Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-ttngx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-14T05:23:37.631Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Constitutional Referrals by Ordinary Courts: A Platform for Judicial Dialogue and Another Toolkit for Judicial Resistance?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 April 2024

Michal Kovalčík*
Affiliation:
Masaryk University, Brno, Czechia, email: michal.kovalcik@law.muni.cz
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Constitutional referrals by ordinary courts – Judicial dialogue between constitutional courts and ordinary courts – Toolkit for judicial resistance – Novel taxonomy of features and functions of constitutional referrals – Separation of powers approach – Democratic decay – Self-defence mechanism – Mix of methodological approaches – Case study on Czechia

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of University of Amsterdam

Introduction: internal referrals by ordinary courts to constitutional courts

Contemporary scholarship has favoured a metaphor denoting the interaction between two courts as judicial dialogue.Footnote 1 While such dialogue can also be carried out through informal channels, this article focuses on a formalised, institutionalised judicial dialogue that requires an institutional framework within which it can be conducted.Footnote 2 I argue that the referrals by ordinary courts to constitutional courts can serve as a platform for such a dialogue. Moreover, I explain how this mechanism forms a unique toolkit in the hands of the judiciary vis-à-vis other branches of power, which is of special interest in a time of democratic backsliding.

A referral process in which one court has the ability to call upon another, particularly a superior court, for interpretations of law can be observed in various, mostly European, jurisdictions.Footnote 3 Perhaps the most popular is the preliminary ruling procedure in the EU.Footnote 4 However, this EU procedure derives from the constitutional referrals mechanism previously adopted in several national judicial systems of the member states, where ordinary courts might query a constitutional court.Footnote 5

In contrast to the preliminary ruling procedure before the European Court of JusticeFootnote 6 or the horizontal dialogue among international courts,Footnote 7 dialogue between constitutional courts and ordinary courts is considerably under-researched. Internal constitutional referrals have been analysed in more detail only by de Visser in her general comparative studyFootnote 8 and by other authors in writings on constitutional systems of particular countries.Footnote 9 Similarly, this mechanism has been overlooked by scholars dealing with abusive constitutionalism and democratic decay.Footnote 10 No one has yet viewed this mechanism through the lens of judicial resistance. Therefore, this article partially fills this gap and delivers the first more general study of this mechanism.

In this article I analyse constitutional referrals both theoretically and empirically, from a general perspective as well as in in-depth case study. I conceptualise this mechanism and provide a novel taxonomy of its main features (the first section) and functions (the second section). I frame this mechanism from the perspective of judicial dialogue on constitutional matters and argue that this mechanism might serve as an exclusive self-defence mechanism of the judiciary against other branches – as a vehicle for judicial resistance in the era of democratic backsliding. This original perspective contributes to the topical debate on judicial dialogue as well as judicial resilience.

To step out of the theoretical level, in the third section I demonstrate these claims on the single case study of Czechia. Czechia has not yet been subject to challenge of the same magnitude as its regional counterparts; however, clear signs of fragility and susceptibility to democratic backsliding might be observed. Thus, Kosař and Vyhnánek refer to Czechia as being in a state of ‘democratic careening’.Footnote 11 The healthy constitutional dialogue between courts and the institutional self-defence of the judiciary can therefore play a key role there. This is even more so given the intriguing evolution of the relationship between ordinary courts and the Czech Constitutional Court in the last 30 years.Footnote 12 Furthermore, in the light of the current cases before supranational courts involving Hungarian and Polish judges, claiming their right to independence,Footnote 13 Czech judges can be considered pioneers in this respect, as they have already been successful at the national level.

Unpacking constitutional referrals: the underlying features

The mechanism of constitutional referrals exists in every European state which has a specialised constitutional jurisdiction.Footnote 14 Its essence lies in concrete constitutional review (i.e. review of a law in the context of an actual case) initiated by ordinary courts – but only initiated. The final say belongs to a constitutional court that provides an answer on the constitutionality of an impugned statute or its particular provision.Footnote 15 Consequently, the referring court has to decide the case at hand in accordance with the constitutional court’s ruling.Footnote 16

That said, the dynamics of this mechanism vary depending on the legal (institutional), political and societal context within which it operates. What matter are, in particular, the other powers of the respective constitutional court and access of individuals to any kind of constitutional review. Take, on the one hand, systems with individual constitutional complaint (e.g. Germany, Austria, Switzerland, Poland, Czechia) or recurso de amparo (Spain), the French model with the long-term dominance of the parliamentary minority in access to constitutional review, recently seasoned by specific constitutional referrals that Pfersmann calls ‘indirect constitutional complaints’,Footnote 17 and, on the other hand, the Italian model where constitutional justices are mostly ‘judges of judges’Footnote 18 and where individual constitutional complaint is completely absent.Footnote 19 In systems with direct access of individuals to constitutional review (constitutional complaints), referrals by ordinary courts amount to a rather supplementary part of constitutional review – the vast majority of cases before these constitutional courts are brought by individuals, not courts.Footnote 20 On the other hand, in the Italian model constitutional referrals by ordinary courts represent the most important way of activating constitutional review. Below, I show how the political context (e.g. constitutional courts’ capture) or the socio-legal context (e.g. a complicated relationship between constitutional courts and ordinary courts in transitional democracies) shapes the functioning of constitutional referrals.

Although the dynamics of this mechanism differ across jurisdictions, some general conceptual remarks are in order. Using an institutional perspective, let us look in detail at six underlying features of the constitutional referrals mechanism as introduced above.

First, the precondition for constitutional referrals is the presence of a body to refer to – a constitutional court or another supreme court with a monopoly of constitutional review.Footnote 21 Thus, the mechanism of constitutional referrals, as perceived in this article, works only in the centralised model of constitutional review.Footnote 22 Even though some sort of internal preliminary reference in constitutional matters is conceivable also in the so-called diffuse model with decentralised constitutional review, that goes beyond the scope of constitutional referrals as understood in this text.Footnote 23 Centralised constitutional courts were mostly established as guardians straddling law and politics, organised separately from the rest of the court system.Footnote 24 Constitutional courts in countries adhering to the modern German model are closer to the ordinary judiciary, while in the French model the constitutional court (council) inclines more towards the political sphere. Nonetheless, mainly because of the extension of human rights and the influence of supranational courts (especially the European Court of Human Rights and the European Court of Justice), both ordinary and constitutional courts are far from being truly separate.Footnote 25 Rather, they retain their specifics, unique virtues and shortcomings, but can be deemed part of the judiciary in a broader sense.Footnote 26

Second, the whole mechanism is triggered by an ordinary court – either any court (e.g. in Germany, Poland, Belgium or Czechia)Footnote 27 or merely a court of a specific level (for example, in Bulgaria power to refer is reserved for the Supreme Court of Cassation and the Supreme Administrative Court alone; and the French model has already been mentioned).Footnote 28 Accordingly, we can distinguish: (a) the model with unlimited referrers (all ordinary courts); and (b) the model with limited referrers. Ordinary courts are generally empowered to interpret and apply ordinary law and, at the same time, they are not endowed with the power to strike down statutes incompatible with constitutional requirements.Footnote 29 The mechanism of constitutional referrals, however, gives ordinary courts an opportunity to pronounce, albeit to a limited extent, on the issue of constitutionality. As will be explained below, ordinary courts play a pivotal role in these proceedings since they embody gatekeepersFootnote 30 sifting through the caseload and, in a similar vein, ‘agenda-setters’ raising the reference.

Usually, though, ordinary courts are only the ‘secondary’ agenda-setters, as the initiating proceedings emanate from a case brought to a court by individuals whose role in these proceedings should also not be overlooked.Footnote 31 That holds true especially in the French model, where only parties may raise the question of unconstitutionality and, after the scrutiny of two ordinary courts (the court hearing the case at hand plus the Cour de Cassation or the Conseil d’etat, respectively the civil/criminal and administrative supreme courts),Footnote 32 the question is ‘only’ transmitted to the Constitutional Council. In other words, ordinary courts lodge questions that are not their own and the original parties are also the primary parties, even though they are not themselves empowered to transmit the referral (question).Footnote 33 Thus, Pfersmann refers to this model as ‘indirect constitutional complaint’ by individuals.Footnote 34 However, it is still important to bear in mind that dialogue takes place between two courts which somehow adopt the party’s question.

Third, as the review arises out of the regular adjudication of a case between parties, the constitutional referrals mechanism represents a type of concrete judicial review.Footnote 35 This type of review consists of the verification of whether a law to be applied in a particular judicial case is actually constitutional. It encompasses both referrals by ordinary courts (objective concrete review) and incidental review of legislation proposed by the parties during constitutional complaint proceedings (subjective concrete review).Footnote 36 However, as Sadurski points out, this kind of concrete review may sometimes be ‘contaminated by abstractness’.Footnote 37 Constitutional courts occasionally examine references by ordinary courts without really engaging with the facts of the case at hand and merely juxtapose a contentious law with the constitution in an abstract fashion. Hence, a formal ‘concrete’ review may virtually transform into an ‘abstract’ one.Footnote 38 At any rate, a specific case can sometimes reveal a constitutional problem which is not apparent in abstracto, and therefore a concrete review is a key way of protecting fundamental rights.Footnote 39

Fourth, a reference by an ordinary court to a constitutional court can, in various jurisdictions, take the form of either a question (the question model) or a motion (the motion model). The former is the European Court of Justice’s model – courts may (or shall) ask the European Court of Justice questions concerning the interpretation or validity of a law.Footnote 40 In the realm of constitutional referrals, that applies in a similar fashion. Ordinary judge do not have to be convinced that a law in question is unconstitutional; it suffices that they seriously doubt its constitutionality, and a constitutional court ultimately clarifies the matter. Italy and France, for example, employ this model.Footnote 41 On the other hand, in a less frequently used model,Footnote 42 which we can observe in Germany, Czechia or Slovakia,Footnote 43 for instance, a court submits a motion detailing reasons why it deems a pertinent law unconstitutional. Thus, in the motion model, a court ‘concludes’ – and does not ‘doubt’ (leastways from a formal point of view) – that a law is unconstitutional.

Fifth, following up on the previous aspect, reference may be compulsory or optional. For example, in Belgium, Germany and Czechia, if certain conditions are met the ordinary court shall refer.Footnote 44 Such conditions may appear as either substantive regarding the interpretation of a law in question (ex officio) or procedural, usually because of a request by the parties.Footnote 45 Although an ordinary court itself assesses the fulfilment of the necessary criteria, this setting, at least formally, does not permit discretion and thus can be referred to as obligatory. Failure to refer in such circumstances amounts to a violation of the law (the constitution). On the other hand, for instance, in Spain and France,Footnote 46 even if the specific criteria are met, the ordinary court only may refer the case to the constitutional court. In other words, the constitution lays down a margin of appreciation for ordinary judges – it is up to them. Although the line between the two is sometimes fluid, the discretionary model versus the compulsory model can be another typology.

Finally, the term ‘constitutional’ indicates a benchmark for review. Preliminary references can only be made concerning the potential unconstitutionality of statutes or their provisions which are to be applied, not for assistance to deal with any constitutional issue that ordinary courts encounter.Footnote 47 But what does ‘unconstitutionality’ mean? In the majority of countries, the grounds for initiating the preliminary reference procedure correspond to those for abstract review and include an entire constitutional order as such.Footnote 48 Nevertheless, in France, for example, the frame of reference consists only of ‘rights and liberties guaranteed by the Constitution’.Footnote 49 The concrete review instituted by the preliminary ruling mechanism is thus narrower than the abstract one.Footnote 50 In any case, a constitutional court has the final say regarding ambiguous questions about standards for reference (and review).

These six essential features of the constitutional referrals mechanism do not just perform an introductory function – it pays to keep them in mind, as these features permeate the rest of the article. They help us better to grasp the mechanism’s functions as well as the specific mechanism in the single case study.

Functions of constitutional referrals approached through the separation of powers

The mechanism of constitutional referrals can serve dozens of functions and there is little point in trying to list them all. However, this section strives to tackle at least some of the most important functions in respect judicial dialogue. First, though, it is necessary to explain an approach to this issue.

To analyse and classify the functions of constitutional referrals more systematically, I employ Barber’s approach to the separation of powers,Footnote 51 recently elaborated by Kavanagh.Footnote 52 They both distinguish negative and positive approaches to the separation of powers (emanating from so-called negative and positive constitutionalism). The negative approach focuses on building friction and seeks to keep the powers that be constrained by each other. On the other hand, the positive account emphasises the efficiency of exercising power – each branch has its specific expertise, skills and virtues and is designed to utilise these virtues for the wellbeing of the state as such.Footnote 53 For example, the judicial branch exists to resolve legal disputes and to interpret and – where needed – to adjust the law.Footnote 54 Through these functions and thanks to their legal expertise, skills and a certain immunity from electoral pressures, courts specifically contribute to the efficient state advancing the wellbeing of its members.Footnote 55

As the constitutional referrals procedure represents a subcategory of judicial review, it amounts to a tool of the judiciary vis-à-vis the legislature as well as the executive.Footnote 56 Thus, it is worthwhile viewing this mechanism from the separation of powers perspective. As explained above, being well aware of the special place of constitutional courts within European constitutionalism, I consider constitutional courts to be part of the judicial branch in a broader sense, and regard the judiciary as bifurcated into ‘constitutional’ and ‘regular’ arms.Footnote 57 Ordinary and constitutional courts are partners in a collaborative enterprise in promoting, tempering and defending a constitutional order.Footnote 58

Drawing on that, I divide the functions of the mechanism of constitutional referrals into negative and positive ones. Negative functions encompass: first, ensuring that the legislature does not overstep constitutional boundaries; and, second, protecting the rights of individuals in specific cases. This overlaps with two of de Visser’s four principal purposes of constitutional adjudication.Footnote 59 On the other hand, the positive functions comprise: first, ensuring the uniform interpretation of the constitution; second, securing the internal coherence of the legal order of the state; and, third, integrating ordinary courts into constitutional dialogue.Footnote 60 Now I elaborate on both categories in more detail.

Negative functions of constitutional referrals: the sword against the other branches of power

The negative functions embrace: (1) ensuring that the legislature does not overstep constitutional boundaries; and (2) protecting the rights of individuals in specific cases. The latter function is crucial – well-entrenched right-based theories maintain that efficacious protection of fundamental rights justify, to a great degree, the very existence of judicial review.Footnote 61 Even if numerous countries enable individuals to challenge a law (to be applied to their case) before a constitutional court via the constitutional complaint procedure, access to a constitutional court usually requires that remedies provided by an ordinary judiciary have been exhausted.Footnote 62 Accordingly, an ordinary court’s reference to the constitutional court is able to hasten the protection of an individual’s rights and facilitate access to justice. Moreover, as mentioned above, a concrete case can occasionally reveal a constitutional flaw that might not be apparent in an abstract review, since such a flaw fully manifests itself only during the application of a respective norm.

On the other hand, the first function – keeping the legislature in check – is the pivotal objective of abstract judicial review.Footnote 63 Nonetheless, I will explain the considerable importance of this function in respect of constitutional referrals as well. As has been outlined, the negative approach to the separation of powers stresses instruments capable of curbing abuse of power and thwarting looming arbitrariness.Footnote 64 In this vein, each institution has its swords (sanctions or threats that one institution can actively use against another) and shields (immunities that serve to protect institutions from each other).Footnote 65 Constitutional review embodies a sword which, to paraphrase Madison, keeps the legislature ‘in its proper place’.Footnote 66 However, abstract review usually requires activity of a different branch to be launched and concrete review through a constitutional complaint depends on an action by individuals. Only concrete review via constitutional referrals proceedings is a type of constitutional review exclusively assigned to the judiciary. Indeed, it initially needs a case to have been brought by individuals, but the procedural framework, which is usually open to all, gives rise to a large number of cases and also allows for a sort of strategic litigation.Footnote 67

Constitutional referrals can thus be viewed as an institutional self-defence mechanism.Footnote 68 In other words, they can be utilised as a vehicle for judicial resistance, by which I mean ‘set of techniques, tools and practices which courts or individual judges can use to prevent, avert, stay or punish imminent political attacks on judicial independence’.Footnote 69

Using this sword, the judiciary (the constitutional and ordinary judiciary acting together) may autonomously (vis-à-vis the legislature and the executive) defy legislative acts which, for instance, deprive courts of some powers or otherwise interfere with their independence. Yet, in addition to the judiciary being able to defend itself, using constitutional referrals it might also counter other acts jeopardising constitutional democracy.

Therefore, I deem this mechanism to be one of those that are, at least potentially, able to postpone or even resist the rule of law and democratic decay.Footnote 70 Utilising their respective specific virtues, the constitutional and ordinary judiciaries in collaboration can act as (at least) a ‘useful speed bump or stop sign’ against authoritarian initiatives.Footnote 71 As they are closer to the everyday problems of individuals, ordinary courts are better positioned than constitutional courts to identify swiftly threats that are minor at first sight but that can have far-reaching damaging effects on the rule of law and democracy.Footnote 72 But, most importantly, they wield the ‘activate button’ to launch the review before the constitutional court. Yet, they lack the power to strike down the law and their rulings often have only limited effects (especially when we look at the lower courts). On the other hand, constitutional courts have the power to quash the law, the potential to have a far-reaching impact because of high media attention and the legitimacy to counter democratic dysfunctions.Footnote 73 But they need their judicial fellows (ordinary courts/judges) to flag up the issue and, notably, to trigger the whole review procedure.

In jurisdictions without constitutional referrals by ordinary courts, the ordinary judiciary is usually entitled to strike down – or, at least, not apply – the unconstitutional law in question. In the model with diffused judicial review, constitutional issues are raised and adjudicated on during ordinary litigation and there is no procedure specifically designed to protect constitutional principles.Footnote 74 Thus, individual constitutional protection may come sooner and more easily, but large-scale systemic effects (lying at the core of this negative function) arrive much later, when the case filters through the net to the apex courts (or often to the Supreme Court). That is also the case with mixed systems (a mix of diffused and centralised review) without constitutional referrals.Footnote 75

On the other hand, the relevance of the constitutional referrals mechanism is growing in countries where individual constitutional complaint is lacking, and the only way to activate the constitutional court from the bottom is via referral by ordinary courts (see above, mainly the Italian and French model of constitutional review). However, in systems where individuals also have access to constitutional review, the way via constitutional referrals is more straightforward and can speed up the countering of democratic dysfunction. Moreover, constitutional referrals can be seen – alongside the general protection of constitutional values – particularly as an exclusive tool of the judiciary in its resilience, that is, in protecting particular values linked with courts (primarily judicial independence).

This negative feature is akin to the way Polish and Hungarian judges at the supranational level have resisted pressure from their (former) populist governments. They have submitted external references to the European Court of Justice or individually to the European Court of Human Rights.Footnote 76 If the constitutional court in question has not yet been captured (as it has been in the case of Poland and Hungary),Footnote 77 the constitutional referrals mechanism poses a similar framework for resistance, but at the domestic level. Certainly – similarly to other tools of judicial resilience – courts alone cannot save democracy. Yet, they can play a crucial role in hindering erosive processes.Footnote 78

Nonetheless, there is a threat that the judiciary will abuse this sword to advance its own interests, e.g. by defying various accountability mechanisms or never allowing its salaries to be cut. Hence, this tool should be utilised prudently and rarely. Here, it holds true more than anywhere else that judicial review must be responsive – cautious of the degree of legal support and political justification there is for the ruling.Footnote 79 Failure to be so risks undermining public trust in the judiciary, resentment by a society which views judges as an untouchable elite group, and thus prepares a breeding ground for politicians aiming to capture the judiciary.Footnote 80 I will return to this issue again at the end of the case study.

Positive functions of constitutional referrals: consistency and integration

Through their positive functions courts live up to their role in the separation of powers as they use their expertise in the interpretation of the law and power to elucidate authoritatively what the law actually is.Footnote 81 They are well placed to deal with constitutional uncertainties and rectify some deficiencies which might otherwise lead to legal turmoil.Footnote 82 Accordingly, via constitutional referrals, the judiciary can: (1) secure the consistent interpretation of the constitution; (2) prevent contradictions in the legal system; and, finally, (3) publicly deliberate on constitutional issues.

The first function targets the future and represents a manifestation of a prospective effect of judicial decision-making. A constitutional court assesses the constitutionality of a challenged statute (its provision) and sets the record straight – either striking down the statute (its provision) or providing a guideline for a constitutionally conforming statutory interpretation. Constitutional courts are vested with a monopoly on these matters (contrary to the diffuse model of judicial review) and have more time to engage in deep contemplation of the fundamental issues involved.Footnote 83 Therefore, it should be guaranteed that they deliver uniform and sufficiently reasoned interpretations of the constitution capable of becoming widely accepted. That fosters legal stability and certainty and is one of the underlying principles of the rule of law.Footnote 84

This function is further amplified in systems with the question model, where the fact that the ordinary court doubts the constitutionality of a law suffices for it to submit a case to the constitutional court.Footnote 85 By not requiring an ordinary court’s assurance that a pertinent law is unconstitutional (the motion model), the way to a constitutional court is more permeable, which should enable a constitutional court to pronounce on more ambiguous issues. The limits of this function lie in the fact that a precondition for a ruling of a constitutional court is a decision by an ordinary court to refer. If an ordinary court chooses to resolve the question of its own accord (notwithstanding whether it is in accordance with the law or not), it will deprive a constitutional court, at least temporarily, of the opportunity to express its final opinion. In that case, ordinary judges must be careful that they do not alter the division of labour that the system is based on.Footnote 86

Ensuring the uniform interpretation of the constitution is closely linked with the second function – securing the internal coherence of the state’s legal order. Also, this function reinforces the stability of the law and legal certainty. Since ordinary courts have to apply a statute unless the constitutional court declares it unconstitutional, that prevents (at least in the long run) the situation where a particular law is applied by one court and not applied as unconstitutional by another.Footnote 87 Indeed, that is not the case absolutely, as a temporary inconsistency among ordinary courts can occur while the referred case is pending before the constitutional court. Nonetheless, it is a small price to pay for the fact that an ordinary court is not compelled to apply – from its point of view – an unconstitutional provision. By striking a justifiable balance between this limited autonomy of the ordinary courts and the centralisation of a power to quash laws, the coherence of the legal order is undoubtedly better safeguarded by use of the mechanism of constitutional referrals than without it.

Finally, the significant function of the mechanism of constitutional referrals is its capability to integrate the ordinary courts into constitutional dialogue. Even though ordinary judges’ day-to-day business consists of the interpretation and application of non-constitutional law, they are at the front line in dealing with the norms and principles emanating from the constitution. This is, according to Sadurski, ‘the standard rationale’ for granting the power of concrete judicial review to ordinary courts.Footnote 88 Thus, the procedure of constitutional referrals puts ordinary courts in dialogue with constitutional courts and allows them to pronounce on a given constitutional issue. This will be thoroughly investigated in the following section.

Constitutional referrals as a platform for judicial dialogue

Constitutional referrals provide a unique procedural framework within which ordinary courts communicate directly with a constitutional court. Communication in which a court stands on at least one side is referred to as judicial dialogue.Footnote 89 Since dialogue through constitutional referrals takes place between two courts in a special hierarchical relationship within one state, in Rosas’ categorisation, it can be classified as a domestic vertical dialogue.Footnote 90

Although the subject matter of such dialogue may encompass various legal questions, the crux of the dispute revolves around the issue of constitutionality. Therefore, dialogue through this mechanism might be seen as a type of constitutional dialogue.Footnote 91 This notion has gained currency in North American scholarship to portray interactions between political institutions and the constitutional judiciary,Footnote 92 and, in time, it has travelled across the ocean. In accordance with Groussot, I use the term to include interactions specifically within the judicial branch – between constitutional courts and ordinary courts.Footnote 93

Nevertheless, constitutional referrals virtually create a dialogic triangle between (1) ordinary courts, certifying the matter to the constitutional court, (2) the legislature, whose acts are subjected to constitutional scrutiny; and (3) the constitutional court itself.Footnote 94 Each vertex of such triangle is given the opportunity to pronounce on the constitutional matter in question, each in accordance with its role in the separation of powers. As Alec Stone-Sweet aptly remarks, by ongoing interactions of all these three actors, the construction of constitutional law is driven.Footnote 95

Thus, the constitutional referrals are part of discursive constitutionalism,Footnote 96 of a ‘continuing colloquy’ among the judiciary, political institutions and society at large on the requisites and demands of constitutional democracy.Footnote 97 As Ferreres Comella points out, the 2008 reform in France, which established the constitutional referrals procedure (question prioritaire de constitutionalité),Footnote 98 has facilitated the emergence of richer constitutional conversations.Footnote 99 Driven mainly by the so-called Melki saga, this ‘legal revolution promising to bring human rights back to its homeland’ prompted the French debate (not only) on judicial and constitutional politics.Footnote 100

Since the centralised model of judicial review otherwise furnishes ordinary courts with only limited opportunities to pronounce on these matters and to communicate directly with a constitutional court,Footnote 101 judicial dialogue on constitutional matters represents an important function of constitutional referrals. In European constitutionalism, the role of constitutional courts in constitutional interpretation ‘tends to be closed and exclusive’.Footnote 102 That said, thanks to its unique institutional design straddling the political and legal spheres, constitutional courts wield great deliberative potential.Footnote 103 Within this procedure, ordinary and constitutional courts can talk directly to each other about constitutional issues, while this talk is formalised, public and thus approachable for at least a professional audience. It is an institutionalised legal discourseFootnote 104 on fundamental values, principles and rights within the judicial branch of power. To underline it in Habermas’ spirit, such public discourse constitutes a procedural ground of liberal democracy.Footnote 105

Ordinary courts differ from constitutional courts in many respects – they encounter problems of ‘laws in action’ on a daily basis and are closer to the commonplace issues of individuals. On the other hand, a constitutional court is able to bring a broader perspective as well as profound expertise to constitutional law and human rights. Although they each have their pros and cons, their dialogue merges their virtues together. This might be described as ‘cross-fertilisation’ within the domestic legal order.Footnote 106 By exchanging the arguments of actors from distinct contexts, the dialogue via constitutional referrals is able to promote better-reasoned judgments and thus rationalise legal outcomes.Footnote 107 That is crucial, as communication is an essential weapon in a court’s arsenal; lacking a purse and a sword that is actually robust (vis-à-vis other branches), the judiciary relies on persuasive legal argument.Footnote 108 Therefore, the difference between ordinary courts and a constitutional court is a strong case for – and not against – their conversation on constitutional matters.

In this fashion, ordinary courts and a constitutional court are collaborators in upholding constitutionality.Footnote 109 The review of legislation via constitutional referrals is carried out on two levels – first, by a preliminary check by an ordinary court and, second, by a constitutional court with its final and binding assessment. Thus, constitutional review can be viewed as a dialogic. Even though Tushnet and Roach used the term ‘dialogic judicial review’ to address relations outside the judicial branch, between the judiciary and the legislature,Footnote 110 we can stay within it and develop its intra-judicial aspect. Ideally, the two courts will deliver their opinions on the constitutional issue and respond to each other – this interplay then provides the outcome.

The opportunity of the ordinary courts to make an initial assessment and to pronounce on the matter of constitutionality represents a specific manifestation of the principle of subsidiarity, encapsulating the fact that fundamental rights must, even in a centralised model of constitutional review, first and foremost be protected by lower-level courts.Footnote 111 Apart from accelerating the protection of individuals’ rights, such setting might contribute to the ‘constitutional cultivation’Footnote 112 of ordinary courts, which is important notably in jurisdictions with short experience of liberal constitutionalism.Footnote 113

Moreover, dialogue is, as Groussot observes, not only a means of communication but also a medium of power.Footnote 114 By way of dialogue via constitutional referrals, ordinary courts can assert their view on the interpretation or validity of a law and try to persuade a constitutional court. Subsequently, lower courts can use this mechanism to ‘leapfrog’ the ordinary judicial hierarchy, especially if they do not agree (or anticipate that they will not agree) with the interpretation of higher ordinary courts.Footnote 115 However, it could also be the other way round – Dyevre, for example, argues that the new concrete review mechanism in France empowered the Constitutional Council and – at the same time – posed a threat to the influence of the Cour de cassation.

In any event, healthy constitutional dialogue requires two preconditions: mutual respect and the active engagement of both actors in communication. If a constitutional court does not respect the ordinary courts, it will disregard or even mock the arguments in the reference. And vice versa, if an ordinary court does not respect a constitutional court, it will be reluctant to submit the reference. Last but not least, if an ordinary court does not want to engage in constitutional debate, there will be no dialogue. In that case, not only will an ordinary court deprive the community as a whole of vibrant deliberation on a constitutional matter,Footnote 116 but it will also fall short of its role in the separation of powers by not utilising all its available virtues.

Furthermore, it should be reiterated that the mode of dialogue also depends on the broader institutional framework in the particular state (apart from the institutional design of constitutional referrals proceedings), as well as on its political and socio-legal context. The (non-)existence of an individual constitutional complaint in particular is a gamechanger. If it is not present, constitutional referral is often the only way in which the constitutional court can pronounce on the certain issue. Therefore, its approach to the ordinary courts should be all the more respectful and open.Footnote 117

To sum up, constitutional referrals offer a platform for constitutional dialogue between ordinary courts and a constitutional court. It is an important function of this mechanism, as it allows ordinary courts to pronounce on constitutional matters and directly communicate with a constitutional court. Such a judicial dialogue can rationalise and legitimise the outcome of legal disputes. However, it does not work without active courts with mutual respect.

Empirical study: how it works in practice

In this section I will examine the theoretical claims using the example of Czechia, a country with centralised constitutional review, following the Germany prototype. Czechia belongs to the Central and Eastern Europe region, where many countries have experienced democratic backsliding and has a still relatively fragile democracy in a state of ‘democratic careening’,Footnote 118 albeit spared from grave democratic excesses.Footnote 119 Czechia has also undergone an intriguing evolution of the relationship between the the Czech Constitutional Court and the ordinary courts since the establishment of the new, post-Communist state in 1993. Mainly in the first decade, the Czech Constitutional Court promoted an anti-formalist type of judicial interpretation and regularly criticised the excessive textual positivism deeply embedded in the post-Communist perception of the application of laws.Footnote 120 Keeping this in mind, it is no surprise that several clashes between the purposive interpretation and value-laden reasoning of the Czech Constitutional Court and the judicial formalism of the Supreme Court have arisen over time. The most famous one, when the Supreme Court refused to respect the case law of the Constitutional Court, went down in history as ‘the war of the courts’.Footnote 121 This term is also used to describe the skirmish between the Constitutional Court and the Supreme Administrative Court.Footnote 122

The Czech Constitutional Court is entrusted with both abstract and concrete judicial review, but only ex post (with the marginal exception of international treaties assessment). An abstract assessment of constitutionality can be initiated by the President of the Republic or a group of members of Parliament, whilst concrete review might be triggered either by individuals and a Panel of the Constitutional Court in connection with the constitutional complaint procedure or by an ordinary court when it encounters a potentially unconstitutional provision in the course of deciding any case (i.e. the mechanism of constitutional referrals).Footnote 123 Thus, abstract and both objective and subjective concrete review exist in Czechia.

The key provision of the Czech Constitution stipulating the constitutional referrals procedure is Article 95(2), which states: ‘Should a court reach the conclusion that a statute which should be applied in the resolution of a matter is not compatible with the constitutional order, it shall submit the matter to the Constitutional Court.’Footnote 124 Using the typology outlined in the first chapter, it is (1) the model of unlimited referrers, as all ordinary courts can refer; (2) the motion model, since ordinary courts have to ‘reach the conclusion’ – and not just have ‘doubts’ (leastways from a formal point of view) – that a law is unconstitutional; (3) the compulsory model because, if certain conditions are met, the ordinary court shall refer. Even though there is formally no discretion, it is up to the ordinary court to determine whether it finds that the conditions for reference – i.e. the conflict of a statute to be applied with the constitutional order – have been met.

In my empirical study I seek to explore whether this mechanism truly serves as a platform for dialogue on constitutional issues or is instead just a series of utterances by two actors who do not listen to each other. Beyond the very existence of dialogue, I aim to reveal some nuances of interaction via this mechanism related to the positive and negative functions explained above. To do so, I have analysed all the submissions by the ordinary courts and the subsequent rulings of the Czech Constitutional CourtFootnote 125 issued during the period from January 2014 to December 2022. These amount to 70 submissions by ordinary courts and 70 subsequent rulings by the Constitutional Court. My study thus covers the so-called ‘Third Constitutional Court’ (also labelled as Zeman’s Constitutional Court), the era of the Czech Constitutional Court with Justices appointed by the former President, Miloš Zeman.Footnote 126 This era can be referred to as the first ‘normal’ one, that is to say, dealing with quite ordinary questions of an established constitutional democracy as opposed to controversial transitional issues (The First Constitutional Court) or sovereignty issues linked to access to the EU (The Second Constitutional Court). This sample thus allows me to isolate the most significant outlier variables. Moreover, this era is interesting, given the questions raised in the previous section, as it overlaps with the rise of the populist leader, Andrej Babiš, the Prime Minister from 2017 to 2021 and very influential Minister of Finance from 2014 to 2017.Footnote 127

Before delving into the analysis itself, a brief data appetizer on constitutional referrals in Czechia is in order. The vast majority of the Czech Constitutional Court’s docket consists of individual constitutional complaints (around 95 per cent). It is not surprising that constitutional review linked with individual complaint is the most common type of judicial review before the Constitutional Court. However, among all ‘qualified’ petitioners empowered to propose the annulment of the statute (i.e. not individuals in connection with their constitutional complaint), ordinary courts are the most frequent and most successful petitioners. From the establishment of Czechia in 1993 to the end of 2022, the Constitutional Court delivered 334 decisions within the constitutional referrals procedure and the number of submissions decreases year on year.Footnote 128

Now, let us move to the analysis. It is two-tiered – it has macro and micro levels.Footnote 129

Macro level: constitutional dialogue in the majority of cases

At the macro-level I conducted a content analysis – all judicial opinions were hand-coded based on the codebook attached in the Appendix (online). As to the submissions of ordinary courts, I focused on the constitutional argument of ordinary courts and looked into whether or not the ordinary courts in their reasoning argued by constitutional principles, referred to the case law of the Czech Constitutional Court or the European Court of Human Rights or to the constitutional scholarship. This stems from the assumption that greater contemplation on constitutional matters requires more than merely working with the text of the constitution itself. On the other hand, regarding the rulings of the Czech Constitutional Court, I examined whether or not the Court had responded to the constitutional arguments of the ordinary court, i.e. whether it dealt with these arguments, took them into consideration and provided answers to them: in other words, whether the Court entered the dialogue. For purposes of this article, I label this a discursive style of reasoning.Footnote 130

After analysing the data through descriptive statistics (frequencies and crosstabs), I found that the ordinary courts argued on constitutional principles such as the separation of powers, equality, judicial independence or proportionality, in 63 per cent of cases. They referred to the case law of the Czech Constitutional Court or the European Court of Human Rights in 70 per cent of cases and to scholarly writing addressing the pertinent constitutional issue in only 17 per cent of cases. Leaving aside the literature references, generally not very frequent in judicial reasonings in Czechia,Footnote 131 the constitutional principles argument and references to the case law appear together in more than half of all submissions, and in only 17 per cent of cases do we find neither of them. On the other hand, the discursive style of reasoning (i.e. the explicit responsiveness of the Czech Constitutional Court to the arguments of the ordinary courts) is present in 64 per cent of all that Court’s rulings, in 71 per cent of those that followed submission with constitutional argument. However, the results suggest that there is no strong link between constitutional argumentation by ordinary courts and a likelihood of discursivity at the Czech Constitutional Court. In other words, it does not appear from the data that arguing constitutional principles, referring to the case law or to constitutional scholarship, would increase the chances of ordinary courts receiving an explicit response to their arguments in their submissions. The Czech Constitutional Court is sometimes discursive even when deeper constitutional law arguments are lacking – and vice versa.

Indeed, an individual reference to the constitutional principles, case law or literature in argument does not constitute dialogue and, likewise, a discursive style of reasoning does not necessarily indicate a meaningful conversation on constitutional matters. However, incorporating all of these elements together, the results provide a valid and reliable picture of the presence or absence of constitutional dialogue in the constitutional referrals procedure. Thus, in the majority of cases, a dialogue on constitutional matters between ordinary courts and the Czech Constitutional Court can be discerned. The data show that constitutional referrals often serve as a platform for inter-judicial constitutional dialogue, as opposed to just a series of unresponsive monologues.

Micro level: disrespectful dialogue and the judicial sword

At the micro level, I employ an in-depth qualitative analysis of these cases (contextual interpretation, idiographic study).Footnote 132 From the dataset on the macro level, I have singled out three most intriguing cases, given the functions of constitutional referrals presented above. By conducting a nuanced analysis of these cases I uncovered some details and peculiarities hidden at the macro level.Footnote 133 In particular, the macro-level analysis was not able to capture the quality and manner of interaction. Dialogue can be healthy, courteous, constructive and mutually enriching, but also disrespectful, condescending and even toxic.Footnote 134

A constructive inter-judicial dialogue on constitutional matters was evident in the majority of cases in which ordinary courts presented sound constitutional reasoning and the Czech Constitutional Court explicitly responded to their arguments.Footnote 135 Notwithstanding the formal result of the case, the mechanism of constitutional referrals in such circumstances fulfils its functions, the ordinary courts are integrated into constitutional issues,Footnote 136 the Czech Constitutional Court lives up to its role, and a professional audience at least can observe this institutionalised legal discourse.Footnote 137

Nevertheless, one of the preconditions for healthy dialogue – mutual respect – is not always present or, maybe more accurately, is not visible to outside observers. An example is the 2020 case of the Supreme Administrative Court’s submission, which seeks to annul the provision of the Code of Administrative JusticeFootnote 138 setting the expiry of the time limit for bringing an action for an administrative authority’s failure to act.Footnote 139 Although the Czech Constitutional Court responded to the principal arguments of the petitioner, it did so in a condescending manner, rejecting the arguments of the Supreme Administrative Court as completely out of touch.Footnote 140 For instance, the Constitutional Court stated that ‘to accept the argument put forward by the Supreme Administrative Court would deny the very essence of the functioning of the judiciary in the Czech Republic’.Footnote 141 Subsequently, the Constitutional Court derisively concluded that ‘the Supreme Administrative Court, after twenty years [of validity of the impugned provision], out of the blue realised that the provision is unconstitutional’.Footnote 142 The mere fact that three dissenting Justices of the the Constitutional Court agreed with the Supreme Administrative Court implies that the reasons provided by the petitioner were not completely pointless, as the Constitutional Court’s contemptuous tone suggests.

In a similar vein, the Czech Constitutional Court in May 2022 dismissed the submission of the District Court, asking it to strike down the provision of the Act on Courts and JudgesFootnote 143 setting the age limit of 70 years for the retirement of judges.Footnote 144 The plaintiff, a 69-year-old judge of the Higher Court, who was to retire in December 2023 at the latest, demanded that the District Court decide on the determination (the lawsuit for determination)Footnote 145 whether his legal relationship with the Higher Court would exist after December 2023. At the same time, he argued that the age limit of 70 years was discriminatory, as other professionals did not have to retire compulsorily. The District Court concurred and referred the case to the Czech Constitutional Court.

The Constitutional Court, again in a very contemptuous manner, held that the District Court should not have dealt with the original lawsuit at all, let alone referred the case to the Constitutional Court. Since judges perform public functions, civil courts do not possess the power to scrutinise their legal status, ‘just as it cannot determine, for example, who is the President of the Republic, a Member of Parliament or the Public Defender of Rights’.Footnote 146 While the rationale had already been elucidated, it seems that the Constitutional Court in the following paragraphs merely wanted to underline the outrageousness of the District Court’s proposal. For example, the Constitutional Court stated that ‘if a statute unambiguously provides for something, it makes no sense for a court to determine that the statute actually applies’. It concluded that ‘this type of lawsuit does not serve to express the plaintiffs’ disagreement with a particular piece of legislation’ and the courts ‘are not supposed to function as a kind of legal advice centre’.Footnote 147

Six Justices attached their joint dissenting opinion, in which they argued that the submission should have been dismissed on substantive grounds but not because of a lack of the District Court’s authority to hear the lawsuit.Footnote 148 The dissenting Justices, among other things, criticised the way in which the majority dealt with the submission. They labelled the majority’s remark on turning courts into ‘legal advice centres’ as ‘completely inappropriate’ and pointed out that the Constitutional Court had simply said ‘not this way, folks’ without at least suggesting a viable alternative.Footnote 149 The Czech Constitutional Court thereby did not live up to its role in the constitutional dialogue.

These two cases reveal the flip side of the interaction between the Czech Constitutional Court and ordinary courts. Heterarchy, comity and mutually enriching exchange of opinions and ideas between two partners are sidelined, whilst hierarchy and conflict take the lead.Footnote 150 Instead of integrating ordinary courts into contemplation on constitutional matters, the Constitutional Court in these cases stressed its exclusive superiority in constitutional interpretation and treated the ordinary courts as pupils who dared to propose such a thing. In other words, the Constitutional Court used the judicial dialogue as a medium of power.Footnote 151 This represents a switch from interpretative constitutional pluralism to interpretative constitutional monism.Footnote 152

Such an approach contributes nothing positive to the legal order. On the contrary, it can even discourage ordinary courts from using constitutional referrals. This approach might explain the downward trend in the number of constitutional referrals in Czechia over the last decade.Footnote 153 In terma of repercussions, not only does it deprive the interested part of society of the public institutionalised deliberation on a constitutional matter,Footnote 154 but it also frustrates both other positive and negative functions of constitutional referrals. The potential to confine the legislature, protect human rights, remove contradictions from the legal order or consistently interpret the constitution – all will be, in the best-case scenario, delayed.Footnote 155

The second case further displays an example of how constitutional referrals can serve as strategic litigation by judges. Judges are a specific group of litigants – almost 6 per cent of analysed cases were brought before an ordinary court by judges. Judges attempted to raise their subjective right to judicial independence, and through this vehicle achieve a derogation from certain pieces of undesired legislation (on retirement age, salaries, disciplinary proceedings).Footnote 156 The following, third, example clearly demonstrates this phenomenon.

In 2014, the Czech Constitutional Court again ruled in in the endless saga of judicial salaries.Footnote 157 In this case, a judge of the Regional Court claimed for payment of the difference between his entitlement to salary before and after the amendment by which Parliament reduced judges’ salaries as part of an austerity package responding to the effects of the economic crisis. Before the Municipal Court, the plaintiff (the judge) proposed that the case be referred to the Constitutional Court in order to annul the amendment. And the Municipal Court did so.

As hinted, it was not the first time the Czech Constitutional Court had dealt with cuts in judges’ pay.Footnote 158 The Constitutional Court has consistently reiterated that the independence of the judiciary ranks among fundamental principles of the Czech legal order, and the reduction in judicial salaries is per se a violation of such independence, as it could be abused as a form of governmental or legislative pressure upon the judicial branch.Footnote 159 Unsurprisingly, judges are aware of this case law and know that the Constitutional Court has so far always sided with them.Footnote 160 This was also the case here. The Constitutional Court, with reference to the previous case law, struck down the contested amendment.Footnote 161

The judiciary thus achieved the annulment of the unwanted law without any outside involvement. A judge initiated the dispute, the first instance court created a petition, and the Czech Constitutional Court accomplished the work. That shatters traditional narratives that courts will not hear cases unless someone outside the judiciary wishes to initiate the proceedings and bring the case to court.Footnote 162 Since judges do not have privileged status to challenge laws in abstract review procedure in Czechia, it turned constitutional referrals to the quasi-abstract judicial review. Therefore, it works as a perfect institutional self-defence mechanism of the judiciary.Footnote 163 The judiciary holds a sword that might be used but is also – as is nearly everything – misused vis-à-vis the legislative branch. As noted above, we can view constitutional referrals as a mechanism for defending against an amendment that threatens the rule of law at the onset of a surge of authoritarian populism.Footnote 164 In other words, as a toolkit of judicial resistance in relation to abusive constitutionalism and democratic decay.Footnote 165

Nonetheless, as stated above, there is a threat that the judiciary will abuse this sword to advance its own interests, e.g. by never allowing its salaries to be cut. And since even the road to hell is paved with good intentions, this tool should be utilised prudently and rarely. Failure to do so risks undermining public trust in the judiciary and fostering resentment in society, creating the sense that judges are an untouchable elite group, which thus becomes a breeding ground for politicians aiming to capture the judiciary.Footnote 166

Furthermore, when constitutional courts are captured by political forces, as has been the case in countries like Hungary and Poland,Footnote 167 the constitutional referrals process becomes futile for the purposes outlined above, leaving recourse to supranational courts as the only viable alternative.Footnote 168 In contrast, in such an environment constitutional referrals can be abused as another tool of the ruling political majority. For instance, if a populist government wants to repeal a certain piece of legislation without overtly doing so itself, it can use constitutional referral submitted by a loyal ordinary-court judge. In doing so, it delegates this unpopular decision to formally independent bodies.Footnote 169 In a similar vein, judges who have deferred to the interests of a populist government can abuse constitutional referrals as an instrument for so-called judicial populism.Footnote 170

Conclusion: beyond judicial dialogue

This article has unpacked the mechanism of constitutional referrals by ordinary courts. Building upon the conceptual analysis, I have sketched the typology of constitutional referrals as: (1) the question and the motion model; (2) the discretionary model and the compulsory model; or (3) the model of unlimited referrers (all ordinary courts) and the model with limited referrers. Furthermore, using Barber’s approach to the separation of powers, I have identified several negative and positive functions of constitutional referrals. I have presented two main arguments – that constitutional referrals can serve as: (1) a platform for inter-judicial dialogue on constitutional matters; and (2) an exclusive tool of the judicial branch against the legislature.

All of the identified functions demonstrate the uniqueness of constitutional referrals, and the necessity of having healthy relationships between constitutional actors in any well-functioning pluralistic democracy governed under the rule of law.Footnote 171 Deliberation on constitutional issues is able to give rise to better-reasoned judgments and rationalise legal outcomes.Footnote 172 That is crucial, as persuasive communication is an essential weapon in the arsenal of the judiciary, whose fate rests on public trust. The importance of well-considered judicial decisions is increasing, especially in the era of ‘a pandemic of populists’Footnote 173 who usually portray courts and judges as enemies, as part of the elite restricting the will of the pure people.Footnote 174

Based on the single case study, I have empirically confirmed that constitutional referrals often serve as a platform for inter-judicial constitutional dialogue. Nonetheless, these dialogues differ significantly in terms of style of reasoning and communication, as well as the motivation of actors. Dialogue is not always harmonious and sometimes lacks sufficient respect from the superior court.

Moreover, empirical findings are in line with the assumption of the theoretical part that constitutional referrals proceedings might serve as a tool of the judicial branch against the legislature,Footnote 175 a tool which – through the possibility of strategic litigation by judges – is completely in the hands of the judiciary. Judges, claiming their right to independence, can, together with their colleagues on both ordinary and constitutional levels, achieve derogation from undesired legislation. This can be abused as a quasi-abstract review, but might also be viewed as an institutional self-defence mechanism of the judiciary against the attempts of politicians to dismantle the rule of law. In this regard, Czech judges can be viewed as pioneers in the light of the current litigation by Hungarian and Polish judges before the supranational courts.

Although the empirical study was conducted on the example of Czechia, the observations could be helpful for theoretical analyses as well as comparisons with other countries in the region and beyond. The institutional frameworks of states with constitutional referrals mechanisms are very often similar, which makes it possible to examine the impact of legal or constitutional culture, the political reality, as well as historical implications for different uses of constitutional referrals in practice. Since Czechia represents a relatively still fragile democracy in the state of ‘democratic careening’,Footnote 176 this article contributes to the topical discussion on democratic decay. It introduces a new tool of judicial resistance vis-à-vis political interference aimed at undermining not only judicial independence but also the rule of law as such.Footnote 177 However, in countries where constitutional courts have already been captured by political authorities (e.g. Hungary and Poland),Footnote 178 it does not fulfil this purpose and the only option is to refer to supranational courts.Footnote 179 On the other hand, in this context the mechanism can serve as another tool of the ruling power or as an instrument for so-called judicial populism.Footnote 180

Despite the exploratory nature of the empirical study, it sheds light on how courts work with this mechanism. Moreover, the theoretical part provides the initial conceptualisation of constitutional referrals and the novel framing of it through the lense of Barber’s theory of the separation of powers. Therefore, the article represents the first but crucial step in a more thorough understanding of constitutional referrals. Drawing on the findings of this article, future research may focus on individual judges and their motivations to utilise – or, on the other hand, disincentives to avoid – this mechanism. A comparative study of multiple jurisdictions, using the conceptual framework presented, might be another way to proceed with follow-up research. Either way, the constitutional referrals pose a unique framework for institutionalised legal discourse and should be the focus of constitutional scholarship.

Supplementary material

To view supplementary material for this article, please visit https://doi.org/10.1017/S1574019624000087

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to David Kosař, Robert Zbíral, Eoin Carolan, Tom Daly and other participants in the UCD Centre for Constitutional Studies’ annual works-in-progress workshop in Dublin, and to anonymous reviewers and EuConst editors for their comments, which have significantly improved this text. The usual caveats apply. Since June 2023, I have been working part-time at the Constitutional Court of the Czech Republic, but all the opinions expressed are my own and do not reflect the views of the institution, I have not been involved in any way in the decisions discussed and the article is based only on publicly available information. The research leading to this article has received funding from the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme (INFINITY, grant no. 101002660).

Data availability statement

The author confirm that the data supporting the findings of this study are available within the article and its supplementary materials.

References

1 See M. Cartabia, ‘Europe and Rights: Taking Dialogue Seriously’, 5 EuConst (2009) p. 5; S. Bogojević, ‘Judicial Dialogue Unpacked: Twenty Years of Preliminary References on Environmental Matters Initiated by the Swedish Judiciary’, 29 Journal of Environmental Law (2017) p. 263 at p. 267-268; E.F. Mac-Gregor, ‘What Do We Mean When We Talk about Judicial Dialogue?: Reflections of a Judge of the Inter-American Court of Human Rights’, 30 Harvard Human Rights Journal (2017) p.89; and M. Belov (ed.), Judicial Dialogue (Eleven International Publishing 2019). See also the critique by B. De Witte, ‘The Closest Thing to a Constitutional Conversation in Europe: The Semi-permanent Treaty Revision Process’, in P. Beaumont et al. (eds.), Convergence and Divergence in European Public Law (Hart Publishing 2002).

2 See P. Popelier and C. Van De Heyning, ‘Constitutional Dialogue as an Expression of Trust and Distrust in Multilevel Governance’ in Belov, supra n. 1, p. 52.

3 B. Bricker et al., ‘Referrals’ in L. Epstein et al. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Comparative Judicial Behaviour (Oxford University Press forthcoming); see O. Pfersmann, ‘Concrete Review as Indirect Constitutional Complaint in French Constitutional Law: A Comparative Perspective’, 6 EuConst (2010) p. 223; O. Jouanjan, ‘Constitutional Justice in France’, The Max Planck Handbooks in European Public Law (Oxford University Press 2020) p. 223 at p. 259; and M. de Visser, Constitutional Review in Europe: A Comparative Analysis (Hart Publishing 2015) p. 132-135.

4 See K. Lenaerts et al. (eds.), EU Procedural Law (Oxford University Press 2014) Ch. 4. At the European level the relatively new advisory opinion mechanism established by the Protocol No. 16 to the ECHR should be mentioned.

5 Bricker, supra n. 3.

6 See e.g. M. Broberg and N. Fenger, Preliminary References to the European Court of Justice, 3rd edn. (Oxford University Press 2021); M. Bobek, ‘Learning to Talk: Preliminary Rulings, the Courts of the New Member States and the Court of Justice’, 45 CML Rev (2008) p. 1611; and A. Rosas, ‘The European Court of Justice in Context: Forms and Patterns of Judicial Dialogue’, 1 European Journal of Legal Studies (2007).

7 See e.g. A. Frese and H.P. Olsen, ‘Spelling It Out – Convergence and Divergence in the Judicial Dialogue between CJEU and ECtHR’, 88 Nordic Journal of International Law (2019) p. 429; P.W. Almeida, ‘The Asymmetric Judicial Dialogue between the ICJ and the IACtHR: An Empirical Analysis’, 11 Journal of International Dispute Settlement (2020) p. 1; and F.G. Jacobs, ‘Judicial Dialogue and the Cross-Fertilization of Legal Systems: The European Court of Justice’, 38 Texas International Law Journal (2003) p. 547.

8 See de Visser, supra n. 3.

9 See e.g. Pfersmann, supra n. 3; Jouanjan, supra n. 3; A. Cortes and T. Violante, ‘Concrete Control of Constitutionality in Portugal: A Means Towards Effective Protection of Fundamental Rights’, 29 Penn State International Law Review (2011) p. 759; J. Ferejohn and P. Pasquino, ‘Constitutional Adjudication, Italian Style’, in T. Ginsburg (ed.), Comparative Constitutional Design (Cambridge University Press 2012) p. 294; C. Pinelli, ‘Experience of the Constitutional Court of Italy’ online roundtable ‘Referral of cases to Constitutional Council by ordinary courts’ (Venice Commission 2021); W. Sadurski, Rights Before Courts: A Study of Constitutional Courts in Postcommunist States of Central and Eastern Europe, 2nd edn. (Springer Netherlands 2014); O. Pfersmann, ‘Le contrôle concret des normes législatives en Autriche’, in X. Philippe (ed.), Le contrôle de constitutionnalité par voie préjudicielle (PUAM 2009) p. 91; and K. Stern, ‘Das Bundesverfassungsgericht und die sog. konkrete Normenkontrolle nach Art. 100 Absatz 1 GG’, 91 Archiv des öffentlichen Rechts (1966) p. 223.

10 On this debate see e.g. L. Garlicki and M. Derlatka, ‘Constitutional Review in the Abusive Constitutionalism (Continuation, Corruption or Disappearance?)’ in M. Granat (ed.), Constitutionality of Law without a Constitutional Court (Routledge 2023); K. Šipulová, ‘Under Pressure: Building Judicial Resistance to Political Inference’ on The Courts and the People: Friend or Foe? The Putney Debates 2019 (Hart Publishing 2021), 154; M. Steuer, ‘The Role of Judicial Craft in Improving Democracy’s Resilience: The Case of Party Bans in Czechia, Hungary and Slovakia’, 18 EuConst (2022) p. 440; C.-Y. Matthes, ‘Judges as Activists: How Polish Judges Mobilise to Defend the Rule of Law’, 38 East European Politics (2022) p. 468; H. Smekal et al., ‘Through Selective Activism towards Greater Resilience: the Czech Constitutional Court’s Interventions into High Politics in the Age of Populism’, 32 The International Journal of Human Rights (2021) p. 1230; C. Reyns, ‘Saving Judicial Independence: A Threat to the Preliminary Ruling Mechanism?’, 17 EuConst (2021) p. 26.

11 D. Kosař and L. Vyhnánek, The Constitution of Czechia: A Contextual Analysis (Hart Publishing 2021) p. 7.

12 For more detail see D. Kosař and L. Vyhnánek, ‘The Constitutional Court of Czechia’, in A. von Bogdandy et al. (eds.), Constitutional Adjudication: Institutions (Oxford University Press 2020) p. 119 at p. 136-174; Z. Kühn, ‘The Constitutional Court of the Czech Republic’, in A. Jakab et al. (eds.), Comparative Constitutional Reasoning (Cambridge University Press 2017) p. 199 at p. 205; Z. Kühn, The Judiciary in Central and Eastern Europe: Mechanical Jurisprudence in Transformation? (Martinus Nijhoff 2011); and D. Kosař, Perils of Judicial Self-Government in Transitional Societies (Cambridge University Press 2016) p. 117.

13 See M. Leloup, ‘Who Safeguards the Guardians? A Subjective Right of Judges to their Independence under Article 6(1) ECHR’, 17 EuConst (2021) p. 394; and R.B. Gisbert, ‘Judicial Independence in European Constitutional Law’, 18 EuConst (2022) p. 591 at p. 594.

14 Jouanjan, supra n. 3, at p. 259; for a deeper comparative analysis, see also de Visser, supra n. 3, at p. 132-135.

15 Cf Pfersmann, supra n. 3, at p. 228.

16 Cf de Visser, supra n. 3, at p. 132.

17 Pfersmann, supra n. 3, at p. 235.

18 J. Ferejohn and P. Pasquino, ‘Constitutional Adjudication: Lessons from Europe’, 82 Texas Law Review (2004) p. 1671 at p. 1684; see E. Lamarque, ‘Direct Constitutional Complaint and Italian Style do not Match. Why is That?’, in V. Barsotti et al. (eds.), Dialogues on Italian Constitutional Justice: A Comparative Perspective (Routledge 2021).

19 Ferejohn and Pasquino., ibid., at p. 1682-1700.

20 Ibid., at p. 1690.

21 See e.g. Estonia, where constitutional review is essentially centralised in the Constitutional Review Chamber of the Supreme Court. Cf C. Ortiz, ‘Constitutional Review in the Member States of the EU-28: A Political Analysis of Institutional Choices’, 47 Journal of Law and Society (2020) at p. 102.

22 See A. Stone Sweet, Governing with Judges: Constitutional Politics in Europe (Oxford University Press 2000) p. 133; and T. Ginsburg, ‘The Global Spread of Constitutional Review’, in K.E. Whittington et al. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Law and Politics (Oxford University Press 2010) p. 81 at p. 85.

23 See V.A. da Silva, ‘Beyond Europe and the United States: the Wide World of Judicial Review’ in E.F. Delaney and R. Dixon (eds.), Comparative Judicial Review (Edward Elgar 2018) p. 318 at p. 318-319.

24 Cf de Visser, supra n. 3, p. 54-55; A. Stone-Sweet, ‘Constitutional Dialogues: Protecting Human Rights in France, Germany, Italy and Spain’, in S.J. Kenney et al. (eds.), Constitutional Dialogues in Comparative Perspective (Palgrave Macmillan 1999) p. 8 at p. 8-10; and C. Saunders, ‘Courts with Constitutional Jurisdiction’, in R. Masterman and R. Schütze (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Comparative Constitutional Law (Cambridge University Press 2019) p. 414 at p. 426.

25 See L. Garlicki, ‘Constitutional Courts Versus Supreme Courts’, 5 International Journal of Constitutional Law (2007) p. 44.

26 That is how I perceive ‘constitutional courts’ in this article. Cf Garlicki, supra n. 25; de Visser, supra n. 3, at p. 377; F.I. Michelman, ‘The Interplay of Constitutional and Ordinary Jurisdiction’, in T. Ginsburg and R. Dixon (eds.), Comparative Constitutional Law (Edward Elgar 2011) p. 278 at p. 278; and Kosař and Vyhnánek, supra n. 11, at p. 142.

27 Art. 100 of the Basic Law for Germany; Art. 193 of the Constitution of Poland; Art. 142 of the Constitution of Belgium and Art. 95(2) of the Constitution of Czechia.

28 Art. 150(2) of the Constitution of Bulgaria.

29 Michelman, supra n. 26, at p. 278.

30 See de Visser, supra n. 3, at p. 133.

31 In his recent book Pavone illuminates how lawyers cooperating with their clients profoundly impact on EU law. It is arguable whether these conclusions can be applied mutatis mutandis to constitutional referrals. See T. Pavone, The Ghostwriters (Cambridge University Press 2022).

32 Art. 61-1 of the Constitution of France.

33 Pfersmann, supra n. 3, at p. 232, 235.

34 Ibid.

35 Cf T. Ginsburg, Judicial Review in New Democracies (Cambridge University Press 2003) p. 38.

36 Cf K. Hesse, Grundzüge des Verfassungsrechts der Bundesrepublik Deutschland, 20th edn. (Müller 1999) p. 282; Pfersmann, supra n. 3, at p. 230; A.W. Heringa and P. Kiiver, Constitutions Compared: An Introduction to Comparative Constitutional Law (Intersentia 2012) p. 162; but cf G. Vanberg, The Politics of Constitutional Review in Germany (Cambridge University Press 2004) p. 87.

37 Sadurski, supra n. 9, at p. 92.

38 Ibid., at p. 91-92; cf de Visser, supra n. 3, at fn. 235.

39 Cf Sadurski, supra n. 9, p. 95.

40 See Art. 267 TFEU and also Lenaerts et al., supra n. 4, Ch. 4.

41 Art. 61-1 of the Constitution of France; Art. 1 of the Constitutional Law no 1/1948; and Art. 193 of the Constitution of Poland. See also Jouanjan, supra n. 3, at p. 264; and Pinelli, supra n. 9.

42 Jouanjan, supra n. 3, at p. 264.

43 Art. 100 of the Basic Law for Germany; and Art. 95(2) of the Constitution of Czechia; or Art. 144(3) of the Constitution of Slovakia. See also D.P. Kommers and R.A. Miller, The Constitutional Jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of Germany (Duke University Press Books 2012) p. 13; and Stern, supra n. 9.

44 Art. 100 of the Basic Law for Germany; Art. 142(3), Art. 142 of the Constitution of Belgium; Art. 95(2) of the Constitution of Czechia.

45 See Pfersmann, supra n. 3, at p. 230-231.

46 Art. 163 of the Constitution of Spain; Art. 61-1 of the Constitution of France. See also E. Guillen Lopez, ‘Judicial Review in Spain: The Constitutional Court’, 41 Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review (2007) p. 529; and Jouanjan, supra n. 3, at p. 264.

47 See de Visser, supra n. 3, at p. 139.

48 Ibid.

49 Art. 61(1) of the Constitution of France.

50 Jouanjan, supra n. 3, at p. 261.

51 See N.W. Barber, The Principles of Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press 2018) Ch. 3.

52 A. Kavanagh, The Collaborative Constitution (Cambridge University Press 2023).

53 Barber, supra n. 51, p. 55-56. See also J. Waldron, ‘Separation of Powers in Thought and Practice?’, 54 Boston College Law Review (2013) p. 433 at p. 466; and Kavanagh, supra n. 52, at p. 31-50.

54 Barber, supra n. 51, at p. 61; cf M.M. Shapiro, Courts: A Comparative and Political Analysis (University of Chicago Press 1986) Ch. 1.

55 Barber, supra n. 51, at p. 241; for more details see also N. Barber, The Constitutional State (Oxford University Press 2012) Ch. 2.

56 Cf C. Möllers, The Three Branches: A Comparative Model of Separation of Powers (Oxford University Press 2013) at p. 127.

57 See de Visser, supra n. 3, at p. 377.

58 See Kavanagh, supra n. 52, at p. 205.

59 See de Visser, supra n. 3, at p. 98. According to the author, the other two purposes of constitutional adjudications are: resolving institutional disputes among governmental organs; and ensuring the integrity of political office and related processes.

60 Cf, mutatis mutandis, G. Tridimas and T. Tridimas, ‘National Courts and the European Court of Justice: A Public Choice Analysis of the Preliminary Reference Procedure’, 24 International Review of Law and Economics (2004) p. 125 at p. 126.

61 A. Harel and A. Shinar, ‘The Real Case for Judicial Review’, in E.F. Delaney and R. Dixon (eds.), Comparative Judicial Review (Edward Elgar 2018) p. 15.

62 Cf Ginsburg, supra n. 35, at p. 38.

63 See Sadurski, supra n. 9, at p. 98; M. Shapiro, ‘Judicial Review in Developed Democracies’, 10 Democratization (2003) p. 7 at p. 19; and T. Ginsburg and M. Versteeg, ‘Why Do Countries Adopt Constitutional Review?’, 30 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization (2014) p. 587.

64 Cf Barber, supra n. 51, at p. 90.

65 D. Kosař et al., ‘The Twin Challenges to Separation of Powers in Central Europe: Technocratic Governance and Populism’, 15 EuConst (2019) p. 427 at p. 434; and N.W. Barber, ‘Self-defence for Institutions’, 72 Cambridge Law Journal (2013) p. 558 at p. 559-560.

66 J. Madison, ‘No. 51’, in A. Hamilton et al., The Federalist Papers (Penguin 1999) at p. 288-293.

67 See the case study infra.

68 Barber, supra n. 55, at p. 79.

69 Šipulová, supra n. 10, at p. 159.

70 See e.g. R. Dixon and D. Landau, Abusive Constitutional Borrowing (Oxford University Press 2021); and A. Sajó, Ruling by Cheating (Cambridge University Press 2021).

71 See Y. Roznai, ‘Who Will Save the Redheads? Towards an Anti-Bully Theory of Judicial Review and Protection of Democracy’, 29 William & Mary Bill of Rights Journal (2021) p. 327 at p. 341.

72 R. Dixon, Responsive Judicial Review, e-book (Oxford University Press 2023) at p. 176.

73 Ibid., at p. 91-101.

74 See de Visser, supra n. 3, at p. 99.

75 But see the case of Portugal, where individuals can appeal directly to the constitutional court against any diffuse review by ordinary courts: Cortes and Violante, supra n. 9.

76 Matthes, supra n. 10. See also the judgment of the ECtHR 23 June 2016, No. 20261/12, Baka v Hungary.

77 See W. Sadurski, Poland’s Constitutional Breakdown (Oxford University Press 2019) Ch. 3; P. Castillo-Ortiz, ‘The Illiberal Abuse of Constitutional Courts in Europe’, 15 EuConst (2019) p. 48; T. Drinóczi and A. Bień-Kacała, Illiberal Constitutionalism in Poland and Hungary (Routledge 2022).

78 See Roznai, supra n. 71, at p. 366.

79 Dixon, supra n. 72, at p. 117-119.

80 Cf Kosař and Vyhnánek, supra n. 11, at p. 163.

81 Cf Barber, supra n. 51, at p. 61; and Shapiro, supra n. 54, Ch. 1.

82 J. Petrov, ‘The COVID-19 Emergency in the Age of Executive Aggrandizement: What Role for Legislative and Judicial Checks?’, 8 The Theory and Practice of Legislation (2020) p. 71 at p. 80.

83 V. Ferreres Comella, Constitutional Courts and Democratic Values: a European Perspective (Yale University Press 2009) p. 36-37.

84 J. Raz, ‘The Rule of Law and its Virtue’ in J. Raz, The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality (Oxford University Press 1979) p. 210 at p. 214.

85 See the first section of this article, supra.

86 Ferreres Comella, supra n. 83, at p. 115.

87 Cf Sadurski, supra n. 9, at p. 67.

88 Sadurski, supra n. 9, at p. 35.

89 Cf Bogojević, supra n. 1, at p. 267-268; and Mac-Gregor, supra n. 1, at p. 40.

90 Rosas, supra n. 6, at p. 6; but cf A.-M. Slaughter, ‘A Typology of Transjudicial Communication’, 29 University of Richmond Law Review (1994) p. 99, where the author defines vertical dialogue only as a dialogue between national and transnational court.

91 See e.g. A. Meuwese and M. Snel, ‘“Constitutional Dialogue”: An Overview’, 9 Utrecht Law Review (2013) p. 123.

92 See de Visser, supra n. 3, at p. 329.

93 X. Groussot, ‘Constitutional Dialogues, Pluralism and Conflicting Identities’, in M. Avbelj and J. Komárek (eds.), Constitutional Pluralism in the European Union and Beyond (Hart Publishing 2012) p. 319 at p. 320.

94 Speaking only of the state power side. The role of parties cannot be overseen, though. See Pinelli, supra n. 9.

95 A. Stone-Sweet, ‘Constitutional Dialogues: Protecting Human Rights in France, Germany, Italy and Spain’, in S.J. Kenney et al. (eds.), Constitutional Dialogues in Comparative Perspective (Palgrave Macmillan 1999) p. 8 at p. 8.

96 R. Alexy, ‘Balancing, Constitutional Review, and Representation’, 3 International Journal of Constitutional Law (2005) p. 572 at p. 572; cf Groussot, supra n. 93, at p. 323.

97 A.M. Bickel, The Least Dangerous Branch, 2nd edn. (Yale University Press 1986) at p. 240.

98 See P. Pasquino, ‘The New Constitutional Adjudication in France. The Reform of the Referral to the French Constitutional Council in Light of the Italian Model’, 3 Indian Journal of Constitutional Law (2009) p. 105.

99 Ferreres Comella, supra n. 83, at p. 59.

100 See A. Dyevre, ‘The Melki Way: The Melki Case and Everything You Always Wanted to Know about French Politics (but Were Afraid to Ask)’, in M. Claes et al. (eds.), Constitutional Conversations in Europe: Actors, Topics and Procedures (Intersentia 2012) p. 309; and M. Bossuyt and W. Verrijdt, ‘The Full Effect of EU Law and of Constitutional Review in Belgium and France after the Melki Judgment’, 7 EuConst (2011) p. 355.

101 Cf e.g. Stone Sweet, supra n. 22, at p. 32-37.

102 Ferejohn and Pasquino, supra n. 18, at p. 1692.

103 C.H. Mendes, Constitutional Courts and Deliberative Democracy (Oxford University Press 2015); and M. Pivoda, ‘Constitutional Courts Asking Questions: A Deliberative Potential of Preliminary Reference Mechanism’, Cambridge Yearbook of European Legal Studies (2023) p. 1 at p. 14.

104 See R. Alexy, A Theory of Legal Argumentation (Clarendon Press 1989) at p. 17.

105 Cf J. Habermas, Between Facts and Norms (MIT Press 1996) at p. 103, 287.

106 Cf in the supranational context Mac-Gregor, supra n. 1, at p. 891; Almeida, supra n. 7; and Jacobs, supra n. 7.

107 P. Popelier, ‘Judicial Conversations in Multilevel Constitutionalism’, in Claes et al., supra n. 100, p. 73; cf A.T. Pérez, ‘Judicial Dialogue as the Source of Legitimacy of Supranational Adjudication’, in A. Torres Pérez (ed.), Conflicts of Rights in the European Union: A Theory of Supranational Adjudication (Oxford University Press 2009) at p. 122.

108 Claes et al., supra n. 100, p. 1.

109 Cf P.J. Yap, Constitutional Dialogue in Common Law Asia (Oxford University Press 2015) p. 27.

110 M. Tushnet, ‘Dialogic Judicial Review’, 61 Arkansas Law Review (2009) p. 205 at p. 212; K. Roach, ‘Dialogic Judicial Review and its Critics’, 23 Supreme Court Law Review (2004) p. 49 at p. 55.

111 J. Kratochvíl, ‘Subsidiarity of Human Rights in Practice: The Relationship between the Constitutional Court and Lower Courts in Czechia’, 37 Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights (2019) p. 69 at p. 72.

112 Z. Kühn, Aplikace práva soudcem v éře středoevropského komunismu a transformace (CH Beck 2005) p. 146.

113 Here, I do not distinguish between liberal and legal constitutionalism. See e.g. A. Sajó and R. Uitz, The Constitution of Freedom: An Introduction to Legal Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press 2017).

114 Groussot, supra n. 93, at p. 319. He cites P. Bourdieu, Language and Symbolic Power (Polity Press 1991).

115 Cf, mutatis mutandis, J. Krommendijk, National Courts and Preliminary References to the Court of Justice (Edward Elgar 2021) at p. 15; and Tridimas and Tridimas, supra n. 60, at p. 135.

116 Ferreres Comella, supra n. 83, at p. 115.

117 Thanks go to David Kosař for this observation.

118 Kosař and Vyhnánek, supra n. 11, at p. 7.

119 Smekal et al., supra n. 10, at p. 1230.

120 Kühn (2017), supra n. 12, at p. 205. For detail, see Z. Kühn, The Judiciary in Central and Eastern Europe: Mechanical Jurisprudence in Transformation? (Martinus Nijhoff 2011).

121 For details see Kosař and Vyhnánek, supra n. 11, at p. 158-159.

122 For details see J. Komárek, ‘Czech Constitutional Court Playing with Matches: the Czech Constitutional Court Declares a Judgment of the Court of Justice of the EU Ultra Vires; Judgment of 31 January 2012, Pl. ÚS 5/12, Slovak Pensions XVII’, 8 EuConst (2012) p. 323.

123 Section 64(2), (4) of the Act on the Constitutional Court.

124 It is stipulated similarly also in s 64(4) of the Act on the Constitutional Court.

125 Since I focus on the content of judicial opinions, I exclude rulings without any substantive argument. Therefore, the dataset encompasses only judgments on merits (nálezy), quasi-substantive decisions (usnesení) that dismiss a petition as manifestly ill-founded, and decisions that dismiss a petition because the court was not authorised to refer. For an explanation of procedure before the Czech Constitutional Court, see Kosař and Vyhnánek, supra n. 12, at p. 159.

126 Justices of the Czech Constitutional Court are appointed by the President of the Republic for 10 years (reappointment is not prohibited, but the new president, Petr Pavel, has declared that no one will be reappointed). All of the President’s nominees must be approved by a simple majority in the Senate (the upper house of Parliament).

127 For more details of the Czech Constitutional Court context, see Smekal et al., supra n. 10.

128 See Appendix and Yearbooks of the Czech Constitutional Court (ročenky Ústavního soudu) and the Annual Statistical Report 2022 (Roční statistická analýza), available at https://www.usoud.cz/rocenky, https://www.usoud.cz/fileadmin/user_upload/ustavni_soud_www/Statistika/Podrobne_grafy_a_statistiky_do_roku_2020.pdf, https://www.usoud.cz/fileadmin/user_upload/ustavni_soud_www/Rocenky/Ustavni_soud_Rocenka_2022_elektronicka.pdf, all visited 11 March 2024.

129 See the three-tiered approach in D. Kosař et al., Domestic Judicial Treatment of European Court of Human Rights Case Law: Beyond Compliance (Routledge 2020) p. 83-159.

130 Cf M. Bobek, Comparative Reasoning in European Supreme Courts (Oxford University Press 2013) at p. 190, 75, 84; Jakab et al., supra n. 12, p. 260 at p. 291.

131 Cf M. Matczak et al., ‘EU Law and Central European Judges: Administrative Judiciaries in the Czech Republic, Hungary and Poland Ten Years after the Accession’, in M. Bobek (ed.), Central European Judges Under the European Influence: The Transformative Power of the EU Revisited (Bloomsbury 2015) at p. 61; and M. Bobek et al., Judikatura a právní argumentace (Auditorium 2013) at p. 443, 459-460.

132 By this I mean a subjective case selection based on the perception of the author and interpretative reading of the judicial opinion. See R. Hirschl, ‘Comparative Methodologies’, in Masterman and Schütze, supra n. 24, p. 11 at p. 22; B. De Witte, ‘Legal Methods for the Study of EU Institutional Practice’, 18 EuConst (2022) p. 637; and M.A. Hall and R.F. Wright, ‘Systematic Content Analysis of Judicial Opinions’, 96 California Law Review (2008) p. 63 at p. 100.

133 Hall and Wright, supra n. 132, at p. 66.

134 See R. Spano, ‘The European Court of Human Rights and National Courts: A Constructive Conversation or a Dialogue of Disrespect?’, 33 Nordic Journal of Human Rights (2015) p. 1 at p. 1.

135 See e.g. judgments of the Czech Constitutional Court of 19 July 2022, Pl. ÚS 12/19; of 16 May 2018, Pl. ÚS 15/16; or 7 October 2014, Pl. ÚS 39/14.

136 See the second section supra on functions of constitutional referrals, and also, mutatis mutandis, Tridimas and Tridimas, supra n. 60, at p. 126.

137 See Alexy, supra n. 104, p. 17.

138 The Code of Administrative Justice, no 150/2002 Coll.

139 Judgment of the Czech Constitutional Court of 14 July 2022, Pl. ÚS 25/19.

140 See ibid., especially §§ 38–47.

141 Ibid., § 39.

142 Ibid., § 47.

143 Act No. 6/2002 Coll. on Courts and Judges.

144 Judgment of the Czech Constitutional Court of 24 May 2022, Pl. ÚS 32/21.

145 See s. 80 of the of Code of Civil Justice, no. 99/1963 Coll.

146 Judgment of the Czech Constitutional Court of 24 May 2022, Pl. ÚS 32/21, § 16.

147 Ibid., §§ 18-19.

148 Ibid., the joint dissenting opinion of Justices Šimíček, Jirsa, Šámal, Uhlíř, and Zemánek.

149 Ibid.

150 Claes et al., supra n. 100, p. 3.

151 Groussot, supra n. 93.

152 See J. Komárek and M. Avbelj, ‘Introduction’, in Avbelj and Komárek, supra n. 93, at p. 2; and N. Walker, ‘The Idea of Constitutional Pluralism’, 65 The Modern Law Review (2002) p. 317.

153 See supra n. 128.

154 Ferreres Comella, supra n. 83, at p. 115.

155 See the second section supra.

156 In the European context see Leloup, supra n. 13.

157 Judgment of the Czech Constitutional Court of 10 July 2014, Pl. ÚS 28/13. This is the 15th judgment of the Czech Constitutional Court in total on judicial salaries. The first one was issued on 15 September 1999, Pl. ÚS 13/99.

158 See Kosař and Vyhnánek, supra n. 11, at p. 163.

159 M. Bobek, ‘The Fortress of Judicial Independence and the Mental Transitions of the Central European Judiciaries’, 14 European Public Law (2008) p. 99 at p. 111. See, primarily, the judgment of the Czech Constitutional Court of 16 January 2007, Pl. ÚS 55/05.

160 Kosař and Vyhnánek, supra n. 11, at p. 163.

161 Judgment of the Czech Constitutional Court of 10 July 2014, Pl. ÚS 28/13, §§ 55-98.

162 Cf Barber, supra n. 51, at p. 162; and Shapiro, supra n. 54, Ch. 1.

163 See Barber, supra n. 55, at p. 79 and also the second section of this article, supra.

164 See e.g. J.-W. Müller, ‘Populism and Constitutionalism’, in C.R. Kaltwasser et al. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Populism (Oxford University Press 2018).

165 See e.g. D. Landau, ‘Abusive Constitutionalism’, 47 UC Davis Law Review (2013) p. 189; and Garlicki and Derlatka, supra n. 10.

166 Cf Kosař and Vyhnánek, supra n. 11, at p. 163.

167 See Sadurski, supra n. 77, Ch. 3; Castillo-Ortiz, supra n. 77; and Drinóczi and Bień-Kacała, supra n. 77.

168 Matthes, supra n. 10.

169 See M. Kovalčík, ‘The Instrumental Abuse of Constitutional Courts: How Populists Can Use Constitutional Courts against the Opposition’, 26 The International Journal of Human Rights (2022) p. 1160 at p. 1170; and M. Wyrzykowski and M. Ziółkowski, ‘Illiberal Constitutionalism and the Judiciary’, in A. Sajó et al., Routledge Handbook of Illiberalism (Routledge 2021) p. 579.

170 See M. Bencze, ‘Judicial Populism and the Weberian Judge – The Strength of Judicial Resistance Against Governmental Influence in Hungary’, 22 German Law Journal (2021) p. 1282 at p. 1293.

171 Claes et al., supra n. 100, p. 1.

172 Popelier, supra n. 107, at p. 72; cf Pérez, supra n. 107, at p. 122.

173 W. Sadurski, A Pandemic of Populists (Cambridge University Press 2022).

174 Castillo-Ortiz, supra n. 77, at p. 68.

175 See the section above on negative functions, and also Šipulová, supra n. 10; and Barber, supra n. 55, at p. 79.

176 Kosař and Vyhnánek, supra n. 11, at p. 7.

177 See e.g. Dixon and Landau, supra n. 70; Šipulová, supra n. 10, at p. 159; and Sajó, supra n. 70.

178 See Sadurski, supra n. 77, Ch. 3; Castillo-Ortiz, supra n. 77; Drinóczi and Bień-Kacała, supra n. 77.

179 Matthes, supra n. 10.

180 See Bencze, supra n. 170, at p. 1293.

Supplementary material: File

Kovalčík supplementary material 1

Kovalčík supplementary material
Download Kovalčík supplementary material 1(File)
File 24.4 KB
Supplementary material: File

Kovalčík supplementary material 2

Kovalčík supplementary material
Download Kovalčík supplementary material 2(File)
File 106.4 KB