Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x24gv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-01T14:06:53.452Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hume and the nominalist tradition

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Deborah Brown*
Affiliation:
School of History, Philosophy, Religion and Classics, The University of Queensland, St Lucia, QLD 4072, Australia

Abstract

Many of the central theses of Hume's philosophy – his rejection of real relations, universals, abstract objects and necessary causal relations – had precedents in the later medieval nominalist tradition. Hume and his medieval predecessors developed complex semantic theories to show both how ontologies are apt to become inflated and how, if we understand carefully the processes by which meaning is generated, we can achieve greater ontological parsimony. Tracing a trajectory from those medieval traditions to Hume reveals Hume to be more radical, particularly in his rejection of abstraction and abstract ideas. Hume's denial of general, abstract ideas is consistent with his philosophical principles but fails to appreciate the more sophisticated nominalist approaches to abstraction, the result of which is a theoretically impoverished account of our capacity for generalization.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abelard, P. 1969. “Theologia Christiana.” In Petri Abaelardi Opera Thelogica, 7375. Vol. 2 Buytaert, Eligius ed. Christianorum, Coprus (continuatio medievalis). Vol. 12 Brepols: Turnholt.Google Scholar
Adams, M. 1987. William Ockham. 2 vols. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Al-Ghazali, 1997. The Incoherence of the Philosophers. Translated and edited by Marmura, Michael Provo, UT: Brigham Young University Press.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. 1981. “Causality and Determination.” In Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Mind, 133147. University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Aquinas, T. 1966. On Being and Essence. Translated and edited by Boyer, C. Rome: Gregoriana.Google Scholar
Aristotle, 1984. The Complete Works of Aristotle. 2 vols. Edited by Barnes, Jonathan Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Baxter, D. 1997. “Abstraction, Identity and Inseparability.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (2): 307330.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkeley, George 1948–57. “A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge.” In The Works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne, edited by Luce, A. A. and Jessop, T.E. vol. 2, 41113. London: Thomas Nelson and Sons. 9 vols.Google Scholar
Bradley, F. H. 1897. Appearance and Reality. 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bradshaw, D. E. 1988. “Berkeley and Hume on Abstraction and Generalization.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 5 (1): 1122.Google Scholar
Brown, D. 1996. “The Puzzle of Names in Ockham's Theory of Mental Language.” Review of Metaphysics 50: 7999.Google Scholar
Copleston, F. C. 1973–74. “The Logical Empiricism of Nicholas of Autrecourt.Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 74: 249262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Marchia, Francisci 2010. Quaestiones in Secundum Librum Sententiarum (Reportatio A). Edited by Suarez-Nani, T. and Duba, W. Leuven University Press.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. [1897–1913] 1996. Oeuvres de Descartes. 11 vols. Edited by Adam, C. and Tannery, P. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Frede, M. and Patzig, G. 1988. Aristoteles Metaphysik Z. Munich: C.H. Beck.Google Scholar
Haldane, J. 2007. “Editorial Introduction: Hume on Mind and Causality.” Journal of Scottish Philosophy 5 (1): ivix.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
David, Hume 2001. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by Norton, David Fate and Norton, Mary J. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Locke, J. 1975. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Edited by Nidditch, P. H. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Malebranche, N. 1997. The Search After Truth. Translated and edited by Lennon, Thomas M. and Olscamp, Paul J. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Meinong, Alexius 1966. Hume Studies I. Translated and edited by Barber, K. F. Dissertation, University of Iowa.Google Scholar
Nadler, S. 1996. “No Necessary Connection: The Medieval Roots of the Occasionalist Roots of Hume.” Monist 79: 448466.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calvin G., Normore 1987. “The Tradition of Medieval Nominalism.” In Studies in Medieval Philosophy, edited by Wippel, John F. 201217. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Ockham, W. 1974. “Summa Logicae.” In Opera Philosophica (O.P.), edited by Boehner, I. P. Gal, G. and Brown, S. Vol. I. St. Bonaventure, NY: The Franciscan Institute at St. Bonaventure University.Google Scholar
Ockham, W. 1975. Summa Logicae: Theory of Terms, Part I. Translated and edited by Loux, Michael J. Vol. 1. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Ockham, W. 1980. “Quodlibeta.” In Opera Theologica (O.T.), edited by Wey, J. C. Vol. IX. St. Bonaventure, NY: The Franciscan Institute at St. Bonaventure University.Google Scholar
Otto of Freising and Rahewin. 1912. Gesta Frederici I Imperatoris. Edited by Simson, B. von Hanover: MGH SRG.Google Scholar
Pannacio, C. 1990. Connotative Terms in Ockham's Mental Language. Cahiers d’épistémologie n.9016. Group de Recherche en Épistémologie Compareé, Université du Québec à Montréal.Google Scholar
Pluta, O. 2001. “Buridan’s Theory of Identity.” In The Metaphysics and Natural Philosophy of John Buridan, edited by Thijssen, J. M. M. H. and Zupko, J. 4964. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Geneviève, Rodis-Lewis 1971. “Descartes aurait-il eu un professeur nominaliste?Archives de Philosophie 34: 3746.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. 1988. Matter, Space and Motion. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Stroud, B. 1977. Hume. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Tienson, J. 1984. “Hume on Universals and General Terms.” Nous 18 (2): 311330.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turnbull, M. 2009. “David Hume: A Catholic?Open House 194: 34.Google Scholar
Weinberg, J. 1964–65. “The Novelty of Hume’s Philosophy.Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 38: 1735.CrossRefGoogle Scholar