Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-4rdrl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-17T06:35:34.513Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

(Un)Seeing Augustus: Libertas, Divinisation, and the Iuvenis of Virgil's First Eclogue

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 August 2021

Bobby Xinyue*
Affiliation:
King's College London
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article argues that Virgil's First Eclogue naturalises the power discourse of the future Augustan Principate. Throughout the poem, Virgil not only presents the iuvenis as a libertas-restoring benefactor who is treated as a god by his beneficiaries, but even imagines his elevated status as crucial to maintaining social cohesion and civic stability, and idealises the beneficiaries’ dependence on his efficacious authority. The poem thus produces the grammar of the discourse of authoritarianism, subtly articulating what will eventually become the central tenets of Augustan ideology. I suggest that it is precisely this process of naturalisation which has led readers since antiquity to identify the iuvenis of Virgil's First Eclogue as the future Augustus. However, in this paper I am interested in transcending this question of individual identification to focus instead on how Virgil's poetic anonymisation is no simple pastoral obfuscation, but rather does the hard graft of ‘soft launching’ a new political system.

Type
Articles
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Society for the Promotion of Roman Studies

When Virgil published his First Eclogue in 35 b.c.,Footnote 1 in which a young man (iuvenis, 1.42) is deified for having restored freedom (libertas, 1.27) to Tityrus and released him from enslavement (servitio, 1.40), the poet could not have foreseen that some fifty years later Augustus, on the verge of divinisation, would open his Res gestae with the sentence:

annos undeviginti natus exercitum privato consilio et privata impensa comparavi, per quem rem publicam a dominatione factionis oppressam in libertatem vindicavi.

Aged nineteen years old I mustered an army at my personal decision and at my personal expense, and with it I liberated the state, which had been oppressed by a despotic faction.

It is striking that in both texts the liberation from slavery is tied up to the intervention of a single individual as liberator. While there is no compelling reason to think that Augustus had in mind Virgil's poem when he looked back on the achievements of his life,Footnote 2 the correspondence between the opening of the Res gestae and the First Eclogue underlines how the official history of a regime can cast a retroactive pall over earlier literary representationsFootnote 3 and, conversely, how poetry can express what would eventually become the central tenet of a master narrative.

Taking this bi-directional interaction as its cue, this paper argues that the frequent identification of Virgil's iuvenis with the future Augustus has much to do with the poem's naturalisation of the power discourse of the Augustan Principate. This naturalising process is most discernible in the poem's conceptualisation of libertas and its idealisation of the figure of the benefactor. Virgil's poem not only frames libertas as a kind of peaceful ease mediated exclusively by the intervention of a powerful iuvenis, but even implies that this benefactor's elevated status and the community's dedication to him are crucial to maintaining civic harmony. In this way, the pastoral drama centred around Tityrus’ worship of his benefactor creates a discourse whereby libertas and dependence on extraordinary power — or to put it another way, freedom and subjection — are notionally compatible,Footnote 4 thereby foreshadowing the defining ideological character of the Augustan Principate.

My argument falls into three parts. In Part I, I will show that the First Eclogue from its outset attempts to associate the benefactor's power with pastoral stability, and that, as the poem proceeds, otium is conflated with libertas. In Part II, I shall consider these aspects of Virgil's poem in connection with the discourse of libertas and the politics of divine self-representation in the triumviral period. It will be argued that the poem's conflation of otium and libertas serves to disembed libertas from its contemporary political context, reframing it evasively as a condition which only an extraordinary benefactor can guarantee, thus sanctifying the concentration of power in one man's hands. This reading will be expanded upon in Part III, where I tackle head-on the question of who the iuvenis is. Here I will suggest that Virgil does not so much invite the reader to identify the deified iuvenis with Octavian (or anyone else, for that matter)Footnote 5 as create an image of a political system with a single powerful ‘liberator’ at its centre — an image that comes remarkably close to the Augustan Principate. It is this prefigurative instantiation of the Augustan regime that has played a large part in persuading readers to see the iuvenis as Octavian. In closing (Part IV), I will contextualise my reading of the poem more broadly within the Eclogues.

In focusing on the issue of libertas and its connection to Octavian's image in the late 40s and early 30s b.c., my work builds on a large body of scholarship that has argued compellingly that the poetry of the triumviral period was particularly alive to the political struggle for libertas. The studies of Du Quesnay, Kennedy and Henderson, among others, have shown that in Satires Book 1 (a near-contemporary of the Eclogues), Horace repeatedly sought to suggest that Maecenas and Octavian — and not the defeated enemy of Octavian — were the true protectors of libertas.Footnote 6 In the case of Virgil's First Eclogue, critics have long thought that Tityrus’ attainment of libertas indirectly casts a positive light on Octavian. For example, Clausen has argued that the poem ‘deliberately confuses the private with the public sense of libertas’ in order to produce a coded praise of Octavian.Footnote 7 In a similar vein, but more teleological in his presentation, Galinsky has suggested that the Virgilian notion of libertas as ‘freedom from interference and oppression’ was precisely the concept of liberty that was later operative under Augustus.Footnote 8

The present study takes the position that something more — and far more insidious — is at play in the First Eclogue. In an illuminating study of the poetic language of patronage, Bowditch has argued that, by assimilating the social discourse of benefaction to the conventions of bucolic voluntarism, Virgil's Eclogues naturalise the triumviral political structure in which power lies in the hands of the oligarchic few.Footnote 9 In this paper, I take a similarly suspicious view of the First Eclogue's apparently sanguine attempt at fostering a connection between the unnamed benefactor and libertas.Footnote 10 Whereas Bowditch's study ultimately finds that the First Eclogue reproduces and reinforces the framework of the triumvirate, this paper argues that the poem's portrayal of the relationship between Tityrus and the iuvenis implicitly endorses the idea that libertas cannot be achieved without accepting a new system of power. Furthermore, I wish to make the case that the anonymity of the iuvenis should not be treated as a riddle to which Octavian is the answer.Footnote 11 Rather, this act of pastoral obfuscation does the hard graft of subtly laying out a new political ideology.

I BENEFACTION, OTIUM AND LIBERTAS

Both the volatility of the triumviral period and the disruption to rural life caused by Octavian's settlement of veterans after Philippi (Suet., Aug. 13) can be detected in the opening exchange of the First Eclogue.Footnote 12 Meliboeus’ song (1.1–5), which discloses that he is about to face exile (1.3–4) while his companion Tityrus somehow manages to hold on to pastoral security (1.1–2, 4–5), already hints at the idea that the shepherds themselves are not in control of their lives.Footnote 13 Tityrus’ reply, while confirming that he is indeed more fortunate, highlights further the shepherds’ lack of agency (1.6–10):

T: O Meliboee, deus nobis haec otia fecit.
namque erit ille mihi semper deus, illius aram
saepe tener nostris ab ovilibus imbuet agnus.
ille meas errare boves, ut cernis, et ipsum
ludere quae vellem calamo permisit agresti.
Tityrus: O Meliboeus, it is a god who gave us this peace — for a god he shall ever be to me; often shall a tender lamb from our folds stain his altar. He allowed my oxen to roam, as you see, and I myself to play what I wish on my rustic pipe.

The verbs fecit (1.6) and permisit (1.10) make clear that the pleasures of pastoral life, namely singing and herding (1.1–2, 4–5, 9–10), which Tityrus generalises as otia (1.6), are possible only because a ‘god’ had granted them.Footnote 14 The shepherd himself had no hand in procuring his present condition. Since Tityrus’ explanation rests firmly on his conviction that this good fortune has been mediated exclusively through divine agency, it follows that he implicitly recognises its inherently contingent nature.Footnote 15 By expressing his gratitude in this way, Tityrus’ words underscore the extent to which the livelihood of these shepherds is dependent on the whim of a single benefactor.

What also stands out from this opening exchange is the way Tityrus engages with Meliboeus’ language of contrasting experience (cf. tu and nos, 1.1–4), appropriating it to insinuate that his benefactor can transform not only his own fortune but the lives of many. In his response to Meliboeus, Tityrus quickly asserts that he is one of a number of shepherds who have benefitted from the god (nobis, 1.6), even though the shift from nobis to mihi in the next line (1.7) indicates that the decision to treat this benefactor as a god is Tityrus’ own.Footnote 16 In the next two lines, Tityrus repeats the same trick: ‘nostris … ovilibus’ (1.8) creates the impression that a community of shepherds is making sacrifice to this provider of otium, but ‘meas … boves’ (1.9) makes one wonder who else other than Tityrus has seen such a good turn of fortune. Thus in his response to Meliboeus’ suggestion that the shepherds are suddenly divided into those who have and those who have not, Tityrus repeatedly tries to pass his individual blessing off as a shared positive experience, thereby countering any claim that this benefactor could have sown division in the pastoral community. Combined with his usage of the time-defying adverbs semper (1.7) and saepe (1.8), Tityrus conjures up an idealised image of a patron–beneficiary relation, whereby an act of benefaction will restore long-lasting peace and common satisfaction. For Tityrus, the honouring of his benefactor as a divinity is no mere personal expression of gratitude, but a unifying societal ritual.

Perplexed by Tityrus’ good fortune, Meliboeus then asks him about his ‘god’ (‘sed tamen iste deus qui sit, da, Tityre, nobis’, ‘But still, tell me, Tityrus, who is that god?’, 1.18). At first, Tityrus avoids answering the question by telling Meliboeus that he went to Rome (1.19–20).Footnote 17 However, when Meliboeus presses him on why he had visited the city, Tityrus finally offers a proper reply, but still keeps the nature of his deus elusive (1.26–35):

M: Et quae tanta fuit Romam tibi causa videndi?
T: Libertas, quae sera tamen respexit inertem,
candidior postquam tondenti barba cadebat,
respexit tamen et longo post tempore venit,
30  postquam nos Amaryllis habet, Galatea reliquit.
namque (fatebor enim) dum me Galatea tenebat,
nec spes libertatis erat nec cura peculi.
quamvis multa meis exiret victima saeptis,
pinguis et ingratae premeretur caseus urbi,
35  non umquam gravis aere domum mihi dextra redibat.
Meliboeus: And what was the great occasion of your seeing Rome?
Tityrus: Freedom, who, though late, yet cast her eyes upon me in my sloth, when my beard began to whiten as it fell beneath the scissors. Yet she did cast her eyes on me, and came after a long time — after Amaryllis began her sway and Galatea left me. For — yes, I must confess — while Galatea ruled me, I had neither hope of freedom nor thought of savings. Though many a victim left my stalls, and many a rich cheese was pressed for the thankless city, never would my hand come home money-laden.

It appears that Tityrus went to Rome in order to free himself from the psychological and emotional captivity caused by his amatory encounters (1.30–2), as well as to procure some kind of alleviation from unrewarding labour (1.33–5). The terms libertas (1.27; spes libertatis, 1.32) and cura peculi (1.32), both set within the context of economic exchange and poverty (1.33–5), have generally encouraged scholars to view Tityrus as a literal slave and interpret his quest for ‘freedom’ as manumission.Footnote 18 At the same time, since amatory themes are frequent in Theocritus’ Idylls and here Virgil's shepherd is recounting his love life, the language of entrapment in Tityrus’ speech (‘me Galatea tenebat’, 1.31) may suggest that his slavery is also to some extent metaphorical, and that libertas for him is not just manumission, but also the freedom from servitium amoris (specifically from Galatea).Footnote 19 The ambiguity of libertas cannot be solved by the poem's opening image of Tityrus’ pastoral security either. There, he may be construed as both a freedman who has managed to retain his possessions and a lover who is untroubled by his amatory life (cf. ‘formosam resonare doces Amaryllida silvas’, ‘you teach the woods to resound “fair Amaryllis”’, 1.5). In fact, Tityrus’ earlier designation of these delights in his life as otia (1.6) blurs the distinction between economic and political stability and the contented ease of an individual, thereby conflating ‘freedom’ with ‘pleasure’. Libertas understood as manumission or the status of non-subjection implies the attainment or reassertion of agency, control and self-governing authority. However, by conflating libertas with the return of pleasant pastoral life, the term is stripped of its acute political meaning and anti-authoritarian resonance. Instead, as we approach the midpoint of Virgil's poem and with the presence of the benefactor looming, libertas appears to be framed as something akin to an untroubled life, but which can only be mediated through external intervention.

II DIVINE SELF-IMAGING AND LIBERTAS IN THE TRIUMVIRAL PERIOD

This evasive re-conceptualisation of libertas, set against the backdrop of Tityrus’ idealisation of his benefactor as a ‘god’, brings to mind the use of divine impersonation and the fluid meaning of libertas during the triumviral period. Recent scholarship on the cultivation of divine associations by prominent figures of the late Republic — commonly referred to as ‘divine imaging’ — has drawn attention to how this practice constituted and shaped the political discourse of that time.Footnote 20 As Cucchiarelli puts it succinctly, ‘the confrontation between the various political leaders took shape in part as a confrontation between different models of divinity’.Footnote 21 In fact, all the evidence we have of divine self-imaging in this period points to it being used as a way of articulating political scenarios — tensions, rivalries, allegiances — in suggestive and animated terms. For example, Octavian's self-presentation as the Divi filius was a way for him to stake his claim to Caesar's legacy and announce his arrival as a genuine political force.Footnote 22 The mutual distrust between Octavian and Antony in the early years of the triumvirate was reflected in the infamous story of Octavian masquerading as Apollo at an ‘Olympian’ banquet (Suet., Aug. 70) — an event that was probably exaggerated (or invented) and circulated by Antony's faction.Footnote 23 By the mid-30s, divine impersonation as political discourse appears to have gathered pace. Soon after Sextus Pompey's defeat at Naulochus in 36 b.c., Octavian and Antony separately adopted Sextus’ Neptunian designs on their own numismatic issues as a means of asserting their maritime supremacy.Footnote 24 The appropriative and dialogic character of their practice strongly indicates that divine self-representation was no mere ‘role play’. Rather, the image of a ‘god-man’ captures how different factions of the triumviral period competed for legitimacy and sought to identify themselves with useful political values.

Chief among these contested political values was libertas. While ‘liberty’ for Romans could be broadly defined as a condition of non-domination,Footnote 25 in the late Republic libertas became an extremely polysemous notion that ‘meant different things to different people’ as various political factions competed to be associated with it.Footnote 26 Following the assassination of Julius Caesar, Brutus and Cassius naturally identified themselves as the liberatores, thus giving the term libertas an anti-Caesarian dimension. But after their defeat at Philippi, Octavian and Antony each claimed to be protecting the libertas of the state.Footnote 27 Later, when the relationship between these two men broke down, the new Caesar, as we saw above (cf. R.G. 1), asserted that he protected libertas by keeping Antony — the unnamed factio in the opening of the Res gestae — away from Rome. The Dionysiac identity cultivated by Antony in the Greek East was weaponised against him by Octavian, who portrayed his rival as a morally bankrupt, disorderly and foreign force that threatened Roman libertas.Footnote 28

With this in mind, let us turn our focus back to the depiction of benefactor-worship and libertas in Virgil's First Eclogue. Set against a contemporary political climate where the meaning and ownership of libertas were fluid and constantly appropriated, the poem's dissociation of libertas from its immediate Roman context is no accident. I would suggest that Tityrus’ evasive aestheticisation of his ‘liberty’, along with the shepherd's enthusiastic worship of his iuvenis, translate the factional political competition for libertas into a quest to find the benefactor who could bring about a better way of life. In doing so, the First Eclogue creates a new discourse of libertas that not only presumes the subject's lack of agency, but even idealises external intervention as salvific power.

III WHO (OR WHAT) IS THE IUVENIS?

This particular discourse of libertas is exactly what we find when Tityrus finally reveals how he met his benefactor (1.40–5):

40  T: Quid facerem? neque servitio me exire licebat
nec tam praesentis alibi cognoscere divos.
hic illum vidi iuvenem, Meliboee, quotannis
bis senos cui nostra dies altaria fumant.
hic mihi responsum primus dedit ille petenti:
45   ‘pascite ut ante boves, pueri; summittite tauros.’
Tityrus: What was I to do? I could not quit slavery nor elsewhere find gods so ready to aid. Here, Meliboeus, I saw that youth for whom our altars smoke twelve times a year. Here he was the first to give my plea an answer: ‘Feed your oxen as before, boys; rear your bulls’.

In this account, Tityrus emphasises again his inability to take action for himself through the impersonal construction ‘me … licebat’ (1.40).Footnote 29 His instinct, as the next verse shows, is to find help from greater authorities (divos, 1.41).Footnote 30 However, the most remarkable aspect of this report is that, instead of elucidating what happened during his encounter with the iuvenis, Tityrus rather obfuscates what his benefactor actually did. While it is clear that Tityrus’ condition has been transformed from a state of servitium to libertas, the quoted injunction of the iuvenis (1.45) suggests not so much a liberation, but rather a restoration (ut ante, ‘as before’, 1.45). To be sure, the attainment of new liberty and the return to pastoral vocation are not necessarily mutually exclusive; but Tityrus ostensibly conflates libertas with otium again, or at least fails to make any meaningful distinction between the two. For this grateful devotee of the iuvenis, freedom, peace, and pleasure mean much the same thing.

Even though both the identity of the iuvenis and the precise nature of his intervention are concealed by Virgil's poem, critics have not stopped trying to ascertain who the iuvenis is.Footnote 31 As mentioned above, ancient commentators and modern scholars have frequently suggested Octavian as the candidate, since he carried out the land confiscations and claimed the title Divi filius during this period. Moreover, given that he was the only triumvir in Rome at the time of the Eclogues’ composition (whereas Antony was in the east and Lepidus was exiled to Circeii after the battle of Naulochus), and Virgil's poem underscores Rome as the site of the perceived divine intervention (cf. hic, 1.42 and 44), Octavian's presence in the city makes him even more likely to be the historical person behind Virgil's iuvenis.Footnote 32 Indeed, the depiction of Octavian as a salvific, divine young man has a precedent in Cicero's Fifth Philippic (delivered on 1 January 43 b.c.). The orator paints a bleak image of life starved of hope and freedom under Antony (‘nondum ullos duces habebamus, non copias; nullum erat consilium publicum, nulla libertas’, ‘we did not yet have any leaders, nor forces; there was no public council, no freedom’, Phil. 5.42), and he welcomes the arrival of Octavian (5.43):

quis tum nobis, quis populo Romano obtulit hunc divinum adulescentem deus? qui, cum omnia ad perniciem nostram pestifero illi civi paterent, subito praeter spem omnium exortus prius confecit exercitum quem furori M. Antoni opponeret quam quisquam hoc eum cogitare suspicaretur.

What god then presented to us and to the Roman people this godlike young man? When every road to our destruction lay open to that baneful citizen, suddenly, to the surprise of all, he arose: he got together an army to oppose Marcus Antonius’ madness before anyone suspected him of such a thought.

Cicero's young Octavian is a divinus liberator, whose appearance is sudden, whose help unexpected and whose action emphatically effective.Footnote 33 This depiction of the Divi filius is similar to that of the iuvenis in the First Eclogue. Tityrus’ suggestion that the Roman youth was more praesens (1.41) than divinities from elsewhere,Footnote 34 and the shepherd's claim that he had ‘seen’ (vidi, 1.42) his saviour,Footnote 35 whose oracular injunction (responsum, 1.44) he could vividly report,Footnote 36 combine to create the impression that Tityrus’ encounter with the iuvenis was surprising, timely, and close to the experience of a divine epiphany.

However, this correspondence between the Ciceronian Octavian and the Virgilian iuvenis should not necessarily be adduced as further evidence for Octavian being the candidate. Elsewhere in the Eclogues, Virgil mentions contemporary Roman political figures without any ambiguity: the names of Pollio, Varus, Julius Caesar, and Gallus appear explicitly in Eclogues 4, 6, 9 and 10.Footnote 37 Therefore we must infer that the undisclosed identity of the divine benefactor in Eclogue 1 is a salient artistic choice, and that this choice is not an obstacle to interpretation, but has a bearing on it.Footnote 38

The point of this act of anonymisation, I would suggest, is twofold. Firstly, the anonymity of the deified iuvenis helps to distance the image of the ‘god-man’ — perhaps especially Octavian's image as the Divi filius — from the suffering and strife described in the poem, and to re-connect it with positive change. The poem's decidedly vague conceptualisation of libertas as a condition which only the ‘god-man’ can provide not only turns the triumviral contest for political legitimacy into an apparently noble process of civic emancipation, but also reframes divine impersonation as a practice rooted in securing peace and stability. At the same time, as Tityrus insinuates that even the worship of an unidentifiable benefactor could have a unifying effect on a community (cf. 1.6–8), the First Eclogue transforms the ‘god-man’ into a personification of political cohesion, which in turn rehabilitates the image of the Divi filius among the poem's contemporary audience.

Secondly, with this act of anonymisation Virgil makes it difficult for the reader to identify the iuvenis with any one particular figure or tradition of divinisation. This pointed avoidance of specificity, I argue, foreshadows Augustus’ self-representation and the political language of the Augustan Principate. As critics have noted, Virgil's depiction of the worship of the iuvenis is informed not only by contemporary political usages of divinising imagery, but also by several other traditions including Hellenistic ruler cult, Epicurean philosophy, Roman republican hero worship, as well as the poetry of Theocritus, Hesiod and Callimachus. To be precise, the appearance and reported speech of the iuvenis recall the Hesiodic Muses in the Theogony (Hes., Theog. 24–6) and Callimachus’ Apollo in the Aetia (Callim., Aet. fr.1.21–4), thereby suggesting that Virgil's iuvenis is likewise an initiator of poetry.Footnote 39 Meanwhile, the idea of a ‘present’ god-man (praesentis, 1.41) suggests the possible influence of the language and practice of Hellenistic ruler-cult on Virgil's poetry (above, n. 34). In terms of the ritual details of Tityrus’ worship, they appear to be modelled on the sacrifices which Ptolemy II Philadelphus and Arsinoe are said to have offered to Ptolemy I Soter and Berenice in Theocritus’ Idyll 17 (especially verses 124–30),Footnote 40 as well as the monthly celebrations of Epicurus held by his followers.Footnote 41 Furthermore, it is also possible that the offerings given to the iuvenis are drawn from the practice of republican hero cult, such as the ones offered to Gaius Marius and Marius Gratidianus.Footnote 42 This amalgamation of different traditions attests to the First Eclogue's varied dialogues with its poetic predecessors and the lively debate surrounding divinisation during the late Republic.Footnote 43 On the other hand, by combining a number of figures and traditions in his depiction, Virgil avoids making his iuvenis look too much like one thing or the other, thus implying that the iuvenis is both the θεὸς ἐπιφανής of Greek ruler cult and the Muse-like figure of Greek poetry (and a whole bunch of other things). In other words, the indecipherability of the status of the iuvenis is part of the point. That the exact nature of this revered iuvenis is not clearly recognisable, but also not entirely unfamiliar, suggestively epitomises the ambiguous position Augustus will come to occupy in the Principate. What is more, the conflation of libertas and otium in Tityrus’ speeches culminates in the dissolution of difference between emancipation (from servitium) and restoration (cf. ut ante); and this discursive evasiveness of Virgil's poem bears the hallmark of the language of the later Augustan Principate, which pointedly refuses to define whether Rome has been transformed or restored by the new Caesar.Footnote 44 In short, the divine young man of the First Eclogue most probably ‘is’ Octavian; but when this poetic portrait is consumed within a cultural milieu shaped by and responding to the politics of libertas and divine self-imaging, the iuvenis is certainly more than just Octavian. Reading deep into this image of a deified Roman benefactor who (somehow) heralds both transformation and restoration, it might just be possible to see the silhouettes of the discursive operation of the Augustan Principate.

IV POETRY, POLITICS, AND THE (AUGUSTAN) GOLDEN AGE

In this final section, I would like to return to the idea that the iuvenis of the First Eclogue, like the Hesiodic Muses and the Callimachean Apollo, is a kind of poetic initiator. Given that Virgil's poem opens with an image of Tityrus singing freely and without worry (1.1–4), the implication that the iuvenis can influence the production of poetry demands further attention. By assimilating the intervention of the iuvenis to the inspiration provided by poetic divinities, Virgil may well be drawing on the literary tradition of depicting one's patron as a god.Footnote 45 However, the iuvenis of the First Eclogue appears to have more control over the shepherds’ artistic output than an ordinary patron: as Tityrus implied, this young man exclusively granted him the permission to sing (permisit, 1.10). If creative productivity and artistic libertas are subject not only to divine inspiration and patronal support, but also to obtaining permission from a figure of authority, it then raises questions about how free Tityrus’ poetic speech really is.Footnote 46 Notably, Meliboeus, who has not encountered a powerful benefactor, announces later in the poem that there would be no more songs from him (‘carmina nulla canam’, 1.77). Pastoral poetry, and the fictional world it generates, is conventionally built on the premise of an organic exchange of songs between shepherds. However, by subjecting this creative process to the whim of a benefactor, through which the framework of exchange is replaced by an economy of permission-and-obligation, the First Eclogue hints at the poetry's transition into an aesthetic product of a new ideological system.

Indeed, the final scene of Eclogue 1 goes even further by suggesting that social cohesion too relies on this new system of benefaction (1.79–83):

T: Hic tamen hanc mecum poteras requiescere noctem
80  fronde super viridi: sunt nobis mitia poma,
castaneae molles et pressi copia lactis,
et iam summa procul villarum culmina fumant
maioresque cadunt altis de montibus umbrae.
Tityrus: Yet this night you could rest here with me on the green leafage. We have ripe apples, soft chestnuts, and a wealth of pressed cheeses. Even now the housetops afar are smoking and longer shadows fall from the mountain heights.

A lot hangs on how one construes the verb poteras (1.79). The form of the imperfect can be hypothetical (i.e. ‘you might have/could have rested here with me’), in which case Tityrus is not really offering hospitality, but rather gesturing towards the end of the old dispensation under which it would have been normal for Meliboeus to spend the night at his.Footnote 47 But if the poteras is supposed to introduce a genuine invitation, then Tityrus’ offer of temporary accommodation (1.79) and personal produce (1.80–1) puts him in the role of the benefactor. Through this promise of aid, which is delivered in the form of a song-reply (just like the richly poetic speech-act of the iuvenis), security and community spirit are thus restored, albeit for one night only (‘hanc … noctem’, 1.79). Bowditch has argued that here pastoral song succeeds in ‘assimilating the social and historical discourse of benefaction to the conventions of bucolic generosity and community’, which in turn ‘dramatizes the ideological potential of pastoral song […] to overcome historical division and provide a shared set of values’.Footnote 48 By closing his poem with an idealised image of pastoral song mediating social cohesion, Virgil leaves the door open for readers to construe the First Eclogue as a text that is complicit in implementing a socio-political system that relies on and privileges the agency of an empowered individual. It is in this respect that the First Eclogue appears to produce the grammar of authoritarianism, articulating what will eventually become the central ideological tenets of the Augustan Principate.

Of course, the Eclogues are not short of moments where Virgil displays profound sympathy for those who have become victims of the triumvirs’ struggle for power. The voice and suffering of Meliboeus in Eclogue 1 counteract the poem's discourse of idealised authoritarianism. In Eclogue 9, which is widely considered a companion-piece to Eclogue 1 (and possibly the earlier of the two), we find another example of this dynamic.Footnote 49 Here the shepherd Moeris is forced off his land, just as Meliboeus is in the opening poem; and Moeris’ account of the new landowner's tyrannical brutality paints a stark picture of authoritarian power (‘haec mea sunt; veteres migrate coloni’, ‘these are mine; move on, old tenants’, 9.4). In the ensuing exchange between Moeris and Lycidas, we learn that the shepherds had hoped that their song-master Menalcas would come to their rescue in the land dispute, like the iuvenis of the First Eclogue (‘audieram … | omnia carminibus vestrum servasse Menalcan’, ‘I had heard that your Menalcas had saved everything with his songs’, 9.7–10). But this turns out to be false (‘audieras, et fama fuit’, ‘you had heard it, and that was the story’, 9.11), and the failure of Menalcas makes clear that he is no iuvenis.

Indeed, Eclogue 9 appears to undercut the notion that a powerful figure of authority could make things better. In parallel to the anonymous iuvenis who comes to the aid of Tityrus in a moment of crisis, Eclogue 9 ends with Moeris appealing for help from a figure of authority identified only as ipse (9.66–7):

M: Desine plura, puer, et quod nunc instat agamus;
carmina tum melius, cum venerit ipse, canemus.
Moeris: Say no more, boy, and let us get on with what is pressing now. We shall sing our songs better, when he himself has come.

Commentators are surely right to identify ipse (9.67) as Menalcas, but the vagueness of the final line is troubling. Venerit anticipates the arrival of the song-master, but we are not told when that will be. ‘Melius … canemus’ looks ahead to the resumption of pastoral singing,Footnote 50 but that seems unlikely when Menalcas has already failed to save the shepherds with song (9.7–11, above). Indeed, Virgil's poem appears to cast doubt on both the efficacy of song and the prospect of pastoral recovery. Earlier in the poem, Lycidas tries to console Moeris by reciting a song he had once heard from his friend — a song about a blessed age heralded by the star of Caesar (9.44–50; especially, ‘ecce Dionaei processit Caesaris astrum, | astrum quo segetes gauderent frugibus’, ‘see the star of Caesar, born of Dione, has risen — the star by which the fields rejoice with corn’, 9.47–8).Footnote 51 However, Moeris immediately says that he cannot remember singing it (9.51–5). By distancing himself from a song about peace under the deified Caesar, Moeris’ reaction not only underlines the fragmentation of shared cultural memory and the breakdown social cohesion in contemporary Rome,Footnote 52 but also punctures the idealism that the pastoral world can depend on the power of a benefactor for stability. Set against this backdrop where the power of song is repeatedly dismissed in the face of crisis, any optimism in the poem's final line is undercut.

Furthermore, the absence of Menalcas’ name in final line of Eclogue 9 contrasts sharply with the ending of Eclogue 5, which has Menalca as its last word (5.90). In that poem, Menalcas not only knew songs like those of Eclogues 2 and 3 (5.86–7), but was even able to divinise Daphnis and reinvigorate the pastoral community with song (5.56–80).Footnote 53 The absence of Menalcas’ name at the end of Eclogue 9 therefore hints at the elusiveness of pastoral recovery. If the unknown identity of the salvific iuvenis of Eclogue 1 adds to his powerful mystique, then the absence of Menalcas’ name here does precisely the opposite. Far from signalling that change is under way, the anonymity of ipse gestures at the unlikelihood of the shepherds’ salvation and the intangibility of hope. As the poem ends, we are left with no secure idea of what help this vaguely identified ipse will bring, or when, or how. The poetics of anonymity cuts both ways: it may be used either to open up salvific possibility (all the more potent and appealing for being undefined), or to undermine this potential altogether.

The tension between the Eclogues’ naturalisation of authoritarian ideology and the poems’ sympathy and despair for the victims of despotic forces cannot be resolved. Nor does it need to be. This irresolvability is what makes the pastoral world of the Eclogues so pertinent to its contemporary readers: it is through this tension that these poems speak to reality. In other words, to get a better sense of the Eclogues’ political inclinations, we need to find moments where Virgil lets go of tension and enters instead the realm of idealism. Luckily, there is one such instance: Eclogue 4.

In this poem, Virgil envisages the return of the Golden Age inaugurated by the birth of a miraculous puer. The poem's unhindered optimism was probably generated by the temporary reconciliation between Octavian and Antony following the Treaty of Brundisium (40 b.c.), brokered by G. Asinius Pollio.Footnote 54 If so, the puer at the time of the poem's composition most likely represented an anticipated offspring of Antony and Octavia (whose marriage sealed the alliance), or a symbol of hope for peace in the Roman world.Footnote 55

In its sketch of Rome's Golden Age, Eclogue 4 strikes a parallel with Eclogue 1 by integrating the idea of willing subjection into its discourse on libertas. The poem imagines the forthcoming glorious age first and foremost as a time in which the Roman world will be freed from fear and ancestral sin (‘si qua manent sceleris vestigia nostri, | inrita perpetua solvent formidine terras’, ‘if some traces of our sin remain, they will be nullified and free the lands from lasting fear’, 4.13–14); and we know from the later works of Virgil and Horace that the imagery of the Romans’ past sins often operates as a metaphor for the civil war.Footnote 56 However, as soon as Virgil proclaims this forthcoming liberation and age of peace for his fellow Romans, the poet makes the anonymous puer their ruler (4.15–17):

ille deum vitam accipiet divisque videbit
permixtos heroas et ipse videbitur illis,
pacatumque reget patriis virtutibus orbem.
He shall receive the gift of divine life, shall see heroes mingled with gods, and shall himself be seen by them, and shall rule the world to which his father's prowess brought peace.

The expression ‘reget … orbem’ (4.17) unmistakably carries the connotation of the authoritarian rule of a single man;Footnote 57 but in Virgil's formulation of Rome's Golden Age, this form of domination happily coexists with the return of libertas. In addition, as Hunter has noted, these lines of Eclogue 4 allude to the divinisation of the Ptolemies in Theocritus’ Idyll 17.13–22.Footnote 58 By assimilating the puer to Hellenistic monarchs, Virgil conflates the beginning of Rome's journey towards a Golden Age of liberty with the introduction of a new, un-republican, system of power.

Furthermore, just as the First Eclogue relies on the conventions of bucolic generosity to naturalise a system of benefaction and inequality, here in Eclogue 4 the idea of Golden-Age voluntarism is used by Virgil to romanticise consent to autocratic rule. In this passage, the puer is depicted as eventually ‘accepting’ (accipiet, 4.15) a life amongst the gods as if he were receiving a gift. The implicit characterisation of his divinisation as an honour conferred upon a benefactor implies that the reign of the puer was something that people gratefully consented to and celebrated. Later in the poem, even the natural world appears to be responding enthusiastically to the boy's reign, as the earth happily produces ‘little gifts’ for him (‘nullo munuscula cultu … tellus … fundet’, 4.18–20). By the end, socio-economic exchange ceases to exist and is replaced by agricultural voluntarism (‘nec nautica pinus | mutabit merces; omnes feret omnia tellus’, ‘nor will the pine ship trade goods; every land will produce everything’, 4.38–9).Footnote 59 This shift from reciprocity to unidirectional and spontaneous production, glossed here as utopian fecundity, aestheticises the onset of a hierarchy based on willing submission. By imagining Rome's future in this way, Eclogue 4 — much like Eclogue 1 — creates a conceptual framework wherein the advent of autocratic power would be embraced.

However, in not giving this authoritarian system a ‘recognisable face’, Virgil makes an important point about contemporary Roman politics and the nature of power. Both Eclogue 4 and Eclogue 1 present an unidentified individual as being more significant than other established forms of power; yet in both instances, Virgil pointedly refuses to identify this one entity that matters. In Eclogue 4, the entire Roman world pins its hope on the puer, while traditional deities barely feature: they show up when the boy is born (‘iam redit et Virgo’, ‘now too the Virgin returns’, 4.6), politely give their support (‘tu modo nascenti puero … | casta fave Lucina’, ‘only do you, chaste Lucina, smile on the birth of the child’, 4.8–10), and wait for him in heaven (4.15–16, above). The puer clearly overshadows the importance of the Olympian pantheon. In Eclogue 1, Tityrus draws a sharp contrast between the absence and insufficiency of traditional divi (1.41) and the presence and power of the singular iuvenis. Indeed, one gets the impression that the pastoral world simply would not function without him. Virgil's emphasis on the efficacy of one-ness, I would suggest, mirrors the way that the triumvirate (three men competing for power) is moving towards the Principate (one man in power). In fact, the way in which all the wannabe one-man rulers of the triumviral period identify themselves with one particular divinity — and wear these identities as masks that conceal their own — further underscores this movement towards a new, depersonalised one-ness. Against this background, Virgil's strategy of not identifying the actual figure of authority subtly constructs one-man rule as a deeply anonymised form of government, wherein the one person who matters the most is so removed from ordinary mortal men that the locus of power is ultimately unknowable.

Later in Aeneid 6, Virgil redeploys imagery from Eclogues 1 and 4 in a eulogy of Augustus (Aen. 6.791–4):

hic vir, hic est, tibi quem promitti saepius audis,
Augustus Caesar, divi genus, aurea condet
saecula qui rursus Latio regnata per arva
Saturno quondam.
Here is the man — here he is — whom you so often hear promised to you: Augustus Caesar, son of a god, who will bring back the golden years to the fields of Latium once ruled over by Saturn.

Virgil's Augustus — here introduced with the words hic vir (6.791) — answers not only the puer of Eclogue 4, but also the description of the iuvenis as iste deus in Eclogue 1 (line 18); and this act of literary self-referentiality, as Geue well notes, is highlighted by the words ‘tibi quem promitti saepius audis’ (6.791): we have indeed heard all about him before.Footnote 60 By presenting the arrival of Augustus as something that has long been anticipated, Virgil frames political transformation as predestined history, thus naturalising the emergence of the Principate.Footnote 61 That Augustus appears so compellingly as the eventual manifestation of the unnamed saviours of Eclogues 1 and 4 is precisely because in the earlier poems Virgil makes the power of an supreme individual not merely compatible with, but the defining feature of, a new age of peace and prosperity. However, the poet's ‘demystification’ of earlier anonymous characters does not render Augustus any closer. The evocation of the puer and the iuvenis creates the sense that Augustus emerged from the unknown to become the ruler of Rome right in front of our eyes (cf. hic … hic, 6.791). Virgil's de-anonymisation is not just for dramatic effect: it hints at how autocratic power can dazzle and take hold before you even know it.

V CONCLUSION

Virgil's First Eclogue translates the harsh reality of citizens’ disempowerment amid the triumviral contest for political legitimacy into a narrative of liberation, whereby the oligarchic few, and Octavian in particular, are framed as the only party capable of restoring ‘liberty’ and bringing positive change. In so doing, the poem not only redefines libertas as a condition of security and peacetime pleasure which can only be activated by those who already have political agency, but also naturalises the idea of political benefaction, which necessarily entails subjection and dependence. Combining this particular interpretation of ‘liberation’ with a story of a benefactor's divinisation, Virgil's poem sanctifies a political structure headed by an overwhelmingly influential individual. It hardly matters who this individual is, because Virgil's poem manages to naturalise a system of power. The anonymity of the poem's iuvenis is part of this naturalising strategy, as it allows anyone — Octavian or some other charismatic leader — to be placed in the role of society's saviour. Seen in this light, the divinisation of the iuvenis in Eclogue 1 is far more than an expression of gratitude for the benefactor or a flattering depiction of the patron's higher social status. Rather, by glorifying the idea that beneficent power rests with a singular charismatic man, and by idealising one's total dependence on an influential benefactor, the First Eclogue gives expression to what will become the central ideological tenets of the Augustan Principate.

Footnotes

I am grateful to the friends and colleagues who have provided valuable feedback on earlier versions of this article, in particular Nick Freer, Fiachra Mac Góráin, Tom Geue, Ian Goh, Caleb Dance, Naomi Scott, Duncan Kennedy and Ellen O'Gorman. I also thank the Editor, Peter Thonemann, and the Journal's anonymous readers for their constructive comments. All translations are my own.

1 The composition of individual poems of the Eclogues may have started as early as 42 b.c.; see Coleman Reference Coleman1977: 14–21, though his attempt to ascertain the date of each poem proves inconclusive. The Eclogues probably underwent continuous modification until the moment of their publication as a single volume in 35 b.c.; see Clausen Reference Clausen1994: 125–6 on the revision process, and Bowersock Reference Bowersock1971 on the date of publication. Cucchiarelli Reference Cucchiarelli2012: 15–16 proposes an earlier publication date of c. 37 b.c.

2 The opening passage of the R.G. does, however, appear to echo the Philippics, where Cicero frequently turned to the theme of the young Caesar's liberation of Rome (cf. Cic., Phil. 3.3, 3.5, 4.2, 4.4); see Cooley Reference Cooley2009: 109 for further discussion. The notion of political liberation is a prevalent motif in the political writing of the late Republic: see also Lepidus’ speech in Sall., Hist. 1.

3 See esp. Galinsky Reference Galinsky2006: 6–8, who argues that the Virgilian libertas in Ecl. 1 correlates precisely with the later Augustan concept of libertas as securitas.

4 A later expression of this compatibility can be found in Tac., Agr. 3.1: ‘Nerva Caesar res olim dissociabilis miscuerit, principatum ac libertatem’ (‘Nerva Caesar has united things once incompatible, the Principate and liberty’).

5 Numerous alternative candidates have been proposed. Liegle Reference Liegle1943: 219–26 argues that the iuvenis is L. Antonius, brother of the triumvir and leader of one side in the Perusine War. Grisart Reference Grisart1966 thinks that the iuvenis is Virgil himself. Berkowitz Reference Berkowitz1972: 26 n. 26 makes the case for Varus, or Gallus, or Pollio, with the latter gaining further support from Cairns Reference Cairns2008: 70–4. Wright Reference Wright1983 suggests that the iuvenis resembles Apollo. Critics interested in the Epicurean tenets of Eclogue 1 argue that the poem's image of the deified benefactor brings to mind Epicurus (see esp. Bing Reference Bing2016; but also Rundin Reference Rundin2003; Hardie Reference Hardie2006: 290–1; Papanghelis Reference Papanghelis2006: 376–7; Karakasis Reference Karakasis2011: 176–7; Davis Reference Davis2012: 79–98; Scholl Reference Scholl2014: 493–4). Relatedly, Kronenberg Reference Kronenberg2016 draws attention to the presence of Lucretius in Virgil's depiction of the iuvenis and Daphnis in Eclogues 1 and 5, respectively.

6 Du Quesnay Reference Du Quesnay, Woodman and West1984: 27–32; Kennedy Reference Kennedy and Powell1992: 29–33; Henderson Reference Henderson1994: 81. Later in Epode 9, Horace implicitly assimilated Octavian's victories at Naulochus and Actium, and strongly implied that they were wars of ‘liberation’ and not civil wars (‘Neptunius | dux… | minatus Urbi vincla’, ‘the Neptunian leader threatened to put the City in chains’, 7–9; ‘Romanus … | emancipatus feminae | … miles et spadonibus | servire rugosis potest’, ‘a Roman, enslaved to a woman … and, a soldier no less, is capable of serving wrinkled eunuchs’, 11–14).

7 Clausen Reference Clausen1994: 31–2.

8 Galinsky Reference Galinsky2006: 6, original emphasis.

9 Bowditch Reference Bowditch2001: 121–3.

10 As with Bowditch, my ‘suspicious’ approach is informed by the notion of ‘negative hermeneutics’, which was first discussed by Paul Ricoeur (Reference Ricoeur1965: 33–44) and developed further by Fredric Jameson (Reference Jameson1971). As Jameson Reference Jameson1971: 119–20 explains: ‘We must … distinguish between what Paul Ricoeur has called negative and positive hermeneutics, between the hermeneutics of suspicion and the hermeneutics of a restoration of some original, forgotten meaning […]. For Ricoeur, of course, the latter cannot be imagined as anything other than the sacred […]. Negative hermeneutic, on the other hand, is at one with modern philosophy itself, with those critiques of ideology and illusory consciousness which we find in Nietzsche and in Marx’.

11 Even among critics who do not identify the iuvenis as Octavian, the approach is generally one of candidate-searching, as shown above in n. 5. One exception is Mayer Reference Mayer1983: 20–6, who treats the iuvenis as a symbol of Rome's power for the good.

12 On the dissatisfaction of both the veterans and the threatened landowners, see App., B Civ. 5.12–13; Dio 48.6–12. While ancient biographies of Virgil claim that the poet's farm was confiscated and returned to him (cf. Donat., Vit. Verg. 19), it is patently clear that this story was extrapolated from the poem itself. See esp. Farrell Reference Farrell, Cheney and de Armas2002: 24−6; Korenjak Reference Korenjak2003; Laird Reference Laird2009.

13 On the exilic connotation of patriam fugio, cf. OLD s.v. fugio and Coleman Reference Coleman1977 on patriae at 1.3. See also Ov., Tr. 1.5.65–6 (clearly reacting to the opening lines of Eclogue 1): ‘ille suam laetus patriam victorque petebat: | a patria fugi victus et exul ego’ (‘He was seeking his native land in joy and as a victor; I have fled mine, defeated and an exile’).

14 Note the contrast between efficacy (fecit, 1.6) and the frivolousness of Tityrus’ action (ludere, 1.10). Ludere, of course, can also be read metapoetically as the production of Callimachean poetry.

15 Davis Reference Davis2012: 20.

16 See Coleman Reference Coleman1977 on 1.7; Du Quesnay Reference Du Quesnay1981: 104; Clausen Reference Clausen1994 on 1.7. The plural nobis (1.6) also disputes Meliboeus’ suggestion that Tityrus’ good fortune is a case of individual blessing (cf. the repetition of tu at verses 1 and 4). Of course, plural pronouns can equally well refer to an individual as to a collective, cf. Lucr. 5.19 (Lucretius on Epicurus), ‘quo magis hic merito nobis deus esse videtur’ (‘for which reason he more rightly seems to be a god to us’), where nobis could refer to the poet himself or both Lucretius and Memmius, the latter mentioned a little earlier in the text (Lucr. 5.11); for further discussion, see Bing Reference Bing2016: 175.

17 This conceit recalls the convention of naming the sedes of the laudandus in a hymn for a deity; see Du Quesnay Reference Du Quesnay1981: 113; Davis Reference Davis2012: 23.

18 See e.g. Coleman Reference Coleman1977: 89–91; Du Quesnay Reference Du Quesnay1981; Clausen Reference Clausen1994: 30–1; Wimmel Reference Wimmel1998; Galinsky Reference Galinsky2006.

19 Eckerman Reference Eckerman2016: 262–3; anticipated by Clausen Reference Clausen1994: 44–5. Eckerman convincingly identifies an allusion to Theoc., Id. 14.52–5 in Tityrus’ account of how he found emotional alleviation by leaving home and his mistress. Note later at 1.40 (‘servitio … exire’), it is still not clear whether Tityrus’ servitude is literal or metaphorical.

20 The most informative recent works on the interaction between ‘divine imaging’ and contemporary poetry are those of Miller Reference Miller2009: 15–53; Cucchiarelli Reference Cucchiarelli2011: 155–60; Pandey Reference Pandey2018: 36–50. Earlier studies, such as Weinstock Reference Weinstock1971, Pelling Reference Pelling1988 and Gurval Reference Gurval1995, remain important. Cole Reference Cole2013 has shown that divinisation and divine impersonation were already an important element of elite discourse by 44 b.c.

21 Cucchiarelli Reference Cucchiarelli2011: 157.

22 It is tempting to think that Octavian's choice to portray himself as a ‘son’ may have something to do with the fact that he was once disparagingly referred to as a mere puer by some in the Senate (Cic., Phil. 13.24; App., B Civ. 3.43.176; Suet., Aug. 12; Dio 46.30.1). Octavian also appropriated the star iconography following the confirmation of Caesar's deification (1 January 42). See e.g. RRC 535/2 (42–39 b.c.): the obverse shows Octavian's head with the legend DIVI⋅F and a star. The reverse of some earlier issues (RRC 525/1–2; 526/1–3) shows Octavian's head with the legend DIVI IULI⋅F; for further discussion, see Weinstock Reference Weinstock1971: 399–401. In addition, the design of the gilded equestrian monument voted to Octavian in January 43 b.c. is said to have undergone modification to make its subject resemble a divinity more closely (Cic., Ad Brut. 1.15.7; Vell. Pat. 2.61.3; App., B Civ. 3.51; Dio 46.29.2). The change of design can be seen by comparing the images on RRC 490/1 and 3 (marked S⋅C) with those on a later coin, RRC 518/2 (marked POPVL⋅IVSSV); see Zanker Reference Zanker1988: 37–9; Osgood Reference Osgood2006: 117. On Cicero's designation of the young Caesar as puer, see Manuwald Reference Manuwald2007: I 94–5.

23 On the interpretation of the ‘Olympian’ banquet, see Charlesworth Reference Charlesworth1933: 175; Scott Reference Scott1933: 30; Gagé Reference Gagé1955: 487; Weinstock Reference Weinstock1971: 15; Gurval Reference Gurval1995: 96–8; Miller Reference Miller2009: 16–18. There is sufficient evidence to suggest that prior to Philippi (42 b.c.) it was Brutus, and not Octavian, who had the strongest public Apolline profile; see Miller Reference Miller2009: 24–6.

24 Miller Reference Miller2009: 24. See Pollini Reference Pollini, Raaflaub and Toher1990: 344–5 on Antony's Neptunian iconography on BMCRR East 149–53 (36–35 b.c.). See Zanker Reference Zanker1988: 97 on the cameo of 35–30 b.c., which depicts a nude Octavian standing in a chariot holding a trident. Note also that both Horace in Epode 4 and, later, Augustus in R.G. 25 portray Sextus’ faction as slaves-turned-pirates (cf. ‘latrones atque servilem manum’, Hor., Epod. 4.19; ‘mare pacavi a praedonibus. eo bello servorum …’ Aug., R.G. 25).

25 Arena Reference Arena2012: 8 defines libertas as a status of ‘non-subjection to the arbitrary will of either a foreign power or a domestic group or individual’. Arena's thinking is critically informed by the works of Skinner Reference Skinner1998; Ando Reference Ando2011; Pettit Reference Pettit2012, among others. See also earlier studies by Wirszubski Reference Wirszubski1950; Klein Reference Klein1969: 1–22; Hellegouarch Reference Hellegouarch1972: 542–59; Brunt Reference Brunt and Brunt1988.

26 Brunt Reference Brunt and Brunt1988: 283. Arena Reference Arena2012: 244–57 shows that, in the lead-up to the battle of Mutina (43 b.c.), claiming to support libertas became a convenient way of gaining political legitimacy for opposing sides.

27 See Tatum Reference Tatum and Balmaceda2020: 208–9 on Antony's attempt to associate himself with libertas in the immediate aftermath of Philippi. Prior to that, in 44–43 b.c., Antony positioned himself as the true libertatis vindex in response to Cicero's allegation that he threatened republican freedom; see Tatum Reference Tatum and Balmaceda2020: 189–207.

28 On Antony's self-identification with Dionysus, see esp. Brenk Reference Brenk, Gallo and Scardigli1995; also Pollini Reference Pollini, Raaflaub and Toher1990; La Rocca Reference La Rocca1992. It is worth noting that Antony's Dionysian impersonation may have had a mixed reception even in Greece and the east: see Plut., Ant. 24.4–5, with a recent discussion by Mac Góráin Reference Mac Góráin and Mac Góráin2020: 21.

29 Eckerman Reference Eckerman2016: 262.

30 Modern scholars generally agree that divus (1.41) here is just a variation of deus. Note also its appearance in Hor., Carm. 3.5.2–4 in connection with Augustus: ‘praesens divus habebitur | Augustus adiectis Britannis | imperio gravibusque Persis’ (‘Augustus will be held a god in our midst when Britons and dread Persians are added to the empire’). Outside the poetic context, however, there is a significant distinction between divus and deus. As Price Reference Price1984: 83 points out, from the cult of the deceased Julius Caesar onwards, divus in official terminology referred exclusively to former emperors and members of their family. But whether some kind of distinction had already existed when the deceased Julius Caesar was given the title divus remains unclear. Varro's attempts to define these two terms (Serv. ad Aen. 12.139 = Varro, Ling. fr. 2. Goetz–Schoell; Serv. ad Aen. 5.34 = Varro fr. 424, Grammaticae Romanae Fragmenta, ed. Funaioli) are considered unsatisfactory by modern critics; see Weinstock Reference Weinstock1971: 29; Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian2013: 7–8; Gradel Reference Gradel2002: 63–6.

31 There is, I think, a subtle but important difference between active concealment (what Virgil does here) and leaving the details of a high-stakes situation vague (e.g. what Horace does in Sat. 1.5 with regard to the purpose of his trip and the whereabouts of Octavian).

32 See also Cucchiarelli Reference Cucchiarelli2011: 159–60.

33 In Cicero's speech, the overlapping of political and religious discourses is encapsulated in the word exortus, which elevates Octavian's status and evokes the emergence of a celestial divinity (further connecting Octavian to the apotheosis of Julius Caesar).

34 Praesens evokes the Hellenistic concept of a sovereign as θεὸς ἐπιφανής: see Cucchiarelli Reference Cucchiarelli2012 on 1.41. On divine rulers as ‘present’ deities in the Hellenistic world, see Koenen Reference Koenen, Bulloch, Gruen, Long and Stewart1993: 65; Clauss Reference Clauss1996, esp. 406–7; Chaniotis Reference Chaniotis, Iossif, Chankowski and Lorber2011: 174–6. Note also that Cicero records Hercules as a benefactor of mankind with the description ‘tantus et tam praesens’ (Cic., Tusc. 1.28), which further suggests that praesens is used of those who are semi-divine or deified for their earthly acts of salvation.

35 Note also Tityrus’ promise later in the poem, that he would never forget the ‘face’ of his saviour (‘illius… vultus’, 1.63).

36 OLD s.v. responsum 1b, 2a; Du Quesnay Reference Du Quesnay1981: 134; Davis Reference Davis2012: 27.

37 Pollio: 4.12. Varus: 6.7–12 and 9.26–7. Julius Caesar: 9.47. Gallus: 6.64 and 10 passim. In addition, the names of the poets Varius and Cinna appear in 9.35.

38 For a recent critical reconsideration of the significance of anonymity in Latin literature, see Geue Reference Geue2019, esp. 1–20.

39 This Hesiodic-Callimachean double-allusion lies in the combination of primus (1.44) and ut ante (1.45); see Wright Reference Wright1983: 118–20 and Cucchiarelli Reference Cucchiarelli2012 on 1.44–5. The instruction of the iuvenis about dealing with animals also contains etymological plays that connote bucolic composition (cf. βουκολέω, Theoc., Id. 7.92; βουκολιάζομαι, 7.36, 9.1); see Wright Reference Wright1983: 114–17.

40 Hunter Reference Hunter2001: 160. The fact that the iuvenis is placed in the exact centre of Virgil's poem is similarly reminiscent of a well-known Theocritean encomiastic motif from the same idyll: ἀνδρῶν δ’ αὖ Πτολεμαῖος ἐνὶ πρώτοισι λεγέσθω | καὶ πύματος καὶ μέσσος (Id. 17.3–4). See Wright Reference Wright1983: 119; and also Octavian's appearance at the halfway point of the prologue to the Georgics and in the so-called ‘proem in the middle’ of Georgics 3.

41 Diog. Laert. 10.16–22, with further discussion by Davis Reference Davis2012: 28. Bing Reference Bing2016: 176 also points out that the Varronian etymology of iuvenis from iuvare brings to mind Epicurus, whose name means the one who ‘comes to aid’ of another (ἐπίκουρος).

42 Marius received offerings of food and libations along with the gods for his victories over Jugurtha and the Germans: Plut., Mar. 27.9; Val. Max. 8.15.7. Lesser offerings of incense and candles were awarded to Marius Gratidianus in 85 b.c.: Cic., Off. 3.80; Sen., De ira 3.18.1; Plin., HN 33.132. While republican hero worship did not always involve animal sacrifice in the manner of the cult of Tityrus’ benefactor, the kind of outburst of popular support for a political leader resulting in the institution of his cult is ostensibly reflected in Tityrus’ fervent devotion to his Roman iuvenis. See Beard et al. Reference Beard, North and Price1998: I 143–4 for further discussion of the cult of republican politicians.

43 On the Romans’ interest in and scepticism surrounding divinisation, see Beard et al. Reference Beard, North and Price1998: I 140–9. On Cicero's contribution to Roman thinking on divinisation, see Cole Reference Cole2013.

44 Geue Reference Geue, Labate and Rosati2013: 56 also points out that the expression ut ante (1.45) functions as a means of naturalising change via a discourse of continuity; and so the iuvenis appears simultaneously as the guarantor and inventor of tradition, much like Augustus himself. On interactions between oppositional ideological constructs (such as tradition and innovation) in the Augustan age, see esp. Galinsky Reference Galinsky1996.

45 This motif in Roman literature appears to have its origin in comedy, where parasites refer to their benefactors as divinities or genii (see e.g. Plaut., Mer. 138).

46 Roman poets were particularly alive to the idea that certain genres enjoyed more ‘freedom’ than others, cf. Hor., Epist. 2.1.145–55, Ars P. 281–4; and Gowers Reference Gowers2012: 148–51, 154–5 on Hor., Sat. 1.4. On the poets’ sensitivity to the issue of ‘free speech’ under the Principate, see Feeney Reference Feeney and Powell1994.

47 I thank Tom Geue for bringing this important point to my attention.

48 Bowditch Reference Bowditch2001: 129.

49 Eclogue 9 depicts a pastoral world in the aftermath of the post-Philippi land confiscations; but this does not necessarily mean that it was composed in late 42 b.c. However, the tone and political outlook of Eclogue 9 do seem to point to an earlier date than Eclogue 1, which, as some have argued (e.g. Clausen Reference Clausen1972; Coleman Reference Coleman1977: 17–18; Perutelli Reference Perutelli and Horsfall1995: 30–1), may well be one of the latest in the collection.

50 Cucchiarelli Reference Cucchiarelli2012: 478 reads this line as the final ‘rilancio’ of pastoral poetry in the book, before Virgil announces his intention to ‘go up’ a genre in the final poem (cf. surgamus, 10.75).

51 Following most modern scholars, I attribute lines 46–50 to Lycidas (rather than Moeris) and identify Moeris as the ‘original singer’ of this recited song. For further discussion of these textual issues, see Perkell Reference Perkell2001: 73–4.

52 Meban Reference Meban2009: 112–15; see also Davis Reference Davis2012: 42 on the poem's performance of ‘consolation of poetic memory’.

53 Cucchiarelli Reference Cucchiarelli2012: 478. On the efficacy of Menalcas’ poetic performance, see Lowrie Reference Lowrie2009: 145–6. Already by the time of Servius, Virgil's Daphnis was seen as an allegory for Julius Caesar (Serv. ad Ecl. 5.20, ‘alii dicunt significari per allegoriam C. Iulium Caesarem’). Modern scholarship has expanded on the Daphnis–Caesar correspondence: Leach Reference Leach1974: 182–6; Coleman Reference Coleman1977: 173–4; Dobbin Reference Dobbin1995: 32–3; Lowrie Reference Lowrie2009: 145 n. 9; Meban Reference Meban2009: 118–24; Cucchiarelli Reference Cucchiarelli2011: 164; Gale Reference Gale, Farrell and Nelis2013: 280.

54 Pollio's consulship is portrayed in Eclogue 4 as the incubating period for the Golden Age: 4.11–12.

55 Coleman Reference Coleman1977: 150–2 offers a summary of the puer-identity hypotheses proposed by ancient and modern commentators. Broadly speaking, the puer has been variously thought to represent an anticipated offspring of Antony and Octavia (e.g. Du Quesnay Reference Du Quesnay1976: 31–8), or of Pollio (e.g. Cairns Reference Cairns2008: 54–63), or of Octavian (e.g. Harrison Reference Harrison2007: 39–44). A number of scholars insist on identifying the puer with Octavian himself (e.g. Leclercq Reference Leclercq1996: 198–206 and Snijder Reference Snijder and Deroux2010) despite the obvious representational awkwardness. More plausibly, some have suggested that the puer could represent Virgil's hope for Octavian (e.g. Cucchiarelli Reference Cucchiarelli2012: 240), or the poet's hope for a global transformation from bad fortune to universal peace and prosperity (e.g. Davis Reference Davis2012: 65). On the cultural origins of the poem's idea of a temporal mega-cycle synced to the birth of a child, see Norden Reference Norden1924, Rose Reference Rose1942, and Nisbet Reference Nisbet1978, amongst others.

56 Cf. Virg., G. 1.501–2; Hor., Epod. 7; Carm. 1.2, 1.12.

57 Bowditch Reference Bowditch2001: 135.

58 Hunter Reference Hunter2001: 160. Verse 16 in particular evokes the Theocritean image of Alexander and Herakles (to whom the Ptolemies traced their ancestry) joining the company of the Olympian gods (Theoc., Id. 17.20–2).

59 Bowditch Reference Bowditch2001: 135–7, who offers an excellent discussion of the theme of voluntarism in the poem, reads the munuscula as symbol for poetry. See also Stöckinger Reference Stöckinger2016: 9–10, 30.

61 For further discussion, see Geue Reference Geue, Labate and Rosati2013: 64–8.

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Ando, C. 2011: Law, Language and Empire in the Roman Tradition, Philadelphia, PA.10.9783/9780812204889CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arena, V. 2012: Libertas and the Practice of Politics in the Late Roman Republic, Cambridge.10.1017/CBO9781139235754CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beard, M., North, J., and Price, S. 1998: Religions of Rome (2 vols), Cambridge.Google Scholar
Berkowitz, L. 1972: ‘Pollio and the date of the fourth Eclogue’, California Studies in Classical Antiquity 5, 2138.10.2307/25010631CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bing, P. 2016: ‘Epicurus and the iuvenis at Virgil's Eclogue 1.42’, Classical Quarterly 66, 172–9.10.1017/S0009838816000173CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowditch, P. L. 2001: Horace and the Gift Economy of Patronage, Berkeley and Los Angeles.Google Scholar
Bowersock, G. W. 1971: ‘A date in the eighth Eclogue’, Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 75, 7380.10.2307/311217CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brenk, F. E. 1995: ‘Heroic anti-heroes: ruler cult and divine assimilations in Plutarch's lives of Demetrios and Antonius’, in Gallo, I. and Scardigli, B. (eds), Teoria e prassi politica nelle opere di Plutarco, Naples, 6582.Google Scholar
Brunt, P. A. 1988: ‘Libertas in the Republic’, in Brunt, P. A., The Fall of the Roman Republic and Related Essays, Oxford, 281350.Google Scholar
Cairns, F. 2008: ‘C. Asinius Pollio and the Eclogues’, Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society 54, 4979.Google Scholar
Chaniotis, A. 2011: ‘The ithyphallic hymn for Demetrios Poliorketes and Hellenistic religious mentality’, in Iossif, P. P., Chankowski, A. S. and Lorber, C. C. (eds), More than Men, Less than Gods, Leuven, 157–95.Google Scholar
Charlesworth, M. P. 1933: ‘Some fragments of the propaganda of Mark Antony’, Classical Quarterly 27, 172–7.10.1017/S000983880001692XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clausen, W. 1972: ‘On the date of the First Eclogue’, Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 76, 201–5.10.2307/310985CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clausen, W. 1994: A Commentary on Virgil, Eclogues, Oxford.Google Scholar
Clauss, M. 1996: ‘Deus praesens: Der römische Kaiser als Gott’, Klio 78, 400–33.10.1524/klio.1996.78.2.400CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cole, S. 2013: Cicero and the Rise of Deification at Rome, Cambridge.10.1017/CBO9781139506373CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coleman, R. 1977: Vergil. Eclogues, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Cooley, A. E. 2009: Res Gestae Diui Augusti. Text, Translation, and Commentary, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Cucchiarelli, A. 2011: ‘Ivy and laurel: divine models in Virgil's Eclogues’, Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 106, 155–78.Google Scholar
Cucchiarelli, A. 2012: P. Virgilio Marone. Le Bucoliche, introduzione e commento, Rome.Google Scholar
Davis, G. 2012: Parthenope: The Interplay of Ideas in Vergilian Bucolic, Leiden.10.1163/9789004233256CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dobbin, R. 1995: ‘Julius Caesar in Jupiter's prophecy, Aeneid, Book 1’, Classical Antiquity 14, 540.10.2307/25000141CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Du Quesnay, I. M. Le M. 1976: ‘Vergil's fourth Eclogue’, Papers of the Liverpool Latin Seminar 1, 31–8.Google Scholar
Du Quesnay, I. M. Le M. 1981: ‘Vergil's first Eclogue’, Papers of the Liverpool Latin Seminar 3, 29182.Google Scholar
Du Quesnay, I. M. Le M. 1984: ‘Horace and Maecenas: the propaganda value of Sermones I’, in Woodman, T. and West, D. (eds), Poetry and Politics in the Age of Augustus, Cambridge, 1958.Google Scholar
Eckerman, C. 2016: ‘Freedom and slavery in Vergil's Eclogue 1’, Wiener Studien 129: 257–80.10.1553/wst129s257CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fantuzzi, M. and Papanghelis, T. (eds) 2006: Brill's Companion to Greek and Latin Pastoral, Leiden.10.1163/9789047408536CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farrell, J. 2002: ‘Greek lives and Roman careers in the Classical vita tradition’, in Cheney, P. and de Armas, F. A. (eds), European Literary Careers: The Author from Antiquity to the Renaissance, Toronto, 2445.Google Scholar
Feeney, D. C. 1994: ‘Si licet et fas est: Ovid's Fasti and the problem of free speech under the Principate’, in Powell, A. (ed.), Roman Poetry and Propaganda in the Age of Augustus, Bristol, 125.Google Scholar
Gagé, J. 1955: Apollon romain, Paris.Google Scholar
Gale, M. R. 2013: ‘Virgil's Caesar: intertextuality and ideology’, in Farrell, J. and Nelis, D. P. (eds), Augustan Poetry and the Roman Republic, Oxford, 278–96.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199587223.003.0015CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galinsky, K. 1996: Augustan Culture. An Interpretive Introduction, Princeton, NJ.Google Scholar
Galinsky, K. 2006: ‘Vergil's uses of libertas: texts and contexts’, Vergilius 52, 319.Google Scholar
Geue, T. 2013: ‘Princeps “avant la lettre”: the foundation of Augustus in pre-Augustan poetry’, in Labate, M. and Rosati, G. (eds.) La costruzione de mito augusteo, Heidelberg, 4967.Google Scholar
Geue, T. 2019: Author Unknown: The Power of Anonymity in Ancient Rome, Cambridge, MA.10.2307/j.ctvnwc025CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gowers, E. 2012: Horace: Satires Book I, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Gradel, I. 2002: Emperor Worship and Roman Religion, Oxford.Google Scholar
Grisart, A. 1966: ‘Tityre et son dieu: des identifications nouvelles’, Les Études Classiques 34, 115–42.Google Scholar
Gurval, R. A. 1995: Actium and Augustus: The Politics and Emotions of Civil War, Ann Arbor, MI.10.3998/mpub.14819CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardie, P. R. 2006: ‘Culture and historical narratives in Virgil's Eclogues and Lucretius’, in Fantuzzi and Papanghelis 2006, 275300.Google Scholar
Harrison, S. J. 2007: Generic Enrichment in Vergil and Horace, Oxford.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199203581.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hellegouarch, J. 1972: Le vocabulaire latin des relations et des parties politiques sous la République, Paris.Google Scholar
Henderson, J. 1994: ‘On getting rid of kings: Horace, Satire 1.7’, Classical Quarterly 44, 146–70.10.1017/S0009838800017274CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hunter, R. 2001: ‘Virgil and Theocritus: a note on the reception of the Encomium to Ptolemy Philadelphus’, Seminari Romani di cultura greca 4, 159–63.Google Scholar
Jameson, F. 1971: Marxism and Form, Princeton, NJ.Google Scholar
Karakasis, E. 2011: Song Exchange in Roman Pastoral, Berlin and New York.10.1515/9783110227079CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kennedy, D. F. 1992: ‘“Augustan” and “anti-Augustan”: reflections on terms of reference’, in Powell, A. (ed.), Roman Poetry and Propaganda in the Age of Augustus, London, 2658.Google Scholar
Klein, R. 1969: Prinzipat und Freiheit, Darmstadt.Google Scholar
Koenen, L. 1993: ‘The Ptolemaic king as a religious figure’, in Bulloch, A. W., Gruen, E. S., Long, A. A. and Stewart, A. (eds), Images and Ideologies: Self-Definition in the Hellenistic World, Berkeley and Los Angeles, 25115.Google Scholar
Koortbojian, M. 2013: The Divinization of Caesar and Augustus: Precedents, Consequences, Implications, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Korenjak, M. 2003: ‘Tityri sub persona: Der antike Biographismus und die bukolische Tradition’, Antike und Abendland 49: 5879.10.1515/9783110176070.58CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kronenberg, L. 2016: ‘Epicurean pastoral: Daphnis as an allegory for Lucretius in Vergil's Eclogues’, Vergilius 62, 2556.Google Scholar
Laird, A. 2009: ‘Virgil: reception and the myth of biography’, CentoPagine 3: 19.Google Scholar
La Rocca, E. 1992: ‘Theoi epiphaneis: linguaggio figurativo e culto dinastico da Antioco IV ad Augusto’, Studi italiani di filologia classica 10: 630–78.Google Scholar
Leach, E. W. 1974: Vergil's Eclogues: Landscapes of Experience, Ithaca, NY.Google Scholar
Leclercq, R. 1996: Le divin loisir, Brussels.Google Scholar
Liegle, J. 1943: ‘Die Tityrusekloge’, Hermes 78, 209–31.Google Scholar
Lowrie, M. 2009: Writing, Performance, and Authority in Augustan Rome, Oxford.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199545674.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mac Góráin, F. 2020: ‘Introduction. Dionysus and Rome: accommodation and resistance’, in Mac Góráin, F. (ed.), Dionysus and Rome. Religion and Literature, Berlin and New York, 137.Google Scholar
Manuwald, G. 2007: Cicero, Philippics 3–9. Edited with Introduction, Translation and Commentary (2 vols), Berlin and New York.Google Scholar
Mayer, R. 1983: ‘Missing persons in the Eclogues’, Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies 30, 1730.10.1111/j.2041-5370.1983.tb00431.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meban, D. 2009: ‘Virgil's Eclogues and social memory’, American Journal of Philology 130, 99130.10.1353/ajp.0.0035CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, J. F. 2009: Apollo, Augustus and the Poets, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Nisbet, R. G. M. 1978: ‘Virgil's Fourth Eclogue: easterners and westerners’, Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies 25, 5978, reprinted in K. Volk (ed.), Oxford Readings in Classical Studies: Vergil's Eclogues, Oxford, 155–87.10.1111/j.2041-5370.1978.tb00385.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norden, E. 1924: Die Geburt des Kindes, Darmstadt.Google Scholar
Osgood, J. 2006: Caesar's Legacy: Civil War and the Emergence of the Roman Empire, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Pandey, N. 2018: The Poetics of Power in Augustan Rome, Cambridge.10.1017/9781108525152CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papanghelis, T. 2006: ‘Friends, foes, frames and fragments: textuality in Virgil's Eclogues’, in Fantuzzi and Papanghelis 2006, 369402.Google Scholar
Pelling, C. 1988: Plutarch: Life of Antony, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Perkell, C. G. 2001: ‘Vergil reading his twentieth-century readers: a study of Eclogue 9’, Vergilius 47, 6488.Google Scholar
Perutelli, A. 1995: ‘Bucolics’, in Horsfall, N. (ed.) A Companion to the Study of Virgil, Leiden, 2762.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. 2012: On the People's Terms: A Republican Theory and Model of Democracy, Cambridge.10.1017/CBO9781139017428CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pollini, J. 1990: ‘Man or god: divine assimilation and imitation in the late Republic and early Principate’, in Raaflaub, K. A. and Toher, M. (eds), Between Republic and Empire: Interpretations of Augustus and his Principate, Berkeley and Los Angeles, 334–63.10.1525/9780520914513-016CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Price, S. R. F. 1984: ‘Gods and emperors: the Greek language of the Roman imperial cult’, Journal of Hellenic Studies 104, 7995.10.2307/630281CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ricoeur, P. 1965: De l'interprétation: Essai sur Freud, Paris.Google Scholar
Rose, H. J. 1942: The Eclogues of Virgil, Berkeley and Los Angeles.10.1525/9780520339330CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rundin, J. 2003: ‘The Epicurean morality of Vergil's Bucolics’, Classical World 96, 159–76.10.2307/4352735CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scholl, W. 2014: Der Daphnis-Mythos und seine Entwicklung. Von den Anfängen bis zu Vergils vierter Ekloge, Hildesheim.Google Scholar
Scott, K. 1933: ‘The political propaganda of 44–30 BC’, Memoirs of the American Academy in Rome 11, 749.10.2307/4238573CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skinner, Q. 1998: Liberty before Liberalism, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Snijder, H. 2010: ‘The cosmology of Octavian's divine birth in Vergil's fourth Eclogue’, in Deroux, C. (ed.), Studies in Latin Literature and Roman History XV, Brussels, 178–95.Google Scholar
Stöckinger, M. 2016: Vergils Gaben: Materialität, Reziprozität und Poetik in den Eklogen und der Aeneis, Heidelberg.Google Scholar
Tatum, J. 2020: ‘“A great and arduous struggle”: Mark Antony and the rhetoric of libertas in 44–43 BC’, in Balmaceda, C. (ed.), Libertas and Res Publica in the Roman Republic, Leiden, 189215.Google Scholar
Weinstock, S. 1971: Divus Julius, Oxford.Google Scholar
Wimmel, W. 1998: ‘Vergils Tityrus und der perusinische Konflikt. Zum Verständnis der 1. Ecloge’, Rheinisches Museum für Philologie 141, 348–61.Google Scholar
Wirszubski, C. 1950: Libertas as a Political Idea at Rome during the Late Republic and the Early Empire, Oxford.Google Scholar
Wright, J. R. G. 1983: ‘Virgil's pastoral programme: Theocritus, Callimachus and Eclogue 1’, Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society 29, 107–60.10.1017/S0068673500004557CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zanker, P. 1988: The Power of Images in the Age of Augustus, Ann Arbor, MI.10.3998/mpub.12362CrossRefGoogle Scholar