Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-pjpqr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-14T20:11:58.640Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Empirical Character of Methodological Rules

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Warren Schmaus*
Affiliation:
Illinois Institute of Technology

Abstract

Critics of Laudan's normative naturalism have questioned whether methodological rules can be regarded as empirical hypotheses about relations between means and ends. Drawing on Laudan's defense that rules of method are contingent on assumptions about the world, I argue that even if such rules can be shown to be analytic in principle (Kaiser 1991), in practice the warrant for such rules will be empirical. Laudan's naturalism, however, acquires normative force only by construing both methods and epistemic goals as instrumental to practical concerns, and issues only in context-specific and not general methodological principles.

Type
Methodology Naturalized and Contextualized
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1996

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I wish to thank Michael Davis, Rachana Kamtekar, Robert Ladenson, George Reisch, Jack Snapper, and Vivian Weil for their helpful comments.

Department of Humanities, Illinois Institute of Technology, Chicago, IL 60616.

References

Donovan, A., Laudan, L., and Laudan., R. (eds.), (1988), Scrutinizing Science: Empirical Studies of Scientific Change. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doppelt, G. (1986), “Relativism and the Reticulational Model of Scientific Rationality”, Synthese 69: 225252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doppelt, G. (1990), “The Naturalist Conception of Methodological Standards in Science: A Critique”, Philosophy of Science 57: 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaiser, M. (1991), “Progress and Rationality: Laudan's Attempt to Divorce a Happy Couple”, Inquiry 34: 433455.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaiser, M. (1993), “Discussion: Philosophers Adrift? Comments on the Alleged Disunity of Method”, Philosophy of Science 60: 500512.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1977), Progress and Its Problems. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1984), Science and Values. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1986), “Some Problems Facing Intuitionist Meta-Methodologies”, Synthese 67: 115129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1987a), “Progress or Rationality? The Prospects for a Normative Naturalism”, American Philosophical Quarterly 24: 1931.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1987b), “Methodology's Prospects”, in Fine, A. and Machamer, P. (eds.), PSA 1986: Proceedings of the 1986 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 2. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 347354.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1987c), “Relativism, Naturalism and Reticulation”, Synthese 71: 221234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1989), “If It Ain't Broke, Don't Fix It”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40: 369375.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1990a), Science and Relativism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1990b). “Normative Naturalism”, Philosophy of Science 57: 4459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1990c), “Aim-less Epistemology?Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 21: 315322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1990d), “Demystifying Underdetermination”, in Savage, C. Wade (ed). Scientific Theories. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 267297.Google Scholar
Laudan, L., Donovan, A., Laudan, R., Barker, P., Brown, H., Leplin, J., Thagard, P., and Wykstra, S. (1986), “Scientific Change: Philosophical Models and Historical Research”, Synthese 69: 141223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, R., and Laudan, L. (1989), “Dominance and the Disunity of Method: Solving the Problems of Innovation and Consensus”, Philosophy of Science 56: 221237.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L., and Leplin, J. (1991), “Empirical Equivalence and Underdetermination”, Journal of Philosophy 88: 449472.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, H. (1990), Science as Social Knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, T. (1986), “Remarks on the Use of History as Evidence”, Synthese 69: 253266.Google Scholar
Quinn, P. L. (1987), “Comments on Laudan's ‘Methodology: Its Prospects’ ”, in Fine, A. and Machamer, P. (eds.), PSA 1986: Proceedings of the 1986 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 2. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 355358.Google Scholar
Resnick, D. B. (1992), “Discussion: Are Methodological Rules Hypothetical Imperatives?Philosophy of Science 59: 498507.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A. (1990). “Normative Naturalism and the Role of Philosophy”, Philosophy of Science 57: 3443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stump, D. (1991), “Fallibilism, Naturalism and the Traditional Requirements for Knowledge”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 22: 451469.CrossRefGoogle Scholar