippus. In the latter case, the author obviously cannot be Chrysippus himself. Conversely, the rejection in the papyrus of physics and dialectics as useless (col. 44.1–14)Footnote 52 – a claim rightly regarded by Antoni as contrasting with Chrysippus’ philosophyFootnote 53 – is not advanced by the author in his own voice, as Antoni seems to believe, but is ascribed by him to another person. The presence of ἔγρα̣φ̣ε̣ ‘he wrote’ immediately before (in line 3) and of the optative οὐδ’ ἂν γέν[οι]το χρή|σιμα (lines 6–7), whose grammatical subject is δι[α]λε|κτικὰ … κα[ὶ] φυσικά (lines 4–5), clearly reveals that the author is here reporting, instead of his own position, that of another philosopher. So, this cannot be taken as a proof against Chrysippus’ authorship of P.Herc. 1384, which remains perfectly possible.

The above shows that Antoni's conclusions (2) and (3) are not logically compelling. As far as (2) is concerned, even assuming that the rejection of dialectic and physics was advanced by the author himself, this would not necessarily make him an exponent of second-century BC Cynicising Stoicism, as Antoni suggests. It is well known that, within the Stoa, such a rejection was advocated for the first time as early as the morally rigorist philosopher Aristo of Chios (died post-230 BC), a pupil of Zeno, who excluded physics and logic (whereof dialectic was considered a part)Footnote 54 from philosophy and confined the latter to ethics.Footnote 55 Besides, second-century BC Stoicism was obviously not restricted to this Cynicising and morally rigorist position, as Antoni surprisingly assumes. This was indeed the position of Zenodotus and Apollodorus of Seleucia, two disciples of Diogenes of Babylon, who in the latter half of the same century fostered a return to ‘the most manly Stoic philosophy’ or a ‘shortcut to virtue’, which they identified with Cynicism and Zeno's earlier philosophical reflection and traced back to Antisthenes through the so-called Cynic–Stoic succession.Footnote 56 But this was just one of the two main and mutually conflicting positions attested within the school in this period,Footnote 57 and certainly not the most authoritative one. As is well known, one of the most prominent exponents of so-called ‘Middle Stoicism’,Footnote 58 Panaetius, who revised Stoic teaching in several respectsFootnote 59 and was considered open to Platonic and Aristotelian influences,Footnote 60 was, on the contrary, hostile to Cynicising Stoicism and, in particular, Cynic ἀναίδεια. While promoting a morally moderate and universally accessible kind of Stoicism,Footnote 61 he did his best to distance himself philosophically from this rigorist tendency and, historically speaking, from the original κυνισμός of the school.Footnote 62 For the same reasons another prominent ‘Middle-Stoic’ philosopher, Posidonius, seems to have dismissed Zeno himself as unworthy.Footnote 63

Likewise, even if Antoni's conclusion (3) were true, it would make no sense from a historico-philosophical point of view. Historically speaking, early Stoics after Chrysippus could never have adopted such a syncretistic position. Philosophers such as Zeno of Tarsus, Diogenes of Babylon and Antipater, while developing Stoic teaching in several ways,Footnote 64 essentially followed in Chrysippus’ footsteps.Footnote 65 At the same time, they were anything but Cynicising or morally rigorist Stoics.Footnote 66 Conversely, those Stoics, such as Zenodotus and Apollodorus, who after Antipater tried to recover Cynic and early Zenonian moral rigorism could only do so in contrast to Chrysippus, the one philosopher, within early Stoicism, who by confuting Aristo's morally rigorist position tried to eliminate this original Zenonian standpoint from within the school.Footnote 67 Finally, ‘Middle Stoics’, such as Panaetius and Posidonius but also Mnesarchus and Boethus, who developed or, in some respects, even rethought Chrysippean StoicismFootnote 68 were, for this very reason, neither stricto sensu Chrysippean nor by any means Cynicising or morally rigorist Stoic thinkers.Footnote 69 Hence – to the best of my knowledge – the philosophical stance that has been proposed by Antoni for the author of P.Herc. 1384 in her conclusion (3) – ‘the author of the treatise preserved by P.Herc. 1384 might be a Stoic author …, who by retrieving Chrysippean elements, incorporated therein elements of Socratic and Cynic inspiration’ – was never favoured by any Stoic follower, at least prior to Philodemus.

If Antoni's conclusions (2) and (3) are unfounded, then only conclusion (1) remains valid: ‘Since there are undoubtedly Stoic elements in P.Herc. 1384 which are proper to Chrysippus, … the author of the roll was an adherent of the Stoa, who was contemporary with, or later than, Chrysippus.’ Here too some observations are called for. If, as Antoni suggests, P.Herc. 1384 contains Chrysippean elements and if its author is a contemporary of Chrysippus (281/277–208/204 BC),Footnote 70 then the most reasonable solution is to conclude that he is Chrysippus himself. That this author is a Chrysippean Stoic philosopher contemporary with Chrysippus but different from him is only theoretically possible, but it is historically fairly unlikely.Footnote 71 If, instead, he is to be identified as a Chrysippean philosopher later than Chrysippus, he could be one of the prominent early Stoics who followed him and remained – though with some differencesFootnote 72 – essentially faithful to his thought, that is Zeno of Tarsus, Diogenes of Babylon or Antipater. After all, as we have seen, ‘Middle Stoics’ such as Panaetius and Posidonius, on the one hand, and Cynicising Stoics such as Zenodotus and Apollodorus, on the other, were not strictly Chrysippean and can even be thought of as anti-Chrysippean Stoic thinkers. But even in the case of the ‘faithful’ Chrysippeans certain restrictions are probably to be applied.Footnote 73 Be that as it may, it is difficult to imagine that the author of P.Herc. 1384 is a Stoic philosopher prior to Chrysippus, because – as far as we know – some terms found in this text are not attested before Chrysippus, or were probably introduced into Stoic philosophy by him.Footnote 74 In summary, the range of possibilities is quite narrow. We must be dealing here with either Chrysippus himself or one of his immediate successors: Zeno of Tarsus, Diogenes of Babylon or – less likely – Antipater.Footnote 75

Now, two of Antoni's arguments (points vii and x above), if improved, can help us narrow the focus down on the possibility of a specifically Chrysippean authorship for P.Herc. 1384. As far as point (x) is concerned, we know that, beside this papyrus, another six Stoic papyri have survived in the Herculanean library, a collection which is otherwise mostly devoted to Epicurean authors and topics.Footnote 76 Four of them, which still bear the corresponding end-title (subscriptio) with the name of the author (Chrysippus), preserve works precisely by this Stoic philosopher. They are P.Herc. 1421 and 1038, which contain the first and the second book of his On Providence;Footnote 77 P.Herc. 307, which preserves his Logical Enquiries;Footnote 78 and P.Herc. 1380, which preserves a logical-linguistic work, On the Elements of Speech.Footnote 79 To these, another two papyri are to be added, namely P.Herc. 1158 and 1020, which, just like P.Herc. 1384, do not preserve any subscriptio but contain works of Stoic and – at least in the latter case – most probably Chrysippean authorship.Footnote 80 Now, the existence in the library of a nucleus of Stoic papyri,Footnote 81 of which most are certainly, and another one is likely to be, by Chrysippus, suggests, for reasons of coherence, that all of them – including P.Herc. 1384 – are by the same Stoic author and that, in reality, this surviving cluster of Stoic papyri belonged to a specifically Chrysippean section of Philodemus’ library.Footnote 82 The importance of Chrysippus as the most renowned representative of the Epicureans’ rival school and, hence, as their philosophical opponent par excellence, whose thought must be properly known in order to be refuted – or, as in Philodemus’ case, even appropriated – has already been highlighted by scholars. In particular, the presence of some Chrysippean treatises in the Herculanean library might have served as an authoritative textual basis for the composition of some of Philodemus’ works.Footnote 83 This also explains why several treatises by Chrysippus are either amply quoted or paraphrased or otherwise circumstantially alluded to by Philodemus in treatises such as On Stoics and On Anger.Footnote 84

As for Antoni's point (vii), the hand of P.Herc. 1384 – a unicum in the Herculanean collection,Footnote 85 which has escaped Guglielmo Cavallo's classificationFootnote 86 and has been dated by Antoni to the second quarter of first century BC – bears a close likeness to that of another graphically atypical Stoic papyrus, viz. P.Herc. 1020,Footnote 87 which has been assigned by Cavallo to his ‘Gruppo H’ (post mid-first century BC).Footnote 88 This similarity strongly suggests that these two books belong to the same editorial project.Footnote 89 Now, P.Herc. 1020 contains not a generically Stoic work – as Antoni contendsFootnote 90 – but an early Stoic text on the wise man's cognitive, moral and dialectical virtues,Footnote 91 which has been attributed on solid grounds by its editor princeps, Hans von Arnim, to either Chrysippus or, possibly, one of his immediate successors, Diogenes of Babylon and Antipater.Footnote 92 The assigning of P.Herc. 1020 to Chrysippus himself was confirmed shortly after von Arnim by Max PohlenzFootnote 93 and Bruno KeilFootnote 94 on the basis of a passage from Isidorus of PelusiumFootnote 95 – which escaped von Arnim – where Chrysippus is explicitly credited with a definition of philosophy as ‘the exercise of the correctness of logos’, coinciding with that provided by the author of P.Herc. 1020 at col. 108.12–15 (ἐπ̣ι̣|τήδε̣υσις λόγου ὀρ[θ]ό|τητο̣ς). Moreover, in more recent years Michele Alessandrelli and myself, in the framework of a re-edition of von Arnim's text (= cols. 104–112 Alessandrelli–Ranocchia) based on our personal inspection of the original papyrus and propaedeutic to its first comprehensive edition,Footnote 96 have offered a new set of further arguments in favour of a specifically Chrysippean authorship for it.Footnote 97 So, even though in principle cases like this are always open to doubt (as mentioned, in P.Herc. 1020 no title survives), there remains no or very little room for acceptable alternatives to Chrysippus.Footnote 98 Now, if P.Herc. 1020 is by Chrysippus and if P.Herc. 1384 probably belongs to the same editorial project or work, it is reasonable to conclude that the latter is by the same author, that is, again, Chrysippus.

Another argument in favour of Chrysippus must be added to this picture. Diogenes Laertius tells us that ‘while Chrysippus holds that virtue can be lost, Cleanthes maintains that it cannot. According to the former it may be lost in consequence of drunkenness or melancholy; the latter takes it to be inalienable owing to the certainty of our mental apprehension.’Footnote 99 For Chrysippus, differently from Cleanthes, in order to avoid losing virtue and, hence, wisdom – whether permanently or temporarily we do not know – the wise man must pay ‘special attention’ (πλείων ἐπιστροφή) or ‘rational attention’ (λογικὴ ἐπιστροφή) to his assents ‘so that they take place, not randomly, but with understanding’.Footnote 100 So, for instance, he must avoid giving his assent to the representation ‘drinking a lot is enjoyable’ if he wants to avoid getting drunk and keep his self-consciousness and his inner rationality; or, he should avoid granting his assent to the representation ‘having much sex is exciting’ if he wishes to avoid falling desperately in love and to maintain his self-control and his inner consistency. By doing so, he will maintain his hegemonikon unaltered and firm and will keep on being virtuous and wise. In the opposite case, he will undermine his reasoning faculty and will lose both virtue and wisdom. Now, in P.Herc. 1384 we find, right within the section of the book devoted to madness, drunkenness, dream delirium and unregulated love (cols. 15) – all irrational states which imply losing one's reason – the construction ἐπιστρ[ε|φομέ]νων ἐπιστρο|[φὴν δ]έχεσθαι ‘to receive attention from people who are attentive to (something)’ (col. 3.4–6), a figura etymologica whose subject – given the contextFootnote 101 – cannot but be the wise man.Footnote 102 This expression, when taken together with the main assumption of the section, according to which ‘the wise man neither abandons himself to madness … nor other states of this kind’ (col. 1.1–4), and the claims according to which drunkenness is an extremely alien state (col. 4.2–3) and ‘makes one a fool’ (col. 5.4–6), suggests that in order to avoid alienating himself from his own nature, losing his reason and becoming a fool, the wise man will have to make sure not to abandon himself to excessive drinking, or – to put it differently – not to grant his assent to the representation ‘drinking a lot is enjoyable’. But alienating oneself from one's own nature, losing one's reason and becoming a fool means losing one's virtue, and this corresponds exactly to the position typical of Chrysippus that was briefly discussed above. In other words, in our papyrus the concrete risk that the wise man may lose his virtue seems to represent the conceptual framework which justifies the special care he must exercise in the case of situations, or false representations, of this sort.Footnote 103

So, it is reasonable to conclude that, just like P.Herc. 1020, P.Herc. 1384 is by Chrysippus himself. But, if so, to which of his works could it belong? To try to answer this question, it is necessary to refer again to P.Herc. 1020. In our new edition of the last eight columns of it (cols. 104–12 Alessandrelli–Ranocchia), Michele Alessandrelli and I have proposed on several grounds that we identify this papyrus as a book of Chrysippus’ On Ways of Life (Περὶ βίων), a lost treatise in four books attested by both Diogenes LaertiusFootnote 104 and Plutarch.Footnote 105 This possibility should be taken into serious consideration for a number of reasons. The first reason is the occurrence, in one of Plutarch's direct quotations from this work,Footnote 106 of the very rare Chrysippean term εὐαπόσειστος ‘so as to be easily shaken off’,Footnote 107 which is attested in Greek literature only here and in P.Herc. 1020, col. 104.8. The second is provided by the frequent allusions to the Stoic wise man detectable in Plutarch's and Diogenes Laertius’ direct quotations from this work.Footnote 108 They are descriptions of the lifestyle typical of the wise man in all the various public and private spheres, which appear very similar to those contained in P.Herc. 1020.Footnote 109 Interestingly – and independently of the case of P.Herc. 1020 – in 2007 Gilles Dorival proposed to identify P.Herc. 1384 too as a book of Chrysippus’ On Ways of Life on the basis of some supposed thematic analogies between the two texts concerning the wise man's political (in)activity.Footnote 110

But what would a work On Ways of Life have looked like? As I have shown in a recent contribution,Footnote 111 the philosophical genre Περὶ βίων was essentially different from the ‘biographical’ or anecdotal one.Footnote 112 It was mostly cultivated by Epicureans and Stoics, but also – at least from the late Hellenistic period onwards, and under the influence of Stoicism – by Academic and Peripatetic philosophers. By cross-analysing the information inferable from other sourcesFootnote 113 and the surviving fragments of Epicurus’ and Chrysippus’ On Ways of Life – the most famous and most representative examples of this genre – we may conclude with a fair degree of confidence that philosophical works Περὶ βίων had the following characteristics: (a) they were moral pieces of writing belonging to the practical or applied section of ethics, rather than proper doctrinal treatises; (b) their protagonist was the wise man; (c) their subject matter consisted in issues related to the wise man's way of life in the most diverse fields of his individual and social action; this included both general lifestyles, which were described and contrasted, and more specific topics or courses of action such as whether the wise man will engage in politics or rhetoric, live together with kings and obey the laws, marry, do business and make money, play the Cynic and beg, fall in love, get drunk or commit suicide, how he will behave with pupils, and whether he will be knowledgeable or a good dialectician or orator; (d) their target was generally (but not always) the non-wise who, in this way, were furnished with an exemplary code of conduct to which to conform their lives, so as to make progress towards (or preserve) wisdom; (e) their purpose was to supply principles enabling the pursuit (or preservation) of the end, however this may have been understood.

In particular, we know from Plutarch that Chrysippus’ On Ways of Life, while comprising different books and covering a wide range of topics, was a ‘unitary treatise’ (μία σύνταξις), which is probably to say an uninterrupted exposition having the same protagonist and preserving the same narrative scheme.Footnote 114 In particular, the first book focused on the possibility for the wise man to be, or live with, a king, to fight for a sovereignFootnote 115 and make profit by being in power, cultivating friendships and engaging in politics.Footnote 116 It also discussed the wise man's relationship with his pupils with respect to teaching and its remuneration,Footnote 117 the possibility for him to pay for doctors when ill and to commit suicide once deprived of his senses,Footnote 118 the issues of whether he will suffer injusticeFootnote 119 and of whether – and with whom – he will fall in love,Footnote 120 and his political activity for the moral elevation of his fellow citizens.Footnote 121 The second book dealt again with his concern about profit-making.Footnote 122 We know nothing about the third book. The fourth book dwelt on the philosopher's life in the school, which was critically equated with an existence full of pleasures and free from political distress,Footnote 123 on the philosophical training of his pupils,Footnote 124 on the wise man's doing nothing or little or what is proper to him,Footnote 125 but also on epistemological and dialectical issues, especially his use of anti-logical arguments and how to tackle the questions raised by Megarics and other insidious opponents in dialectical discussions.Footnote 126 This picture clearly shows that the main characteristic of the work was to describe the wise man's behaviour in every life situation. In any case, Chrysippus’ Περὶ βίων – the only work with this title to have been written by a Stoic philosopher – must have enjoyed considerable popularity in antiquity, since a specific section Περὶ βίων is included – and described with Stoic terms and examples – in the Stoic-influenced divisions of practical ethics by Eudorus of Alexandria and Philo of Larissa reported in the ethical doxography conventionally attributed to Arius Didymus.Footnote 127

Now, already in 2004, when she still believed in a Philodemean authorship for P.Herc. 1384, Antoni noticed that its text, while having the same protagonist, was arranged into different thematic sections.Footnote 128 This fact led Antoni to propose a possible identification of the papyrus as a book of Philodemus’ On Ways of Life (Περὶ ἠθῶν καὶ βίων), a treatise which includes at least On Frank Speech (P.Herc. 1471).Footnote 129 As mentioned, in 2007 Dorival – in the study co-authored by Antoni – tentatively proposed that we identify it, once again, with a work On Ways of Life, but this time by Chrysippus. In particular, our papyrus would correspond to book 4 of this treatise because here the author, as in P.Herc. 1384, maintains that the wise man does not engage in politics, concerns himself with few things and only minds his own business.Footnote 130 Although Dorival's argument for this kind of identification is different from Antoni's,Footnote 131 and is essentially flawed,Footnote 132 his intuition that P.Herc. 1384 may belong to this Chrysippean work, together with Antoni's suspicion that it may fall into the philosophical genre Περὶ βίων, seems to go in the right direction.

Like any other work Περὶ βίων and like Chrysippus’ treatise by the same title, P.Herc. 1384 is not a real doctrinal treatise, but looks like a text on descriptive ethics with a prescriptive goal in the background. As we have seen above, its protagonist is the wise man, and the subjects it deals with are topics related to the wise man's mode of life in the various fields of his individual and social action. Its target are those who are receptive towards the teaching of a proficient master (col. 50), namely those progressing towards virtue or, to put it otherwise, the philosopher's pupils in the school.Footnote 133 From the above points it follows that its purpose, albeit not directly discernible, must deal with moral progress (col. 24) and the pursuit of wisdom. Just like Chrysippus’ Περὶ βίων, P.Herc. 1384 is an uninterrupted exposition arranged into different thematic sections. Worth noting is the fact that three of the main topics it presents – those concerning the erotic, the political and the educational activity of the wise man – recur in the latter text as well, and in a similar fashion. In particular, in col. 24 of P.Herc. 1384 the wise man is said to cultivate love for moral progressors (τοῖς τε προκεκοφόσιν ἐπιβαλ{λ}εῖν τοῦτο [sc. ἔρως]), just as in Chrysippus’ Περὶ βίων (book 1) he is said ‘to love those youths who show a natural disposition to virtue (τὴν πρὸς ἀρετὴν εὐφυΐαν) in their outward appearance’.Footnote 134 In cols. 31–41, the wise man's active political engagement for the sake of future generations is described, just as in Περὶ βίων (book 1) he is said to engage in politics to stop vice and incite to virtue,Footnote 135 to the point that, if possible, he will become a king or live together with a ruler and fight on his side.Footnote 136 These claims are only apparently contradicted by the aforementioned chreia reported in P.Herc. 1384 whereby someone (most probably Chrysippus)Footnote 137 confesses that he ‘will not engage in politics because, if one does so well, he displeases the citizens’, but if [one does so] badly, he displeases the gods (col. 38.1–5).Footnote 138 In fact, this text alludes to Chrysippus’ personal choice of life,Footnote 139 which need not necessarily coincide with the wise man's way of life as such.Footnote 140 Even if it did, the Stoics admitted of three preferable ways of life (kingly, political and scientific), which are either equally worthy of being chosen by the wise man or are hierarchically ordered so that the kingly and the political life generally take precedence over the scientific one. So, for Stoicism every wise man is free to choose for himself which of these three different lifestyles is best suited to him, according to his own inclinations and the different circumstances of his life. In particular, if he is not a king himself or if it is impossible for him to engage in politics, he will gladly choose the scientific life (to be identified with the scholastic one), being aware that, whichever way of life he adopts, only the rational life or life according to virtue is preferable in itself.Footnote 141 So, this chreia does not entail any contradiction whatsoever with the Stoic wise man's primary engagement in politics,Footnote 142 as described in both P.Herc. 1384 and Chrysippus’ Περὶ βίων, and in other ancient sources.Footnote 143 Finally, in cols. 42–9 of our papyrus, the wise man's educational mission and the philosophical training of his disciples are illustrated, just as in Chrysippus’ On Ways of Life (possibly, again, book 1) his teaching activity and relationship with his pupils are discussed.Footnote 144 In both cases, a reference to the profit deriving from this kind of activity is made: in P.Herc. 1384, the author speaks of a share of profits and benefits, which given the context must refer to the relationship between master and pupils (col. 45.1–11);Footnote 145 in the Περὶ βίων, Chrysippus discusses whether the wise man/master will expect to be paid for his lectures in advance or later on, on the basis of a specific agreement.Footnote 146

What cannot escape the reader is that these three claims all come from the same book of Chrysippus’ On Ways of Life, namely book 1 (although this is only a hypothesis in the case of the third claim).Footnote 147 Bearing in mind all the analogies between P.Herc. 1384 and both the philosophical genre Περὶ βίων and Chrysippus’ work by this title briefly discussed above (i.e. the fact that they share the same practical–ethical character, protagonist, range of topics, narrative scheme, target readership and purpose, along with very similar claims), the presence of some major topics and statements concerning the erotic, political and educational activity of the wise man in both P.Herc. 1384 and book 1 of Chrysippus’ Περὶ βίων is sufficient evidence to propose a possible identification of our papyrus with this very book. One may wonder why these conceptual analogies are not supported by any textual overlap between the fragments of that book and P.Herc. 1384. But, in the first case, Diogenes Laertius’ testimony cannot by any means be regarded as a proper quotation from Chrysippus’ Περὶ βίων, because it is simultaneously ascribed by him to Zeno's Republic and Apollodorus’ Ethics.Footnote 148 The second and the third Chrysippean testimonies, by contrast, do contain some direct quotations from book 1 of Περὶ βίων. However, given the small extent of the surviving text in P.Herc. 1384 – between one and two tenths of the original text, according to AntoniFootnote 149 – a possible textual match between Chrysippus’ Περὶ βίων and this piece of writing should be regarded, statistically speaking, as a very fortunate coincidence.Footnote 150

A possible identification of P.Herc. 1384 with book 1 of Chrysippus’ On Ways of Life is reinforced by its comparison with P.Herc. 1020, which, as we know, probably belongs to the same editorial project and has recently been ascribed, on several grounds, to book 4 of the same treatise.Footnote 151 Without once again entering into the discussion of why this should be the case, suffice it here to say that its genre, protagonist, thematic variety and narrative scheme are the same as in the philosophical genre Περὶ βίων, Chrysippus’ work by the same title and P.Herc. 1384. In particular, the main topics inferable from the portion of P.Herc. 1020 edited so far (cols. 104–12 Alessandrelli–Ranocchia)Footnote 152 – the wise man's cognitive, moral and dialectical virtues – fit in well with what we know about book 4 of Chrysippus’ On Ways of Life. Just as in the latter the author addresses epistemological and dialectical issues, such as the use of anti-logical arguments and how to tackle the questions raised by Megarics and other opponents in dialectical discussions,Footnote 153 so in P.Herc. 1020 the author dwells on epistemology (cols. 104–8 and 112), dialectic and, in particular, on how to dialectically engage with formidable adversaries (cols. 109–10). In addition, just as in Περὶ βίων book 4, where Chrysippus discusses philosophy in general and its parts,Footnote 154 so in P.Herc. 1020 the author provides a masterly definition of philosophy by contrasting it with one of its sub-sections, viz., again, dialectic (col. 108.12–27).Footnote 155 So, if P.Herc. 1384 and 1020 both belong to this Chrysippean treatise, they must coincide with books 1 and 4 respectively.

To be sure, here we are not dealing with strictly deductive pieces of proof, but with various kinds of arguments, whose synergistic combination points in the same direction, by corroborating this attribution hypothesis from different sides (philosophical, thematic, lexical, literary, stylistic and palaeographical). One only wonders where the two remaining books (books 2 and 3) of Chrysippus’ Περὶ βίων may have ended up and why they have not yet been identified in the Herculanean collection. As in the case of Epicurus’ 37-book On Nature and several multi-volume works by Philodemus – of which several books, albeit not all, have been preserved – their loss must be considered merely accidental. However, as experience suggests, nothing rules out the possibility that they will be identified in the future.Footnote 156 If this argumentation is correct, the Stoic or, better, Chrysippean section of Philodemus’ library also included, among the various works mentioned above, a complete copy of Chrysippus’ famous treatise On Ways of Life.

Footnotes

I would like to thank Michele Alessandrelli and the two anonymous referees for contributing in various ways to the improvement of this article.

1 For information concerning the unrolling and the state of conservation of P.Herc. 1384 see Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 25–7 and 37.

2 See Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b).

3 These had been transcribed from the original by the Neapolitan draughtsman Francesco Celentano and had subsequently been engraved by Domenico Casanova, Ferdinando Ventrella and Luigi Corazza in VH2 (1876), 52–66. The original drawings are kept in folder no. 1384 in the Officina dei Papiri Ercolanesi of the ‘Vittorio Emanuele III’ National Library, Naples. On the information concerning the drawings of P.Herc. 1384 see Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 27–8.

4 By Sbordone (Reference Sbordone1965) 311–12.

5 See Crönert (Reference Crönert1906) 35 n. 183.

6 I.e. either On Rhetoric (Περὶ ῥητορικῆς) or On Ways of Life (Περὶ ἠθῶν καὶ βίων). See Antoni (Reference Antoni2004) 35–8.

7 See Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 103–6. The arguments sketched by Antoni in this contribution are very similar to those subsequently advanced in Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b), on which see below.

8 I.e. an anecdotal sentence or a short exchange of sayings between two persons within a narrative context. See Searby (Reference Searby1998) 15–16.

9 Stob. Flor. 4.4.29 Hense (Chrysippus fr. 3.694 SVF) Χρυσίππου⋅ Χρύσιππος ἐρωτηθεὶς διὰ τί οὐ πολιτεύεται, εἶπε⋅ Διότι εἰ μὲν πονηρά [τις] πολιτεύεται, τοῖς θεοῖς ἀπαρέσει⋅ εἰ δὲ χρηστὰ τοῖς πολίταις. See also Stob. Ecl. 2.31.76 Wachsmuth (Antisthenes fr. V A 173 SSR).

10 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1043a–b (Chrysippus fr. 3.703 SVF).

11 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1043b (Chrysippus fr. 3.704 SVF).

12 See Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 106–9.

13 See Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 18–25 and also Antoni (Reference Antoni and Schubert2012a). On the uncertainty and the inconsistency of some of Antoni's conclusions see below.

14 See Obbink (Reference Obbink1996) 81–2 and n. 9; Janko (Reference Janko2000) 190–3, who refers in particular to Philodemus’ On Poems, On Music and On Rhetoric; Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 106; and Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 20–1.

15 See Cic. Nat. D. 1.26.72 (Epicurus fr. 72 Usener); Sedley (Reference Sedley, Bollack and Laks1976); and Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 20–1.

16 See Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 105 and Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 20–1.

17 See Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 105 and Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 20–1.

18 See Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 105 and Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 20–1.

19 See Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 21–3.

20 See Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 21–3 and, on the specific case of Epicurus, who was credited with using only his own words without any quotations from other authors, Diog. Laert. 10.26 and 7.181. The first section of Philodemus’ On Anger (cols. 1–34.6 Indelli) and the second section of his On Arrogance (cols. 10–24 Jensen), which are full of literary quotations, are no exception to this rule because they represent paraphrases and/or quotations from authors of a completely different philosophical inspiration (Cynic and Stoic in the former case, probably Stoic in the latter). See Ranocchia (Reference Ranocchia2007b) and Ranocchia (Reference Ranocchia2007a).

21 See Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 21–3. On Philodemus’ systematic avoidance of hiatus see Strathmann (Reference Strathmann1892) and McOsker (Reference McOsker2017).

22 See, on the Stoic doctrine of circumstances, Ioppolo (Reference Ioppolo1980) 188–207.

23 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1039b and chs. 22 and 28; Sext. Emp. Math. 11.194; Script. Stoic. Anon. (P.Herc. 1020) col. 108.11–12 Alessandrelli–Ranocchia. According to von Arnim (Reference Arnim1890) 492, ἐπιστροφή understood in this sense was ‘ein Lieblingswort des Chrysippos’. The presence of ἐπιστρ[ε|φομέ]νων immediately before (lines 4–5) produces a figura etymologica, which reinforces the concept.

24 See e.g. fr. 3.414 SVF.

25 On Stoic moral progress see e.g. frr. 3.217, 220, 226, 510, 530, 532, 534–6, 539, 543 SVF, and Ioppolo (Reference Ioppolo1980) 137–41; Inwood and Donini (Reference Inwood and Donini1999); Roskam (Reference Roskam2005).

26 On the Stoic concept of καθῆκον or ‘appropriate action’ see e.g. frr. 1.230–2, 576–86, 3.491–523 SVF; Panaet. frr. 92–103 Alesse; Cic. Off. 3.51–5.91; Diog. Laert. 7.124 and 129; and Sedley (Reference Sedley and Ierodiakonou1999). Here the participle καθή[κο]υ[σαν] agrees with διάθ[εσιν] ‘disposition’ (line 4), another interesting term of (not only) Stoic moral psychology.

27 See e.g. frr. 1.537 and 2.599 SVF.

28 See e.g. frr. 2.318 and 989, 3.384, 462, 613 and 615 SVF. In our passage this adjective governs τῶ[ι ὀρ]θῶι νόμωι (line 5), which immediately follows in Antoni's list of Stoic lexemes.

29 See, on both expressions, frr. 1.537, 3.4 and 332 SVF. ὀρθὸς νόμος as such is only attested in Alex. Aphr. In Arist. Top. 224–5 Wallies–Reimer.

30 On Stoic providence see frr. 2.1106–86 SVF and Reydams-Schils (Reference Reydams-Schils1999).

31 In fact, neither ἀφιλοτίμως nor the corresponding adjective ἀφιλότιμος or otherwise the noun ἀφιλοτιμία is attested in Stoic authors. See Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 106 and Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 21–3.

32 See Antoni (Reference Antoni2004); Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 106; Antoni (Reference Antoni, Antoni, Arrighetti, Bertagna and Delattre2010) 71–9; and Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 21–3. See, in particular, Diog. Laert. 7.180–1 and 10.26–7, where Epicurus’ and Chrysippus’ literary usages are compared, and, on the latter's exploitation of Euripides, Diog. Laert. 7.180. See also, on the systematic use of quotations from earlier poets by Chrysippus to support his own views, frr. 2.890, 904–8, 911 SVF and Puglia (Reference Puglia1993) 41, which have escaped Antoni.

33 See Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 104–5; Antoni (Reference Antoni and Schubert2012a); and Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 21–3. Here Zeno reworks a famous Hesiodean passage (Οp. 293–5) to make his point (see above).

34 See e.g. fr. 2.1009 SVF; Sen. Ben. 1.13.3; Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 105; and Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 21–3.

35 See Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 21–4.

37 On the former stylistic feature see frr. 3.113, 117, 471, 501 and 602 SVF, and on the latter e.g. fr. 3.563 SVF. See too Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 21–3.

38 See Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 103–4 and 106; Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 23–4, 28 and 30. On P.Herc. 1020 see below.

39 Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 23–4 and Puglia (Reference Puglia1993). In particular, the topic of the self-sacrifice for the fatherland detectable in some fragments of this papyrus recalls, for Antoni, the wise man's strenuous engagement in politics for the state's sake, inferable from cols. 31–3 of P.Herc. 1384. Among the stylistic similarities between these two papyri, Antoni underlines the common presence of a great number of citations from poetic authors.

40 See Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 107–8 and Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 24–5.

41 See Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 109 and Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 24–5.

42 Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 24. See also, on a similar, but more generic, conclusion (she only speaks of early Stoicism) Antoni (Reference Antoni, Antoni, Arrighetti, Bertagna and Delattre2010) 78–9. The translations from the French are my own.

43 See, on the importance of physics for Chrysippus, Diog. Laert. 7.39–41 and 87–9; Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1035a (fr. 2.42 SVF); Stob. Ecl. 2.75.11–76.8 Wachsmuth; and Long and Sedley (Reference Long and Sedley1987) 266–7; on the role and the significance of dialectic, Cic. Fin. 4.9 (fr. 1.47 SVF); Diog. Laert. 7.180 (fr. 2.1 SVF), 182–4 (frr. 2.1 and 2.9 SVF); Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1035f–1037b (frr. 2.127, 129 and 270 SVF); and Long and Sedley (Reference Long and Sedley1987) 189–90.

44 Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 24.

45 See Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 24.

46 Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 24.

47 At point (ii), for instance, it would have been useful to stress that early Stoics’ and Chrysippus’ well-known systematic exploitation of literary quotations from earlier poets – cherished as a treasure trove of ancient wisdom and often interpreted in an allegorical way – should be regarded not just as a literary or stylistic phenomenon, but as a coherent argumentative method used to support one's own philosophical views, which was typical of early Stoicism. See e.g. Puglia (Reference Puglia1993) 41.

48 In particular, to point (i) one should add at least ἀξίωμα ‘proposition’ (col. 3.2), a term probably introduced into Stoic logic by Chrysippus (see frr. 2.193–220 SVF), and the expression φρον]ί̣μως | [κ]αὶ εὐλαβῶ[ς ‘prudently and cautiously’ (col. 7.2–3). On εὐλάβεια ‘caution’, a positive emotion (εὐπάθεια) defined by Chrysippus as ‘reasonable avoidance’, and its derivatives see frr. 2.127, 270, 359, 3.90, 175, 264–5, 275, 411, 431 and 439 SVF. To point (vi) one should add at least the syntagm ἀκολούθως + dative, ‘in accordance with’ (col. 20.4), which was typical of e.g. Zeno (frr. 1.179 and 230 SVF), Diogenes of Babylon (fr. 1.116 SVF), Antipater (fr. 1.62 SVF) and, above all, Chrysippus (frr. 2.131, 528, 892, 895, 911, 989, 3.4, 6, 8–9, 149, 264, 294, 494, 548 and App. 2.28.1–2 SVF).

49 In the Stoic doxography reported by Diogenes Laertius at the end of the life of Zeno of Citium, for instance, we read, as much as in our papyrus, that the wise man will take wine, but not get drunk (Diog. Laert. 7.118; cf. P.Herc. 1384, col. 25), that he will not be liable to madness (Diog. Laert. 7.118; cf P.Herc. 1384, col. 1), that he will take part in politics if nothing hinders him (Diog. Laert. 7.121; cf. P.Herc. 1384, cols. 31–41) and that he will feel affection for youths (Diog. Laert. 7.129; cf. P.Herc. 1384, cols. 22 and 24).

50 The author contends polemically that politicians can endure difficult tasks (πόνους) better than hedonist philosophers. This sounds like a biased philosophical argument against the well-known Epicurean refusal to engage in politics. This is grounded, for the author, in the hedonistic principle, which makes Epicureans unable to undertake any difficult tasks. This is also the reason why other kinds of hedonistic philosophers (i.e. the Cyrenaics) should be excluded here.

51 ‘… μὴ] || πολιτε[ύ]σεσθαι διό|τι, ἐὰν μὲν χρηστὰ | πολιτεύηται, τοῖς [π]ο|λίτ[αις ἀπαρ]έσει, [ἐὰν] | δὲ [πονηρά], τοῖς θ[εοῖς]’ ‘that he [i.e. the wise man] will not engage in politics, because if one does so well, he displeases the citizens; if [one does so] badly, he displeases the gods’ (my translation). Even though the syntax is not identical in both sources (see Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 107–8), there can be no doubt that we are dealing with the same chreia.

52 ἰατρικὰ καὶ γεωμε|τρικὰ καὶ ὡσαύ[τως] | ἔγρα̣φ̣ε̣ ̣ ̣ ̣ ̣ ̣α̣ ̣ ̣ ̣ ̣ | δὲ ταῦτα μέν, δι[α]λε|κτικὰ δὲ κα[ὶ] φυσικὰ | οὐδ’ ἂν γέν[οι]το χρή|σιμα οὔτε καὶ περὶ | γενομένων χ̣ρ̣ησ̣[ί]|μων οὔ[τε] περὶ τῶν | ἠθικῶν ̣[ ̣ ̣ ̣ ̣ ̣] οι[ ̣ | τ]ὰ̣ [σ]υγγρ[ά]μματ[α] | [καὶ] τ̣ὰς πο[ι]ήσεις̣ | [εὐ]χρήστω[ς  ̣]  ̣ ου ̣ ̣ ̣ | [συ]γγράμ[μα]τα ‘works about medicine and geometry and, in like manner, he wrote […], on the one part, these, whereas, on the other, dialectics and physics would not be useful because they neither (focus on) what is useful nor on ethical issues […] the treatises and the poetic compositions serviceably […] treatises’ (my translation).

53 See above on this.

54 See Diog. Laert. 41–3 (frr. 1.48 SVF and 1.482); Sext. Emp. Math. 2.6–7 (fr. 1.75 SVF); Quint. Inst. 2.20.7 (fr. 1.75 SVF); Cic. Fin. 2.17 (fr. 1.75 SVF) and Orat. 32.113 (fr. 1.75 SVF).

55 See on this point Diog. Laert. 6.103 (fr. 1.354 SVF ), 7.160 (fr. 1.351 SVF); Stob. Ecl. 2.8.13 Wachsmuth (fr. 1.352 SVF ); Euseb. Praep. evang. 15.62.7 (fr. 1.353 SVF ); Cic. Luc. 123–4 (fr. 1.355 SVF ); Sext. Emp. Math. 7.12 (fr. 1.356 SVF ); Sen. Ep. 89.13 (fr. 1.357 SVF); and Ioppolo (Reference Ioppolo1980) 49 and 59–63; on the rejection of dialectic, Diog. Laert. 2.79 (fr. 1.349 SVF), 7.163 (fr. 1.333 SVF); Plut. De tuenda san. praec. 133c (fr. 1.389 SVF); Stob. Ecl. 2.2.14 Wachsmuth (fr. 1.392 SVF), 2.2.18 (fr. 1.393 SVF), 2.2.22–3 (frr. 1.391 and 1.394 SVF); and Ioppolo (Reference Ioppolo1980) 63–7.

56 On Zenodotus see Diog. Laert. 7.30 and Nickau (Reference Nickau, Wissowa, Kroll and Mistelhaus1972), who identified him with Zenodotus of Mallus, a disciple of the grammarian Crates; on Apollodorus of Seleucia see Apollod. Sel. frr. 3.1–18 SVF and, in particular, Diog. Laert. 7.121 and 129 (frr. 3.17 and 18 SVF). See also Mansfeld (Reference Mansfeld1986) 347–51; Hahm (Reference Hahm1992); Alesse (Reference Alesse2000) 55–61; Goulet-Cazé (Reference Goulet-Cazé2003) 137–81; Bees (Reference Bees2011) 263–8.

57 On these positions and the internal debate concerning the origins of Stoicism and its relationship to Cynicism see Cic. Fin. 3.68, 4.3, 14, 44–5 and 61, De or. 3.61 and Alesse (Reference Alesse2000) 55–61.

58 The controversial expression ‘Middle Stoa’ or ‘Middle Stoicism’ – to be distinguished from early and Imperial Stoicism – is used to designate a phase in the school's history inaugurated by Panaetius and marked by receptiveness towards Platonic and Aristotelian doctrines. The expression was introduced by Schmekel (Reference Schmekel1892), who was followed by Zeller and Nestle (Reference Zeller and Nestle1928) 303–4 and Tatakis (Reference Tatakis1931). But against this historiographical paradigm, see the strong reservations formerly expressed by Pohlenz (Reference Pohlenz1959) 387–8 and, nowadays, by Frede (Reference Frede1999) and Tieleman (Reference Tieleman2003) 11, 199, 225 and n. 76, 226 n. 77, 240, 242–3 and 287.

59 See e.g., on his rejection of the idea of a periodical cosmic conflagration, Phil. Aet. mund. 76; on his criticism of astrology, Cic. Div. 1.6–7 and 2.88; and, on his adjustments to ethics, Cic. Fin. 4.23 and 79, Acad. pr. 2.135, Tusc. 1.79–80; Gell. NA 12.5.10; and Alesse (Reference Alesse1994). On his substantial doctrinal continuity with Chrysippus concerning moral psychology, however, see Tieleman (Reference Tieleman2003) 245–50.

60 On his alleged fondness for Plato and Aristotle see Phld. Stoic. hist. col. 61 Dorandi; Cic. Tusc. 1.79; and Alesse (Reference Alesse2000) 56–7.

61 See Alesse (Reference Alesse1994) 16–21 and 23–162.

62 See e.g. Cic. Off. 1.128; Ioppolo (Reference Ioppolo1980) 54; Alesse (Reference Alesse2000) 56–7; and Ranocchia (Reference Ranocchia2007a) 76–8. This was also, in all probability, the reason why, according to Diogenes Laertius (7.34), the Stoic Athenodorus, the keeper of the library of Pergamum – a milieu where Panaetius himself had formerly studied and been active – was caught expunging from Zeno's works (including, in all likelihood, the Republic) some passages he regarded as contrasting with true Stoic teaching. See Fritz (Reference Fritz, Wissowa, Kroll and Mistelhaus1972) 88–90; Mansfeld (Reference Mansfeld1986) 344–5; Alesse (Reference Alesse1997a) 209–210; Schofield (Reference Schofield1999) 8–13. Certainly this was the reason which, according to Philodemus’ History of the Stoa and On Stoics, induced Stoics at different times to attempt to justify, downplay and criticise this work, or even to declare it inauthentic. See Phld. Stoic. hist. col. 4 Dorandi (but the text is partly conjectural), De Stoic. passim; and Dorandi (Reference Dorandi1982) 92–7; Schofield (Reference Schofield1999) 8–13; Alesse (Reference Alesse2000) 43–6; Bees (Reference Bees2011) 29–41.

63 See Phld. De Stoic. col. 13.15–16 Dorandi (but the name Ποσει]δών̣[ιος] is conjectural) and Dorandi (Reference Dorandi1982) 93.

64 The most striking case in this sense is that represented by Diogenes of Babylon, who is credited by ancient sources with having performed an extensive revision of Stoic doctrine in several fields, such as linguistics, moral psychology, ethics, political philosophy, rhetoric and musical theory, and with having acknowledged Plato and Aristotle as important philosophical authorities. See Schäfer (Reference Schäfer1936); Barth and Goedeckemeyer (Reference Barth and Goedeckemeyer1941) 107ff.; Obbink and Vander Waerdt (Reference Obbink and Vander Waerdt1991) 355–9; Vander Waerdt (Reference Vander Waerdt1991) 205–10; Isnardi Parente (Reference Isnardi Parente1992) 596–619; and Nussbaum (Reference Nussbaum, Brunschwig and Nussbaum1993) 120–1. But at least as far as moral psychology and musical theory are concerned, see the recent account by Tieleman (Reference Tieleman2003) 242–50, who has convincingly argued for a substantial doctrinal continuity between Chrysippus and Diogenes in these fields.

65 See, lastly, Tieleman (Reference Tieleman2003) 242–87.

66 To the contrary, moderate views in ethics are attested for most of them. Consider, in particular, Diogenes of Babylon's revision of the early Stoic doctrine of the telos (Arius Didymus ap. Stob. Ecl. 22.76.9–10 Wachsmuth; Diog. Laert. 7.88; and Clem. Strom. 2.21) and his justification of private property (Cic. Fin. 3.49–55 and Annas (Reference Annas, Griffin and Barnes1989) 151–73). Consider too Antipater's defence of the moral and social value of marriage, the family and heterosexual love, which openly contrasts with some of the theses expressed in Zeno's Republic (see Stob. Ecl. 70.13 Wachsmuth = fr. 3.62 SVF, Flor. 67.25 Hense = fr. 3.63 SVF; Alesse (Reference Alesse1997a) 210 and (Reference Alesse2000) 45), and his (probably negative) view of Zeno's Republic, by which he was certainly embarrassed (see Phld. De Stoic. col. 17.4–10 Dorandi and Alesse (Reference Alesse2000) 44–5).

67 See Ioppolo (Reference Ioppolo1980) 9–18, 33–8, 159–62 and 166–70.

68 On Panaetius see above; on Posidonius see Tieleman (Reference Tieleman2003) 242–87, who, however, argues for a substantial doctrinal continuity with Chrysippus in moral psychology; on Mnesarchus of Athens see Diels (Reference Diels1879) 615 and Fritz (Reference Fritz, Wissowa, Kroll and Mistelhaus1932) 2272–4; on Boethus of Sidon see Alesse (Reference Alesse1997b) 359–83.

69 On Panaetius see above; on the similar case of Posidonius, Mnesarchus and Boethus, suffice it to say that Cynicising Stoicism represented for them – just as for Panaetius – the diametrically opposite side of the philosophical spectrum (with Chrysippus in between) and, from a historical point of view, the very target of the debate which had emerged within the school in the second half of second century BC. See above and Alesse (Reference Alesse2000) 55–61.

70 See Dorandi (Reference Dorandi1999) 40.

71 The only Stoic contemporary of Chrysippus whom we know of was Sphaerus of Borythenes (ca 285–post-222 BC, see Hobein (Reference Hobein, Wissowa, Kroll and Mistelhaus1929) 1683–93 and Dorandi (Reference Dorandi1999) 40), a student of Zeno and then Cleanthes (Diog. Laert. 7.177 (fr. 1.620 SVF); Plut. Cleom. 2 (fr. 1.622 SVF); Ath. 8.354e (fr. 1.624 SVF); Phld. Stoic. hist. col. 37.6–8 Ranocchia). But could Sphaerus – whose philosophical teaching remains largely unknown to us – be regarded as a Chrysippean philosopher himself? His discipleship with both the school's founder Zeno and the latter's immediate successor Cleanthes, his rich and varied philosophical production (see Diog. Laert. 7.178) and even his biography (he eventually left Athens in 238/237 BC, or even earlier, when Chrysippus must have been in his late thirties or early forties, i.e. as the latter had yet to reach his mature years) seem, rather, to hint at a fairly independent philosophical personality. Likewise, the testimony of Cic. Tusc. 4.53 (fr. 1.628 SVF), in which Sphaerus’ and Chrysippus’ definitions of courage are contrasted and the former thinker is said to have been ranked by his school fellows as one of the best Stoics at providing definitions, possibly points in the same direction.

72 See above on this point.

73 In particular, the author's praise of paederastic love (col. 22) – a topos of classical Greek culture – and his account of the wise man's love for those who make moral progress (col. 24) appear hardly compatible with Antipater's exaltation of heterosexual love and marriage against alternative forms of ἔρως. See Stob. Flor. 4.22.103 Hense (Antip. fr. 3.62 SVF), 4.22.25 (Antip. fr. 3.63 SVF) and above. This makes Antipater not an especially good candidate for the authorship of P.Herc. 1384.

74 This is the case with ἀξίωμ[α (col. 3.2), here to be understood as ‘proposition’, as the logical-cognitive context (lines 4–6 ἐπιστρ[ε|φομέ]νων ἐπιστρο|[φήν) seems to confirm. As mentioned above, this concept was apparently introduced into Stoic logic, and was extensively used, by Chrysippus. See Chrysippus frr. 2.193–220 SVF and Alessandrelli (Reference Alessandrelli2013) 38–47.

75 See above, n. 73 on the case of Antipater.

76 On the Stoic works transmitted through the Herculaneum papyri see Marrone (Reference Marrone1987) and (Reference Marrone1988); Puglia (Reference Puglia1993) 42–3; and Del Mastro (Reference Del Mastro2005) 66–7.

77 See P.Herc. 1421, subscr., 1038, subscr. and Del Mastro (Reference Del Mastro2014) 276–7 and 206–7, respectively.

78 See P.Herc. 307, subscr. and Del Mastro (Reference Del Mastro2014) 114–17.

79 See P.Herc. 1380, subscr. and Del Mastro (2014) 61–70.

80 See, on P.Herc. 1158, Puglia (Reference Puglia1993), who has proven with good arguments the distance of this text from Epicureanism and its closeness to Stoicism, and, on P.Herc. 1020, below.

81 The presence of Stoic works at Herculaneum has usually been explained as providing documentary evidence for Philodemus’ comparison between Epicurean and Stoic teaching and as a source and a target for, respectively, his ‘historico-philosophical’ (History of the Stoa) and polemical (On Stoics) works concerning the Stoics. This would also explain why so many of his treatises are full of quotations from Stoic sources. See Marrone (Reference Marrone1988) 224; Puglia (Reference Puglia1993) 42–3; Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 109; and Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 24–5.

82 See Alessandrelli and Ranocchia (Reference Alessandrelli and Ranocchia2017) 10.

83 See Alessandrelli and Ranocchia (Reference Alessandrelli and Ranocchia2017) 10.

84 In On Stoics, Philodemus refers to Chrysippus’ On Justice, Republic, On Appropriate Action, On the Beautiful and Pleasure, On Zeno's Proper Use of Names, On Those Things Which Are Chosen in Themselves and the otherwise unknown On the City and Law, On Life according to Nature and Against Those Who Understand Prudence in a Different Way. See Dorandi (Reference Dorandi1982) and Mansfeld (Reference Mansfeld1986). For this reason, Puglia (Reference Puglia1993) 42–3 and Del Mastro (Reference Del Mastro2005) 66 n. 49 and 67 do not exclude the possibility that at least some of these works were included in Philodemus’ library. In the former part of On Anger (cols. 1–34.6 Indelli), Philodemus extensively quotes and paraphrases – along with Bion of Borysthenes’ and Antipater's On Anger – book 4 of Chyrisippus’ On Emotions in a way which undoubtedly presupposes his direct knowledge and possession of this work. See Ranocchia (Reference Ranocchia2007b).

85 See Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 23: ‘En dépit de certaines ressemblances, la main du P.Herc. 1384 reste jusq’à ce jour une main unique parmi tous les papyrus d'Herculanum.’

86 See Cavallo (Reference Cavallo1983).

87 See Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 103–4 and Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 23 and 28–30. In particular, Antoni has shown that in P.Herc. 1020 all letters – with very few exceptions and despite the larger spacing, the smaller number of ligatures and the more open writing angle – have the same shape as the ones we find in P.Herc. 1384.

88 See Cavallo (Reference Cavallo1983) 34–5 and 52. Significantly enough, this graphic typology is rarely witnessed in the Herculaneum collection and some of its elements show divergency from the scribal hands of which it is composed. Note also that P.Herc. 1020 is the only non-Philodemean papyrus included in ‘Gruppo H’ and that its only relationship to this group is represented, according to Cavallo, by its generic graphic similarity only to P.Herc.1428 (Philodemus, On Piety).

89 An editorial project is an ancient edition of a single work by an author executed by the same hand, or very similar ones, and written in typologically similar graphic forms. In this sense, a single work may have come down to us through either one or more editorial projects, i.e. different copies of the same work (or parts of it) which are graphically uniform within themselves and have been written by the same hand or very similar ones. This is often the case within the Herculaneum collection. See Cavallo (Reference Cavallo1983) 58–65.

90 See Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 23 and 28–30. Previously, Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 106 and 109 had explicitly assigned P.Herc. 1020 to Chrysippus.

91 And not only or mainly ‘dialectic’, as Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 104 and Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 23 contend.

92 See von Arnim (Reference Arnim1890), who edited the last eight text columns of the papyrus, and Arnim (Reference Arnim1903), where P.Herc. 1020 is included among the testimonies concerning Chrysippus’ dialectic (fr. 2.131 SVF) and is the object of some new conjectures.

93 See Pohlenz (Reference Pohlenz1904) 1503.

94 See Keil (Reference Keil1905) 155–8.

95 Ep. 5.558 (PG 78.1637 = FDS 2b).

96 See Alessandrelli and Ranocchia (Reference Alessandrelli and Ranocchia2017). A new comprehensive edition of P.Herc. 1020 is a part of the EU-funded Project ERC Starting Grant 241184-PHerc (FP7, ‘Ideas’). See www.pherc.eu.

97 These can here be summarised as follows: (a) according to Diog. Laert. 7.122–3 (fr. 3.556 SVF), Chrysippus claimed that ‘the wise are infallible (ἀναμαρτήτους), since they are not subject to error’. The same term recurs in P.Herc. 1020, col. 108.4–5, again with reference to the wise; (b) at the end of the Stoic doxography conventionally attributed to Arius Didymus (Stob. Ecl. 2.116.13–14 Wachsmuth) several works of Chrysippus are mentioned, which are considered to have served as a source for it. A section of it (Stob. 2.111.18–113.11 (fr. 3.548 SVF = fr. 89 FDS) shows impressive lexical analogies with P.Herc. 1020; (c) if, as seems likely, the source for Epict. Diss. 1.7 is Chrysippus (see Long (Reference Long2002) 57), the intriguing, and sometimes compelling, lexical analogies between this text and P.Herc. 1020 might represent a further argument in favour of the latter's Chrysippean authorship; (d) the existence in the Herculanean library of a nucleus of specifically Chrysippean papyri brings us in the same direction. See Alessandrelli and Ranocchia (Reference Alessandrelli and Ranocchia2017) 9–10.

98 And this also because, as the recent research has shown, the other possible candidates, i.e. the early Stoics who succeeded Chrysippus, did not necessarily follow him in all respects. See Alessandrelli and Ranocchia (Reference Alessandrelli and Ranocchia2017) 8–9 and above on this point.

99 Diog. Laert. 7.127. See also Diog. Laert. 7.128; Alex. Aphr. An. 2.161 (fr. 3.239 SVF); Simpl. In Arist. Cat. 10.402 (fr. 3.238 SVF); and Graver (Reference Graver2007) 115–16.

100 See P.Herc. 1020, col. 108.1–12 Alessandrelli–Ranocchia: τούτοις δὲ πά̣λιν | ἀκολ[ο]υθεῖ καὶ τὸ τοὺς | σο̣φο[ὺ]ς ἀνεξαπατή|τους εἶναι καὶ ἀναμαρ|τήτο̣υς καλῶ[ς] τε ζῆν | καὶ πάντα πράτ̣τειν | εὖ⋅ διὸ καὶ περὶ [τὰς] συγ|[κα]ταθέσεις, ὅπ̣ως γίν{ο}<ω>ν|ται μὴ ἄλλως, ἀλ{α}<λ>ὰ με|τὰ καταλήψεως, πλεί|ω<ν> γέγονεν ἐ[π]ιστ̣ρο|φή. Virtue is not explicitly mentioned in the passage, but is indirectly inferable from the wise man's asserted cognitive and moral infallibility. On the technical meaning of ἐπιστροφή, a term which, among the early Stoics, is only found in Chrysippus, see, besides the passage just mentioned from P.Herc. 1020, Gal. PHP 4.6.149, p. 383 Müller (fr. 3.475 SVF), where the reference is to excessive love: οἵας μάλιστα φορὰς καὶ οἱ ἐρώμενοι ἀξιοῦσι πρὸς ἑαυτοὺς ἔχειν τοὺς ἐραστάς, ἀπερισκεπτότερον καὶ ἄνευ ἐπιστροφῆς λογικῆς ἱσταμένους κτλ., and, with a generic meaning, Sext. Emp. Math. 11.194 (fr. 3.752 SVF); Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1039b (fr. 3.724 SVF) and 1045a (fr. 3.754 SVF).

101 As we know, the protagonist of the book is the wise man, who is also the subject of this section (cols. 1–5), as is proven by e.g. col. 1.1–4.

102 See P.Herc. 1384, col. 3.1–8 [ ̣ ̣ ̣ ̣τ]οι[ο]ύτοις [ ̣ ̣ |  ̣ ̣ ̣ ̣] τὸ ἀξίωμ[ ̣ ̣|  ̣ ̣ ̣] ̣ον δὲ καὶ [π]ρὸς | [ ̣ ̣ ̣ ̣] ̣ν ἐπιστρ[ε|φομέ]νων ἐπιστρο|[φὴν δ]έχεσθαι τ[ ̣ ̣|  ̣ ̣ ̣ ̣ ̣ ̣] ̣ως εἰς τ[α]ῦ|[τα ̣ ̣] ̣βλέπον̣τες. The passage is fairly lacunose.

103 Thanks are due to Michele Alessandrelli for drawing my attention to this passage.

104 Diog. Laert. 7.121 (fr. 3.697 SVF), 129 (fr. 3.716 SVF) and 188 (fr. 3.685 SVF). This work is not expressly mentioned in the catalogue of works by Chrysippus reported at the end of his Life. But, as is known, this has reached us in an incomplete form through the manuscript tradition.

105 Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1033c–d (fr. 3.702 SVF), 1035a (fr. 2.42 SVF = fr. 24 FDS), 1036d–e (fr. 2.270 SVF = fr. 351 FDS), 1043a (fr. 3.703 SVF), 1043b–c (fr. 3.691 SVF), 1044a (fr. 3.579 SVF) and 1047f (fr. 3.693 SVF).

106 Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1036d (fr. 2.270 SVF = fr. 351 FDS).

107 See LSJ s.v.

108 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1043b–c, 1044a, 1047f, and Diog. Laert. 7.121, 129 and 188.

109 See Alessandrelli and Ranocchia (Reference Alessandrelli and Ranocchia2017) 15–17.

110 See Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 108 and above.

111 See Ranocchia (Reference Ranocchia2021).

112 Pace Verhasselt (Reference Verhasselt2016) 59–83, who has tried to reconcile both traditions. See, for my critique of Verhasselt's account, Ranocchia (Reference Ranocchia2021).

113 See, in particular, the divisions of ethics by Eudorus of Alexandria and Philo of Larissa included in Arius Didymus’ ethical doxography (resp. Stob. Ecl. 2.7.2, pp. 44, 24–45, 2 Wachsmuth = Eudor. fr. 1 Mazzarelli and 2.7.2, pp. 39, 19–41, 25 = Philo Lar. fr. 25 Wiśniewski, fr. 2 Mette, fr. 32 Brittain) and the late Peripatetic discourse on the lives of the sage (Stob. Ecl. 2.7.24, pp. 143–5 Wachsmuth).

114 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1043a (fr. 3.703 SVF).

115 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1043b–c (fr. 3.691 SVF).

116 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1043b–c (fr. 3.691 SVF, see immediately above), 1043e (fr. 3.691 SVF) and Comm. not. 1061d (fr. 3.691 SVF). See also Stoic. repugn. 1043e (fr. 3.693 SVF) and 1047f (fr. 3.693 SVF).

117 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1047f (fr. 3.693 SVF, see immediately above) and 1043e (fr. 3.701 SVF). But the attribution of this passage to book 1 is conjectural. See von Arnim (Reference Arnim1903) App. 2.7, fr. 4.

118 See Plut. Comm. not. 1061d (fr. 3.691 SVF, see above).

119 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1044a (fr. 3.579 SVF). Inexplicably, this passage is not incuded by von Arnim (Reference Arnim1903) App. 2.7 among the fragments of Chrysippus’ Περὶ βίων.

120 See Diog. Laert. 7.129 (fr. 3.716 SVF).

121 See Diog. Laert. 7.121 (fr. 3.697 SVF).

122 See Diog. Laert. 7.188 (fr. 3.685 SVF).

123 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1033c–d (fr. 3.702 SVF) αὐτὸς γοῦν Χρύσιππος ἐν τῷ τετάρτῳ Περὶ βίων οὐδὲν οἴεται τὸν σχολαστικὸν βίον τοῦ ἡδονικοῦ διαφέρειν (‘Chrysippus indeed himself, in his fourth Book of Lives, thinks there is no difference between a scholastic life and a life of pleasure’; tr. E. Goodwin). On the interpretation of this controversial passage see recently Bénatouïl (Reference Bénatouïl, Bonazzi and Helmig2007) 1–13, who has convincingly shown that: (a) the criticism contained in it is directed against the Platonic and the Aristotelian conception of the absolute preferability of the contemplative life over the active one; (b) Chrysippus does not reject the scholastic life as such; (c) the Stoics admitted of three preferable ways of life, among which the scientific one (see Stob. Ecl. 2.109.10 Wachsmuth = fr. 3.686 SVF and below); (d) on a higher level, for Stoic philosophers only the rational life or life according to virtue, viz. a mixed form of life combining the contemplative (i.e. scientific) and the active (i.e. political), is to be chosen in itself by the wise man (Diog. Laert. 7.130 = fr. 3.687 SVF). And the rational or virtuous life does not imply the choice of any specific way of life (since none is preferable in itself); rather, it simply dictates to the wise man what is best in any circumstance and what share of the active and the contemplative life he should have in general and in the different situations of his life.

124 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1035a (fr. 2.42 SVF).

125 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1043a (fr. 3.703 SVF).

126 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1036c (fr. 2.270 SVF).

127 See above and Ranocchia (Reference Ranocchia2021).

128 See Antoni (Reference Antoni2004) 38 and also Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 19–20.

129 See Antoni (Reference Antoni2004) 38.

130 See P.Herc. 1384, col. 38.1–5; Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1043a–b (fr. 3.703 SVF); and Antoni and Dorival (Reference Antoni and Dorival2007) 108.

131 No allusion to the thematic variety or the narrative scheme of P.Herc. 1384 is made by Dorival.

132 As we have seen, the author of P.Herc. 1384 never says that the wise man will not engage in politics, but rather the exact opposite (see cols. 31–41 and above). As to the presence in it (col. 38.1–5 Antoni = point ix above) of the Chrysippean chreia quoted above (Stob. Flor. 4.4.29 Hense (Chrysippus fr. 3.694 SVF); see above, n. 9, for the Greek text), this probably refers to Chrysippus’ personal choice of life. Indeed, in Stobaeus’ version of this chreia the grammatical and logical subject is Chrysippus himself, who ‘was asked why he did not engage in politics’, i.e. why he personally preferred the scholastic life to the political one. So, no reference is made in the chreia to the wise man as such. On the other hand, Chrysippus in book 4 of his On Ways of Life (Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1043a–b (fr. 3.703 SVF)) did not claim – as Dorival contends – that the wise man will not engage in politics, but only that he ‘is unmeddlesome and does little and that he minds his own business’. In other words, he contrasts oligopragmosynē with polypragmosynē, not with political engagement. See Keith (Reference Keith, Pace and Cacciatore2013) 261–2 on this point. In fact, as we have seen, in book 1 of the treatise he maintained that the wise man will partake in politics, if nothing hinders him (Diog. Laert. 7.121 = fr. 3.697 SVF). See, on a similar misunderstanding, Verhasselt (Reference Verhasselt2016) 73–4.

133 See also Antoni (Reference Antoni and Schubert2012a).

134 See Diog. Laert. 7.129 (fr. 3.716 SVF).

135 See Diog. Laert. 7.121 (fr. 3.697 SVF).

136 See Diog. Laert. 1043b–c and e (fr. 3.691 and 693 SVF).

137 See above, n. 132.

138 See Stob. Flor. 4.4.29 Hense (fr. 3.694 SVF) and above, nn. 9 and 132.

139 As we know, Chrysippus was an extremely busy philosopher and master who conceived of his philosophical activity as a mission for life and any other business as a distraction from it. Concerning his refusal to engage in an active life see the episode reported by Diogenes Laertius (7.185) according to which Chrysippus, differently from his fellow disciple Sphaerus (on whom see above, n. 71), disdainfully declined to join Ptolemy IV in Alexandria. See also above, n. 132.

140 Chrysippus regarded neither himself nor any of his predecessors or disciples as a wise man and maintained that only one or two wise men at most may exist in the world at any given time. See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1048e and Diogen. ap. Eus. Praep. evang. 6.8.13–14 (fr. 3.668 SVF). Moreover, he recognised that the Stoic ideal of the wise man is so lofty and superhuman as to seem like a fable to the people. See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1041f (fr. 3.545 SVF). More generally, the Stoics maintained that wisdom is hardly achievable by men and that the wise man is rarer than the phoenix. See Alex. Aphr. Fat. 28, p. 199.7 Bruns (fr. 3.658 SVF) and Ioppolo (Reference Ioppolo1980) 118–20. In particular, the evidence available to us on both early Stoics in general and each of them taken individually suggests that they did not consider themselves to be sages. For a thorough discussion of this point see now Brouwer (Reference Brouwer2014) 92–105, with further relevant references.

141 See Stob. Ecl. 2.109.10 Wachsmuth (fr. 3.686 SVF); Diog. Laert. 7.130 (fr. 3.687 SVF); and above, n. 123.

142 On the wise man and politics see now Laurand (Reference Laurand2005).

143 As is known, Plutarch in On Stoic Self-Contradictions is constantly concerned with detecting any supposed inconsistencies within Chrysippus’ On Ways of Life, On Appropriate Action and On Those Things Which Are Chosen in Themselves and tends to misrepresent Chrysippus’ positions so as to make them appear self-contradictory. See Keith (Reference Keith, Pace and Cacciatore2013). For this reason Plutarch's account is to be interpreted with caution.

144 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1043e, 1047f (fr. 3.693 SVF) and 1043e (fr. 3.701 SVF). The attribution of the last fragment to book 1, while likely, is conjectural (see von Arnim (Reference Arnim1903) App. 2.7, fr. 4 and above).

145 Pace Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 89, the supplement δ[ὴ τῶν χρ]ημά|των suggested by Richard Janko at lines 5–6 is both palaeographically and logically possible, given that only a few lines before (line 2) we have καρπ[ού]ς̣, ‘profits’.

146 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1047f (fr. 3.693 SVF) and 1043e (fr. 3.701 SVF).

147 In fact there seems to be also a generic consonance between P.Herc. 1384, col. 44 (the role of dialectic and physics, as well as of medicine, geometry and poetry, in the education of youths) and book 4 of Chrysippus’ Περὶ βίων (the succession of logic, ethics and physics in the philosophical training of youths: see Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1035a (fr. 2.42 SVF)). But in the former case, as we have seen above, the author is polemically reporting not his own position, but that of another philosopher (the rejection of physics and dialectic as useless).

148 See Diog. Laert. 7.129 (fr. 3.716 SVF).

149 See Antoni (Reference Antoni2012b) 35–45. According to her reconstruction, the original roll was ca 11.60 m long (excluding the initial agraphon and title), against the mere 2.39 m surviving today, and it contained about 213 columns of text, of which only fifty survive. In addition, of the original forty text lines per column, only between four and twenty are still surviving today. Finally, five columns are completely lost between Antoni's cols. 34 and 35; another two between cols. 39 and 40, i.e. exactly in the ‘political’ section of the book; and two more between cols. 42 and 43, namely in the ‘educational’ section.

150 In particular, the scant fragments from book 1 of Chrysippus’ Περὶ βίων with which we are concerned here might well have occurred in the lost lower portion of any column or in the columns that are missing in both the ‘political’ and the ‘educational’ section of the papyrus. See the preceding note.

151 See Alessandrelli and Ranocchia (Reference Alessandrelli and Ranocchia2017) 15–17 and above.

152 The first critical edition of cols. 96–103, which immediately precede this section, is now being published by Alessandrelli and Ranocchia (Reference Alessandrelli and Ranocchiaforthcoming).

153 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1036c (fr. 2.270 SVF).

154 See Plut. Stoic. repugn. 1035a (fr. 2.42 SVF).

155 Not even in the case of P.Herc. 1020 has any textual overlap with the (few) fragments belonging to book 4 of Chrysippus’ Περὶ βίων been detected so far. But it must be noted that, out of the more than a hundred columns originally to be found, only the last eight have been edited by scholars so far. Even in the already edited portion of it (cols. 104–12 Alessandrelli–Ranocchia), between eight and eleven lines are missing in the lower part of each column and, besides, one column (111) is entirely lost. See Alessandrelli and Ranocchia (Reference Alessandrelli and Ranocchia2017) 30–3.

156 In principle, these books could be among the ca 280 still unopened papyri in the collection. Alternatively, they could be found in the already unrolled papyri. In this regard, a good candidate could be P.Herc. 1158, an intriguing early Stoic text (on which see above). However, its poor condition and the fairly limited extent of the surviving text do not allow us to say anything certain about it. Only a new critical edition of this papyrus based on a stereo-microscope reading and the use of advanced techniques could disclose new promising information on its author, genre and content.

References

Works cited

Alessandrelli, M. (2013) Il problema del λεκτόν nello stoicismo antico. Origine e statuto di una nozione controversa, Florence.Google Scholar
Alessandrelli, M. and Ranocchia, G. (2017) Scrittore stoico anonimo, Opera incerta (P.Herc. 1020), coll. 104112. Edizione, introduzione e commento, Rome.Google Scholar
Alessandrelli, M. and Ranocchia, G. (forthcoming) Scrittore stoico anonimo, Opera incerta (P.Herc. 1020), coll. 96103. Edizione, introduzione e commento, Philosophical papyri 1.Google Scholar
Alesse, F. (1994) Panezio di Rodi e la tradizione stoica, Naples.Google Scholar
Alesse, F. (ed.) (1997a) Panezio di Rodi. Testimonianze. Edizione, traduzione e commento, Naples.Google Scholar
Alesse, F. (1997b) ‘Lo Stoico Boeto di Sidone’, Elenchos 18, 359–83.Google Scholar
Alesse, F. (2000) La Stoa e la tradizione Socratica, Naples.Google Scholar
Algra, K., Barnes, J., Mansfeld, J. and Schofield, M. (eds.) (1999) The Cambridge history of Hellenistic philosophy, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, J. (1989) ‘Cicero on Stoic moral philosophy and private property’, in Griffin, M. T. and Barnes, J. (eds.), Philosophia togata: essays on philosophy and Roman society, Oxford, 151–73.Google Scholar
Antoni, A. (2004) ‘Deux citations d'Euripide dans le P.Herc. 1384. Vers une nouvelle identification de ce livre de Philodème?’, CErc 34, 2938.Google Scholar
Antoni, A. (2010) ‘Solon et le stoïcisme. La col. A du P.Herc. 1384’, in Antoni, A., Arrighetti, G., Bertagna, M. I. and Delattre, D. (eds.), Miscellanea Papyrologica Herculanensia. Volume i, Pisa, 71–9.Google Scholar
Antoni, A. (2012a) ‘L'avant-dernière colonne du P.Herc. 1384. Une citation de Zénon de Citium’, in Schubert, P. (ed.), Actes du 26e Congrès international de papyrologie (Genève 16–21 août 2010), Geneva, 45–8.Google Scholar
Antoni, A. (2012b) ‘Le P.Herc. 1384. Édition critique’, CErc 42, 17189.Google Scholar
Antoni, A. and Dorival, G. (2007) ‘Il P.Herc. 1384. Una nuova ipotesi di attribuzione’, CErc 37, 103–10.Google Scholar
Arnim, H. von (1890) ‘Über einen stoischen Papyrus der herculanensischen Bibliothek’, Hermes 25, 473–95.Google Scholar
Arnim, J. ab (ed.) (1903) Stoicorum veterum fragmenta. Volume ii: Chrysippi fragmenta. Logica et physica. Volume iii: Chrysippi fragmenta moralia. Fragmenta successorum Chrysippi, Leipzig.Google Scholar
Barth, P. and Goedeckemeyer, A. (1941) Die Stoa, 5th edn, Stuttgart.Google Scholar
Bees, R. (2011) Zenons Politeia, Leiden and Boston.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bénatouïl, T. (2007) ‘Le débat entre stoïcisme et platonisme à propos de la vie scolastique. Chrysippe, la Nouvelle Académie, Antiochus’, in Bonazzi, M. and Helmig, C. (eds.), Stoic Platonism and Platonic Stoicism: the dialogue between Platonism and Stoicism in Antiquity, Leuven, 120.Google Scholar
Brouwer, R. (2014) The Stoic sage: the Early Stoics on wisdom, sagehood and Socrates, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cavallo, G. (1983) Libri scritture scribi a Ercolano, Naples.Google Scholar
Crönert, W. (1906) Kolotes und Menedemos, Leipzig.Google Scholar
Del Mastro, G. (2005) ‘Il P.Herc. 1380: Crisippo, Opera logica’, CErc 35, 61–7.Google Scholar
Del Mastro, G. (2014) Titoli e annotazioni bibliologiche nei papiri greci di Ercolano, Naples.Google Scholar
Diels, H. (1879) Doxographi Graeci, Berlin.Google Scholar
Dorandi, T. (1982) ‘Gli Stoici (P.Herc. 155 e 339)’, CErc 12, 91133.Google Scholar
Dorandi, T. (1999) ‘Chronology’, in Algra, Barnes, Mansfeld and Schofield (1999) 31–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frede, M. (1999) ‘Epilogue’, in Algra, Barnes, Mansfeld and Schofield (1999) 771–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fritz, K. von (1932) ‘Mnesarchos’ (no. 5), in Wissowa, G., Kroll, W. and Mistelhaus, K. (eds.), Paulys Realencyklopädie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft. Volume xv.1, Stuttgart and Munich, 2272–4.Google Scholar
Fritz, K. von (1972) ‘Zenon von Kition’ (no. 2), in Wissowa, G., Kroll, W. and Mistelhaus, K. (eds.), Paulys Realencyklopädie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft. Volume x.A.1, Stuttgart and Munich, 83121.Google Scholar
Goulet-Cazé, M.-O. (2003) Les Kynika du stoïcisme, Stuttgart.Google Scholar
Graver, M. R. (2007) Stoicism and emotions, Chicago and London.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hahm, D. E. (1992) ‘Diogenes Laertius vii: On the Stoics’, in ANRW ii.36.6, 4088–4105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hobein, H. (1929) ‘Sphairos’ (no. 3), in Wissowa, G., Kroll, W. and Mistelhaus, K. (eds.), Paulys Realencyklopädie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft. Volume iii.A.2, Stuttgart and Munich, 1683–93.Google Scholar
Inwood, B. and Donini, P. (1999) ‘Stoic ethics’, in Algra, Barnes, Mansfeld and Schofield (1999) 675–738.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ioppolo, A. M. (1980) Aristone di Chio e lo Stoicismo antico, Naples.Google Scholar
Isnardi Parente, M. (1992) ‘Fra Stoa e media Stoa’, SIFC 85, 596619.Google Scholar
Janko, R. (ed.) (2000) Philodemus, ‘On Poems’, book 1, Oxford and New York.Google Scholar
Keil, B. (1905) ‘Chrysippeum’, Hermes 40, 155–8.Google Scholar
Keith, T. R. (2013) ‘Plutarch on Chrysippus Peri biōn and the problem of the sage’, in Pace, G. and Cacciatore, P. Volpe (eds.), Gli scritti di Plutarco. Tradizione, traduzione, ricezione, commento. Atti del ix Convegno Internazionale della International Plutarch Society (Ravello, 29 settembre – 1 ottobre 2011), Naples, 257–62.Google Scholar
Laurand, V. (2005) La politique stoïcienne, Paris.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Long, A. A. (2002) Epictetus: a Stoic and Socratic guide to life, Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Long, A. A. and Sedley, D. (eds.) (1987) The Hellenistic philosophers: translation of the principal sources with philosophical commentary. Volume i, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (1986) ‘Diogenes Laertius on Stoic philosophy’, Elenchos 7, 295382.Google Scholar
Marrone, L. (1987) ‘Testi stoici ercolanesi’, CErc 17, 181–4.Google Scholar
Marrone, L. (1988) ‘Testi stoici ercolanesi ii’, CErc 18, 223–5.Google Scholar
McOsker, M. (2017) ‘Hiatus in Epicurean authors’, CErc 47, 145–62.Google Scholar
Nickau, K. (1972) ‘Zenodotos von Ephesos’ (no. 6), in Wissowa, G., Kroll, W. and Mistelhaus, K. (eds.), Paulys Realencyklopädie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft. Volume x.A.1, Stuttgart and Munich, 2345.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. (1993) ‘Poetry and the passions: two Stoic views’, in Brunschwig, J. and Nussbaum, M. C. (eds.), Passions & perceptions: studies in Hellenistic philosophy of mind. Proceedings of the Fifth Symposium Hellenisticum, Paris and Cambridge, 97149.Google Scholar
Obbink, D. (ed.) (1996) Philodemus, ‘On Piety’. Part 1: Critical text with commentary, Oxford and New York.Google Scholar
Obbink, D. and Vander Waerdt, P. A. (1991) ‘Diogenes of Babylon: the Stoic sage in the city of fools’, GRBS 32, 355–96.Google Scholar
Pohlenz, M. (1904) ‘Reste einer Schrift des Chrysippos?’, BphilWoch 24, 15021503.Google Scholar
Pohlenz, M. (1959) Die Stoa: Geschichte einer geistigen Bewegung, 2nd edn, Göttingen = La Stoa. Storia di un movimento spirituale (Italian tr.). Volume i, Florence.Google Scholar
Puglia, E. (1993) ‘Frammenti da P.Herc. 1158’, CErc 23, 2965.Google Scholar
Ranocchia, G. (2007a) Aristone, ‘Sul modo di liberare dalla superbia’, nel decimo libro ‘De vitiis’ di Filodemo, Florence.Google Scholar
Ranocchia, G. (2007b) ‘Filodemo e l'etica stoica. Per un confronto fra i trattati Sulla superbia e Sull'ira’, WJA n.F. 32, 147–68.Google Scholar
Ranocchia, G. (2021) ‘Philosophical vs. biographical: a new assessment of Greek literature Peri biōn’, Mnemosyne 75, 134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reydams-Schils, G. (1999) Demiurge and providence: Stoic and Platonist readings of Plato's Timaeus, Turnhout.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roskam, G. (2005) On the path to virtue: the Stoic doctrine of moral progress and its reception in (Middle-)Platonism, Leuven.Google Scholar
Sbordone, F. (1965) ‘Nuovi frammenti di papiri ercolanesi’, PdP 103, 308–12.Google Scholar
Schäfer, M. (1936) ‘Diogenes als Mittelstoiker’, Philologus n.F. 45, 174–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmekel, A. (1892) Die Philosophie der mittleren Stoa in ihrem geschichtlichen Zusammenhange dargestellt, Berlin.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. (1999) The Stoic idea of the city, 2nd edn, Chicago and London.Google Scholar
Searby, D. M. (1998) Aristotle in the Greek gnomological tradition, Uppsala.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. (1976) ‘Epicurus and his professional rivals’, in Bollack, J. and Laks, A. (eds.), Études sur l'Epicurisme antique, Cahiers de philologie 1, 119–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sedley, D. (1999) ‘The Stoic–Platonist debate on kathekonta’, in Ierodiakonou, K. (ed.), Topics in stoic Philosophy, Oxford, 128–52.Google Scholar
Strathmann, G. (1892) ‘De hiatus fuga, quam invenimus apud Philodemum Epicureum’, Jahresbericht über das Real-Progymnasium der Stadt Viersen 16, 228.Google Scholar
Tatakis, B. N. (1931) Panétius de Rhodes. Le fondateur du Moyen stoïcisme. Sa vie et son oeuvre, Paris.Google Scholar
Tieleman, T. (2003) Chrysippus’ ‘On affections: reconstruction and interpretation, Leiden and Boston.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vander Waerdt, P. A. (1991) ‘Politics and philosophy in Stoicism’, OSAPh 9, 185211.Google Scholar
Verhasselt, G. (2016) ‘What were works Περὶ βίων?’, Philologus 160, 5983.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
VH2 (1876) Herculanensium voluminum quae supersunt. Collectio altera. Volume xi, Naples.Google Scholar
Zeller, E. and Nestle, W. (1928) Grundriss der Geschichte der griechischen Philosophie, 13th edn, Leipzig.Google Scholar