Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wg55d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-02T13:14:16.380Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism: The “Theory-Informity” of Observation and the Quine-Duhem Thesis

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

John D. Greenwood*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, City College, City University of New York

Abstract

It is argued that neither the “theory-informity” of observations nor the Quine-Duhem thesis pose any in principle threat to the objectivity of theory evaluation. The employment of exploratory theories does not generate incommensurability, but on the contrary is responsible for the mensurability and commensurability of explanatory theories, since exploratory theories enable scientists to make observations which are critical in the evaluation of explanatory theories. The employment of exploratory theories and other auxiliary hypotheses does not enable a theory to always accommodate recalcitrant observations to preserve evidential equivalence with a rival theory. Explanatory theories become rapidly degenerating if exploratory theories or other auxiliary hypotheses which inform the original confirmation base are modified to accommodate recalcitrant observations.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1990 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

My thanks to Jarrett Leplin, Cecilia Wee and two anonymous reviewers for their critical comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

References

Berlin, B. and Kay, P. (1969), Basic Color Terms: Their Universality and Evolution. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Brown, H. I. (1977), Perception, Theory and Commitment: The New Philosophy of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1939), “Foundations of Logic and Mathematics”, in O. Neurath, R. Carnap and C. Morris (eds.), International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, Vol. I, part I. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1966), Philosophical Foundations of Physics, ed. by Gardner, M. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. (1979), Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511625435CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, H. H., and Clark, E. V. (1977), Psychology and Language. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.Google Scholar
Duhem, P. (1906), La Theorie Physique: Son Objet et sa Structure. Paris.Google Scholar
Enc, B. (1976), “Spiral Dependence Between Theories and Taxonomy”, Inquiry 19: 4171.10.1080/00201747608601786CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feigl, H. (1970), “Beyond Peaceful Coexistence”, in R. H. Stuewer (ed.), Historical and Philosophical Perspectives on Science. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 5. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Feigl, H. (1974), “Empiricism at Bay?” in R. Cohen and M. Wartofsky (eds.), Methodological and Historical Essays in the Natural and Social Sciences. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 14. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. (1975), Against Method. London: New Left Books.Google Scholar
Gibson, J. J. (1979), The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton-Mifflin.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (1983), Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511814563CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanson, N. R. (1958), Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge Univeristy Press.Google Scholar
Harré, R. (1981), Great Scientific Experiments. Oxford: Phaidon.Google Scholar
Heft, H. (1980), “What Heil is Missing in Gibson: A Reply”, Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior 10: 187193.10.1111/j.1468-5914.1980.tb00015.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, J. (1979), “What Gibson's Missing”, Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior 9: 265269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C. G. (1952), “Fundamentals of Concept Formation in Empirical Science,” in International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, Vol. II, no. 7. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. (1965), Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. and Oppenheim, P. (1948), “Studies in the Logic of Explanation”, Philosophy of Science 15: 135175.10.1086/286983CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hesse, M. (1974), The Structure of Scientific Inference. London: Macmillan.10.1525/9780520313316CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klotz, I. M. (1980), “The N-Ray Affair”, Scientific American 242: 122131.10.1038/scientificamerican0580-168CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koertge, N. (1972), “For and Against Method”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23: 274290.10.1093/bjps/23.3.274CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. (1970), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1970), “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes”, in I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, J. (1984), “Truth and Scientific Progress”, in J. Leplin (ed.) Scientific Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press.10.1525/9780520337442CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, E. (1961), The Structure of Science. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.10.1119/1.1937571CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polanyi, M. (1958), Personal Knowledge. London: Routledge and Kegal Paul.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1959), The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutcheson.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1963), Conjectures and Refutations. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1981), Reason, Truth and History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1953), “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”, in his From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. and Ullian, J. S. (1970), The Web of Belief. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Reed, E. S., and Jones, R. K. (1981), “Is Perception Blind?: A Reply to Heil”, Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior 2: 8791.10.1111/j.1468-5914.1981.tb00024.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosch, E. (1974), “Linguistic Relativity”, in A. Silverston (ed.), Human Communication: Theoretical Perspectives. New York: Halstead Press.Google Scholar
Shapere, D. (1982), “The Concept of Observation in Science and Philosophy”, Philosophy of Science 49: 485525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slobin, D. I. (1971), Psycholinguistics. Glenview, Ill.: Scott, Froesman.Google Scholar
Watson, J. D. (1978), The Double Helix: A Personal Account of the Discovery of the Structure of DNA. New York: Penguin.Google Scholar
Weinberg, S. (1977), The First Three Minutes: A Modern View of the Origin of the Universe. London: Andre Deutsch.Google Scholar
Whorf, B. L. (1956), “Science and Linguistics”, in J. B. Carroll (ed.), Language, Thought and Reality: The Selected Writings of Benjamin Lee Whorf. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1953), Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar