Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-r5zm4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-14T22:33:15.244Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Framing conservation: ‘biodiversity’ and the values embedded in scientific language

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 August 2020

Kevin C Elliott*
Affiliation:
Lyman Briggs College, Department of Fisheries and Wildlife, Department of Philosophy, Michigan State University, 35E Holmes Hall, 919 E Shaw Lane, East Lansing, MI48825, USA
*
Author for correspondence: Professor Kevin C Elliott, Email: kce@msu.edu
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Summary

The global loss of biodiversity is one of the most important challenges facing humanity, and a multi-faceted strategy is needed to address the size and complexity of this problem. This paper draws on scholarship from the philosophy of science and environmental ethics to help address one aspect of this challenge: namely, the question of how to frame biodiversity loss in a compelling manner. The paper shows that the concept of biodiversity, like many scientific concepts, is value-laden in the sense that it tends to support some ethical or social values over others. Specifically, in comparison with other potential concepts, the biodiversity concept is tied more closely to the notion that nature has intrinsic value than to the idea that nature is valuable instrumentally or relationally. Thus, alternative concepts could prove helpful for communicating about biodiversity loss with those who emphasize different value systems. The paper briefly discusses five concepts that illustrate the potential for using different concepts in different contexts. Going forward, conservationists would do well to recognize the values embedded in their language choices and work with social scientists to develop a suite of concepts that can motivate the broadest swath of people to promote conservation.

Type
Research Paper
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Foundation for Environmental Conservation

Introduction

The recent publication of the Global Assessment Report from the Intergovernmental Science-Policy Platform on Biodiversity and Ecosystem Services (IPBES) has highlighted the loss of biodiversity as one of the grand challenges facing humanity (see Diaz et al. Reference Díaz, Settele, Brondízio, Ngo, Guèze and Agard2020). Unfortunately, current efforts have not been sufficient to stem the decline in biodiversity (Crist Reference Crist2019). The magnitude of this challenge merits a wide variety of efforts to address the problem. Social psychologists have shown that one can potentially intervene on many different factors – including values, beliefs, norms, attitudes and behaviours – in order to promote conservation activities (Vaske & Manfredo Reference Vaske, Manfredo, Decker, Riley and Siemer2012). This paper focuses on one particular intervention point: namely, the concepts and terms used for framing the entire conservation enterprise. Although there are likely to be a variety of intervention points that are efficacious (e.g., see Rounsevell et al. Reference Rounsevell, Harfoot, Harrison, Newbold and Mace2020), it is important to think clearly about the overall framing of conservation efforts (Cox Reference Cox2007). This is especially important given the power of problem framing to influence policymaking. As Judith Layzer puts it, “The side that succeeds in crafting the authoritative problem definition has an enormous advantage because the way people think and talk about a policy problem determines which solutions they are likely to embrace” (Layzer Reference Layzer2016, p. 10; see also Nisbet & Mooney Reference Nisbet and Mooney2007).

Although biodiversity has been the central organizing concept in the field of conservation biology since its inception (Soulé Reference Soulé1985, Takacs Reference Takacs1996), critics have recently questioned its effectiveness in the policy domain (Escobar Reference Escobar1998, Dowie Reference Dowie2011, Santana Reference Santana, Casetta, Marques da Silva and Vecchia2019, Devictor & Meinard Reference Devictor and Meinard2020). A coalition of non-governmental organizations and research centres recently launched a ‘Biodiversity Revisited’ initiative that summarizes many of these worries with the following problem statement: “Biodiversity has not, broadly speaking, proven to be a compelling object for sufficient action to halt the degradation of the diversity of life on earth” (Wyborn et al. Reference Wyborn, Kalas and Rust2019, p. 5). Faced with this worry, it makes sense to explore the strengths and weaknesses of this concept in comparison with other potential concepts that could inform conservation activities. As environmental ethicist Bryan Norton has emphasized, “[A]ll of our categories, including biological categories, develop from the need to communicate and to act together” (Norton Reference Norton, Askins, Dreyer, Visgilio and Whitelaw2008, p. 13). This does not mean that scientific categories are entirely ‘socially constructed’ or divorced from reality, but it does suggest that we can critically evaluate our language choices to determine how well they enable us to achieve both our scientific and social goals. Building on Norton’s insight, this paper argues that conservation scientists and practitioners should recognize the values embedded in the concept of biodiversity and work with social scientists to develop a suite of concepts that can motivate the broadest swath of people to promote conservation. The argument is limited in scope; it focuses on a conceptual analysis of the biodiversity concept itself rather than on a psychological or sociological analysis of how people actually respond to it. Nevertheless, this sort of conceptual analysis can encourage further sensitivity among conservation practitioners to the potential strengths and weaknesses of different concepts and prompt additional research on this issue.

To provide the background for this argument, I provide a brief overview of philosophical scholarship on the ways in which scientific language can support or encourage particular ethical or social value frameworks. Building on this literature, I then examine how the concept of ‘biodiversity’ is conceptually linked more closely with some value systems than others. This raises the worry that it may be less effective than other concepts for motivating individuals who adhere to different value systems. In response to this concern, I go on to explore the possibility of augmenting the biodiversity concept with alternative concepts: life support systems, food security, sustainability, environmental justice and caring for nature. Although none of these concepts is perfect, together they illustrate the potential for developing a combination of concepts that communicate the importance of conservation to the widest possible array of stakeholders. Thus, by recognizing the values embedded in the concepts they employ, conservationists can do a better job of addressing the grand challenge of biodiversity loss by framing conservation activities in ways that are compelling to as many stakeholders as possible.

Values embedded in scientific language

Philosophers of science have recently emphasized a wide range of ways in which scientific research is ‘value-laden’, in the sense that scientists make numerous choices or judgements that are not settled by the available evidence, but that can support particular social or ethical values (Longino Reference Longino1990, Lacey Reference Lacey1999, Douglas Reference Douglas2009). For example, scientists have to decide what topics to study, what questions to ask about those topics, how to design their studies, what methods to use for collecting and analysing data, how to interpret ambiguous results and how to frame and conceptualize their findings (Elliott Reference Elliott2017a). When undertaking applied research that informs environmental decision-making, it is common that some research choices are more likely to generate results that support values like public and environmental health, whereas other choices are more likely to yield results that support different values, such as short-term economic growth.

Like many other elements of scientific practice, choices involving scientific language can be value-laden (Elliott Reference Elliott2009, Larson Reference Larson2011, Johns & DellaSala Reference Johns and DellaSala2017). First, scientists can end up supporting some values over others depending on how they frame the topics under investigation. For example, members of the public respond differently to climate change depending on whether it is framed as a matter of scientific uncertainty, unfair economic burden, religious morality or public accountability (Nisbet & Mooney Reference Nisbet and Mooney2007). Second, scientists often use terms that have metaphorical or otherwise value-laden connotations. For example, Brendon Larson (Reference Larson2011) argues that it is important to consider the metaphorical significance of terms like ‘invasive’, ‘alien’ or ‘exotic’ species, which may subtly encourage people to draw connections between biological issues involving these species and social issues such as military invasions or disputes over immigration. Similarly, John Dupré (Reference Dupré, Kincaid, Wylie and Dupré2007) has argued that when scientists take terms such as ‘rape’ that are used in human social contexts and apply those terms in biological contexts, they may import ethical or social connotations into those non-human contexts. Third, choices about how to define the terms or categories used in scientific research are often value-laden. For example, the increasing use of the concept of ‘wetlands’ in the second half of the twentieth century helped prompt limited conservation of these areas, but major political and legal disputes have arisen about how to define what counts as a wetland because there are competing interests (e.g., Rapanos v. United States 547 US 715 (2006)). During the George HW Bush presidency, his administration tried to shrink the number of lands classified as wetlands – thereby facilitating his campaign promise of ‘no net loss’ of wetlands – but this plan came under intense opposition from environmental groups (Elliott Reference Elliott, Bensaude-Vincent, Loeve, Nordmann and Schwarz2017b).

These choices about frames, terms and definitions can have major social, policy and ethical consequences when dealing with environmental issues (Elliott Reference Elliott2009). For example, they can influence the future course of research by drawing scientists’ attention to some problems and lessening their attention to other problems. Sheldon Krimsky (Reference Krimsky2000) has shown that developing a unifying concept such as ‘wetlands’ or ‘endocrine disruption’ or ‘climate change’ to describe a set of phenomena can be a powerful stimulus for promoting research efforts. Choices about language can also change the burdens of proof or the kinds of evidence required for taking action in response to environmental concerns, as illustrated by the Bush administration’s efforts to influence environmental policymaking by changing the definition of wetlands. Finally, choices about language can influence the extent to which policymakers and members of the public pay attention to environmental problems, as Nisbet and Mooney (Reference Nisbet and Mooney2007) have argued in the case of climate change. One way in which particular language choices can promote attention to environmental problems is by framing them in such a way that they connect or resonate with particular ethical theories, value frameworks or emotional attachments (Johns & DellaSala Reference Johns and DellaSala2017). The following sections of this paper focus on this issue in detail, showing how concepts such as ‘biodiversity’ are conceptually linked more closely with some value frameworks than others, thereby potentially communicating the importance of environmental conservation more effectively to some stakeholders than others.

‘Biodiversity’ and environmental ethics

Biodiversity is notoriously difficult to define (Takacs Reference Takacs1996, Holt Reference Holt2006), which contributes to both its strengths and its weaknesses. On the one hand, Georg Toepfer (Reference Toepfer, Casetta, Marques da Silva and Vecchia2019) argues that it is particularly useful because it is an ‘umbrella term’ that is vague enough and rich enough in its connotations to mediate between many different disciplines and discourses (see also Burch-Brown & Archer Reference Burch-Brown and Archer2017). On the other hand, Carlos Santana (Reference Santana2014) contends that the open-endedness of the biodiversity concept means that it is difficult to measure and that it does not clearly pick out the specific elements in nature that are valuable (see also Meinard et al. Reference Meinard, Coq, Schmid, Casetta, Marques da Silva and Vecchia2019). Another worry is that the slipperiness of the concept provides an opportunity for scientists to surreptitiously import their own values into policymaking. If biodiversity is assumed to be valuable and worthy of protection, but if scientists are the ones operationalizing the concept, then they end up with significant power to determine which elements of nature are prioritized for conservation (Morar et al. Reference Morar, Toadvine and Bohannan2015).

The goal in this paper is not to revisit these debates about the ambiguity of the biodiversity concept, but instead to explore its connections to major value frameworks used in environmental ethics. The upshot of this analysis is that the biodiversity concept has conceptual features that are likely to make it more effective for working with communities who attribute intrinsic value to nature than communities who approach nature with instrumental or relational value frameworks. Historically, the major value frameworks employed in the field of environmental ethics have focused on ‘instrumental value’ and ‘intrinsic value’ (Afeissa Reference Afeissa, Callicott and Frodeman2009). Instrumental value is the value that something has because of the ways in which it serves other interests. For example, biodiversity has instrumental value to humans insofar as it contributes to other things of value, such as economic benefits and ecosystem services. Building on this instrumental value, one can construct an ‘anthropocentric’ ethic that justifies concern for the environment because of the ways it serves human interests. During the final decades of the twentieth century, however, a number of figures challenged anthropocentric approaches to ethics as inadequate for addressing environmental problems. They argued that elements of the environment should be appreciated for their intrinsic value (i.e., the value that they have ‘in and of themselves’, independently of the ways they serve human interests; White Reference White1967, Routley Reference Routley1973, Rolston Reference Rolston1989). This notion that entities in the environment have intrinsic value provides the basis for ‘non-anthropocentric’ approaches to environmental ethics, which have roots in many sources, including Daoism, Hinduism, Buddhism and a variety of environmental writings.

Biodiversity clearly has value. As Toepfer puts it, “The impressive success of the concept ‘biodiversity’ in the last decades, in particular in the arena of politics, is in a large part due to its power to amalgamate facts and values: the fact that living beings show variety on every level of their existence, and the assumed values that are associated with this variety” (Reference Toepfer, Casetta, Marques da Silva and Vecchia2019, p. 341). Some philosophers have gone so far as to say that biodiversity should be defined primarily as a normative concept (Sarkar Reference Sarkar, Casetta, Marques da Silva and Vecchia2019). Taken to the extreme, this view would define biodiversity simply as whatever the field of conservation biology aims to protect (Sarkar Reference Sarkar2002). Thus, the concept of biodiversity is value-laden in at least two interrelated senses. First, as Toepfer emphasizes, it is a concept that incorporates both factual and normative elements. Second, it is conceptually tied more closely to some value systems than to others, thereby framing environmental discourse in ways that encourage some ways of thinking about nature over others.

Given that biodiversity has value, the deeper question is what kind of value it has and to which kinds of value systems it is most closely connected. The argument in this paper is that biodiversity has conceptual features that tie it particularly closely to the notion that nature has intrinsic value. The reason for this is that it refers primarily to entities in nature rather than to the usefulness of those entities or their relationships with humans. As noted in the previous paragraph, one can argue that biodiversity has other forms of value, but the concept itself does not explicitly draw attention to those other forms. Consider, for example, the classic definition of biodiversity in the Convention on Biological Diversity (CBD): “[T]he variability among living organisms from all sources including, inter alia, terrestrial, marine and other aquatic ecosystems and the ecological complexes of which they are part; this includes diversity within species, between species and of ecosystems” (CBD 1992). This definition focuses scientific and public attention on many elements of nature that merit conservation: genes, individuals, populations, species and ecosystems. However, it does not explicitly include the connections between humans and these elements of nature. Because it focuses solely on these entities and their differences rather than the ways they relate to human beings, the concept’s primary focus appears to be the intrinsic value of these entities.

Commentators on biodiversity have consistently affirmed this intrinsic value. For example, in his influential essay laying out much of the groundwork for the field of conservation biology, Michael Soulé explicitly stated that the most fundamental normative postulate of the field is that “Biotic diversity has intrinsic value, irrespective of its instrumental or utilitarian value” (Soulé Reference Soulé1985, p. 731, emphasis in original). Similarly, the first line of the Preamble to the CBD states that biological diversity has intrinsic value, and one of the five organizational values of the Society for Conservation Biology (SCB) is as follows: “There is intrinsic value in the natural diversity of organisms, the complexity of ecological systems, and the resilience created by evolutionary processes” (SCB 2011). A number of other legal and policy statements also affirm the intrinsic value of biodiversity or other aspects of nature (Vucetich et al. Reference Vucetich, Bruskotter and Nelson2015). And Georg Toepfer, who emphasizes how biodiversity brings together both facts and values, emphasizes that “the term maintains its strong non-instrumental ethical dimension: it expresses a non-anthropocentric value of plants and animals” (Toepfer Reference Toepfer, Casetta, Marques da Silva and Vecchia2019, p. 342).

Of course, as noted earlier, biodiversity can have intrinsic value while also having instrumental value for achieving other goals or purposes. For example, the Preamble to the CBD states that biodiversity also has “ecological, genetic, social, economic, scientific, educational, cultural, recreational, and aesthetic values.” However, the concept of biodiversity does not inherently bring these other values to light; one must draw attention to them and, in some cases, argue for them. To take one particularly noteworthy example of how these arguments can play out, the stability–diversity debate among ecologists explored the extent to which reductions in biodiversity are likely to generate instability in ecosystems, which in turn has important implications for human well-being (McCann Reference McCann2000). The huge amount of ink spilled over this debate illustrates how difficult it can be to take a concept like biodiversity and demonstrate the ways in which it has instrumental value (e.g., see Hooper et al. Reference Hooper, Chapin, Ewel, Hector, Inchausti and Lavorel2005, Hautier et al. Reference Hautier, Tilman, Isbell, Seabloom, Borer and Reich2015, Wang & Loreau Reference Wang and Loreau2016, De Boeck et al. Reference De Boeck, Bloor, Kreyling, Ransijn, Nijs, Jentsch and Zeiter2018). One might object that the tendency among ecologists to analyse biodiversity in a quantitative way could still promote instrumental perspectives that connect biodiversity with ecosystem services and human well-being (e.g., see Worm et al. Reference Worm, Barbier, Beaumont, Duffy, Folke and Halpern2006, Cardinale et al. Reference Cardinale, Duffy, Gonzalez, Hooper, Perrings and Venail2012, Sandifer et al. Reference Sandifer, Sutton-Grier and Ward2015). However, the tendency to analyse biodiversity in a highly quantitative way does not seem inherent to the concept itself; in many cases, biodiversity is analysed in very simple terms as a matter of the number of species present in a given location. Norton quotes biodiversity expert Thomas Lovejoy as stating that “the term is really supposed to mean diversity at all levels of organization. But the way it’s most often used is basically relating to species diversity” (Norton Reference Norton, Askins, Dreyer, Visgilio and Whitelaw2008, p. 18). Norton emphasizes that this simple approach to the concept is especially prominent when it is used in popular, non-scientific contexts.

A promising new approach to environmental ethics is to focus on ‘relational values’, which have the potential to transcend conflicts over whether nature has intrinsic value or only instrumental value. As the term suggests, relational values are grounded in the relationships between humans and nature. For example, relational values can stem from the ways in which nature contributes to the identity of a person or a community of people, or they can stem from the ways in which being in nature strengthens the ties between people (Chan et al. Reference Chan, Balvanera, Benessaiah, Chapman, Díaz and Gómez-Baggethun2016). Proponents of the relational value framework argue that it effectively captures the ways in which many people value nature; in other words, they view nature neither as a resource to be exploited nor as something that has value completely independently of its connections with human life. An important strength of this approach is that it can encompass traditional Western philosophies while creating more space for contemporary feminist approaches, Eastern philosophies and Indigenous worldviews. Thus, relational values have the potential to capture the lived experiences of many different people and their connections with nature. Although it might seem like relational values perpetuate a dualistic distinction between humans and nature, with humans being treated as superior, this is not necessarily the case. Relational values could emphasize the interconnections between all living things while starting from the lived experiences of humans in nature.

Just as biodiversity can be justified for its instrumental value, it can be defended based on relational values as well. For example, the recent report from IPBES includes the concept of ‘nature’s contributions to people’ (NCP), which explores the many ways in which biodiversity contributes to people’s quality of life (Diaz et al. Reference Díaz, Pascual, Stenseke, Martín-López, Watson and Molnár2018). These contributions can include ecosystem services such as the provision of food, water and materials, but they can also involve social relationships, opportunities for recreation or inspiration and spiritual experiences. An advantage of the NCP framework is that it can capture local, context-specific ways in which people relate to biodiversity that are sometimes missed by analyses drawn from the natural sciences and economics (Diaz et al. Reference Díaz, Pascual, Stenseke, Martín-López, Watson and Molnár2018). Stephen Kellert has documented a host of ways in which human beings relate to the natural world, including “attraction and curiosity, affection and kinship, knowledge and understanding, mastery and control, moral and spiritual relation, even fear of and aversion to the natural world’’ (Kellert Reference Kellert, Moore and Nelson2010, p. 375). Of course, there are tensions among these ways of relating, and some may be ethically preferable to others, but they illustrate the multifaceted ways in which different stakeholders connect with nature.

Nevertheless, while it is possible to identify ways in which the protection of biodiversity can be supported based on relational values, the biodiversity concept itself does not capture relational connections between humans and nature; one must deliberately draw attention to these connections. This is because the concept of biodiversity describes elements of nature (such as genes, individuals, populations or species) and the differences between them (i.e., diversity) rather than the relationships between humans and nature. In fact, contemporary critics of traditional approaches to biodiversity conservation argue that biodiversity has too often been conceptualized as being in conflict with human activities (Kareiva et al. Reference Kareiva, Marvier and Lalasz2012). For example, journalist Mark Dowie (Reference Dowie2011) contends that conservation groups have frequently pushed Indigenous peoples off their historic lands because those groups felt it was easier to achieve their goal of preserving biodiversity in the absence of human interference. Dowie cites a speech by Martin Saning’o, a Maasai leader from Tanzania who addressed the Third Congress of the World Conservation Union in 2004, claiming that “in the interest of a relatively new vogue in conservation called ‘biodiversity’ … more than one hundred thousand Maasai pastoralists have been displaced from their traditional homeland’’ (Dowie Reference Dowie2011, p. xv). Saning’o asserted that “‘We [the Maasai] were the original conservationists,’ but ‘now you [conservationists focused on biodiversity] have made us enemies of conservation’” (Dowie Reference Dowie2011, p. xv).

In sum, although the biodiversity concept can be employed in conjunction with multiple approaches to environmental ethics, the concept itself focuses on the intrinsic value of nature. Because the concept does not draw explicit connections between humans and nature, arguments are needed to establish the instrumental and relational value of biodiversity. Of course, this does not mean that biodiversity fails to have these additional forms of value; they are just not immediately captured by the concept itself. Thus, from the perspective of the philosophy of science, the concept of biodiversity is ‘value-laden’ insofar as it is conceptually tied more closely to some ways of approaching environmental ethics than others. This embedding of values within the biodiversity concept is significant because some people can appreciate instrumental or relational approaches to valuing nature more than intrinsic approaches. Thus, if conservationists want to frame their efforts in ways that will motivate as many different stakeholders as possible, they should work with social scientists to explore whether other concepts could be effectively employed alongside or in place of biodiversity.

Other ways of framing conservation

The notion that the biodiversity concept could be replaced or augmented with other concepts is not new. For example, Norton has argued that different definitions of biodiversity could be used in the scientific and political spheres, and he has suggested that other productive terms should be investigated as well: “Rather than clinging to definitions that don’t work, we can investigate which terms and linguistic forms are conducive to communication and cooperative behavior within the community seeking to protect the wonders of the biologically diverse world” (Norton Reference Norton, Askins, Dreyer, Visgilio and Whitelaw2008, p. 19). Similarly, building on the work of Sahotra Sarkar (Reference Sarkar2002), Carlos Santana has argued that conservation science operates via a series of representations: “estimator surrogate → true surrogate → biodiversity → biological value” (Santana Reference Santana2014, p. 762). In other words, when conservationists focus on particular entities, they may be useful primarily because they represent something else that is of more fundamental importance. According to figures such as Sarkar and Santana, biodiversity is a general concept that is used to represent the many different biological entities and processes that are valuable in nature. Thus, if ‘biodiversity’ does not turn out to be the best way to refer to those valuable things, we can and should pursue alternative terms and concepts for representing them (Santana Reference Santana, Casetta, Marques da Silva and Vecchia2019). The novel contribution of this paper is to focus specifically on exploring how alternative terms and concepts relate to the major value frameworks employed in environmental ethics so that conservationists can think more deeply about the potential ramifications for conservation of making different language choices.

Before proceeding to consider the ethical ramifications of alternative concepts, however, it is important to address two potential objections to pursuing a project such as this one. First, one might think it would be more effective (and perhaps more ethically satisfactory) to convince people to value nature intrinsically rather than shifting to terms that are conceptually tied to instrumental and relational value systems (e.g., see Crist Reference Crist2019). This objection might be supported by evidence from social psychology, which indicates that people are more likely to engage in pro-social and environmentally friendly behaviour when they are motivated by intrinsic values (e.g., see Crompton Reference Crompton2011, Sheldon et al. Reference Sheldon, Nichols and Kasser2011, Cetas & Yasué Reference Cetas and Yasué2017). However, this research should be interpreted carefully. These studies do not define intrinsic values in exactly the same way that environmental ethicists do; they tend to define these values as “those pursuits that are generally congruent with the psychological needs for relatedness, autonomy, and competence proposed by self-determination theory” (Grouzet et al. Reference Grouzet, Kasser, Ahuvia, Dols, Kim and Lau2005, p. 801). Under this definition, intrinsic values include things such as community feeling, self-acceptance and physical health, as opposed to extrinsic values such as money or popularity (Grouzet et al. Reference Grouzet, Kasser, Ahuvia, Dols, Kim and Lau2005, p. 801). Thus, this research does not establish that the intrinsic values discussed in this paper are more motivationally efficacious than all instrumental or relational values. Rather, it shows that community-orientated instrumental and relational values, as well as what environmental ethicists call intrinsic values, are more efficacious than shallow, self-centred instrumental and relational values. This conclusion is supported by the empirical evidence that many Indigenous cultures have held relational value frameworks and have conserved significant amounts of biodiversity for millennia (Dowie Reference Dowie2011, Chan et al. Reference Chan, Balvanera, Benessaiah, Chapman, Díaz and Gómez-Baggethun2016). Thus, it would be premature to conclude that concepts associated with intrinsic value systems (in the sense used by environmental ethicists) will typically be more motivationally efficacious (or ethically superior) in comparison with other concepts. Given the ambiguity of the available evidence and the complexity of shifting people to different value orientations, it makes sense to engage in further social science research to determine what suite of concepts is likely to be most effective at promoting biodiversity conservation in response to the range of values that people currently hold.

Another objection is that it might seem manipulative for conservationists to choose terms and concepts with the express goal of convincing people to engage in conservation activities. By employing this approach, one might think conservation scientists fall into a stance of ‘stealth issue advocacy’ that is inappropriate for scientific researchers (Pielke Reference Pielke2007). This is an important concern, but it is not a compelling reason to avoid using value-laden language designed to promote conservation. Given that conservation biology is a highly policy-relevant discipline, it is doubtful that any language employed in this field could be completely value-neutral; any terms and concepts used in the public sphere are likely to have some connotations, either positive or negative (Elliott Reference Elliott2017a). Philosophers of science have argued that scientists should respond to the inevitability of these value-laden choices both by making the most responsible choices they can and by trying to be transparent about them (Kourany Reference Kourany2010, Elliott Reference Elliott2018, Brown Reference Brown2020). With this advice in mind, and given the importance of biodiversity conservation to the future well-being of humanity and all other living things, there appear to be good ethical reasons for scientists to make value-laden choices in ways that promote conservation rather than detracting from it (Cox Reference Cox2007). It is also noteworthy that the use of multiple terms and concepts in the context of biodiversity conservation could actually be a productive way to promote greater transparency among information recipients by helping them to recognize the value-laden connotations and nuances of different terms (McKaughan & Elliott Reference McKaughan and Elliott2013). Focusing on the single concept of biodiversity could actually detract from transparency because of its vagueness; different groups could be using the same term without realizing that they have very different value orientations and intentions (Meinard et al. Reference Meinard, Coq, Schmid, Casetta, Marques da Silva and Vecchia2019).

Assuming, then, that it makes sense to explore alternative language choices, the remainder of this section briefly explores the strengths and weaknesses of five terms that could be used either as additions or as alternatives to the biodiversity concept: life support systems, sustainability, food security, environmental justice and care for nature. The section focuses especially on how these concepts relate to intrinsic, instrumental and relational value frameworks. This group of terms is intended neither to be exclusive nor exhaustive. Rather, it provides a sampling of terms with different strengths and weaknesses in relation to the major value frameworks. For example, life support systems and sustainability resemble biodiversity in that they are somewhat vague umbrella terms, but they have a stronger instrumental and relational focus than biodiversity does. The concept of food security also has very strong instrumental and relational connotations, but it has a much narrower focus. The concept of environmental justice is another term with a narrower focus, and it illustrates how conservation can be conceptualized in ways that resonate with broader social movements. Finally, the concept of respect for nature illustrates that not all alternatives to the biodiversity concept must have a strong instrumental focus; respect for nature bridges relational and intrinsic value systems. Taken together, these terms exemplify major avenues open to conservationists interested in exploring linguistic choices that resonate with different value frameworks.

Life support systems

The concept of life support systems has played an important role in major international conservation documents. For example, the 1980 World Conservation Strategy focused on three major principles: protection of Earth’s life support systems, protection of biodiversity and sustainable use of natural resources (IUCN et al. 1980). The Agenda 21 document released by the 1992 Earth Summit in Rio de Janeiro also referred to Earth’s life support systems. The United Nations Educational, Cultural, and Scientific Organization (UNESCO) has a project called the Encyclopedia of Life Support Systems (UNESCO-EOLSS), which provides the following definition of this concept:

A life support system is any natural or human-engineered (constructed or made) system that furthers the life of the biosphere in a sustainable fashion. The fundamental attribute of life support systems is that together they provide all of the sustainable needs required for continuance of life. These needs go far beyond biological requirements. Thus life support systems encompass natural environmental systems as well as ancillary social systems required to foster societal harmony, safety, nutrition, medical care, economic standards, and the development of new technology. The one common thread in all of these systems is that they operate in partnership with the conservation of global natural resources. (UNESCO-EOLSS 2020)

On the one hand, an important strength of the ‘life support system’ concept is that it explicitly highlights the relationships between humans (and other living things) and the broader environmental context in which they find themselves. In contrast to the concept of biodiversity, the importance of maintaining life support systems is readily apparent because it refers to something (life) that is almost universally valued. If one cares about human life (or life in general), it is obviously important to maintain the systems that support life. The UNESCO-EOLSS project explicitly draws comparisons to the life support systems that function in the intensive care units of hospitals, which facilitates exploring how other themes and concepts from the healthcare context could be applied to environmental conservation (e.g., see Wilson & Law Reference Wilson and Law2016). Thus, the use of this concept can highlight the ways in which the well-being of all living things, including humans, depends on conservation, just as human well-being depends on medical care. On the other hand, a disadvantage of the concept is that it has the potential to draw people’s attention to only one way in which humans relate to nature: namely, obtaining what is needed for our survival. Thus, talking about life support systems does little to highlight the range of spiritual, aesthetic and cultural ways in which human beings relate to nature.

Sustainability

Like the notion of life support systems, the concept of ‘sustainability’ or ‘sustainable development’ has played a major role in international documents related to conservation, and sustainability has been far more widely discussed than life support systems in recent years. Thus, it has the advantage of being widely recognized not only in the environmental community, but throughout society. For example, the concept of sustainability is already widely discussed in the business world (Svensson et al. Reference Svensson, Høgevold, Ferro, Varela, Padin and Wagner2016), which makes it a promising lever for influencing corporate decision-making. In addition, sustainability cuts across all aspects of social life, including not only the provision of basic needs such as food production, but also wider economic and cultural systems. The concept of sustainability clearly links the environment with human well-being, both now and in the future.

Unfortunately, the concept of sustainability has been so widely adopted and has so many different potential meanings and definitions that it has the potential to become vacuous (Faber et al. Reference Faber, Jorna and van Engelen2005, Glavic & Lukman Reference Glavic and Lukman2007, Thompson Reference Thompson2007). As Vucetich and Nelson put it, “[S]ustainability could mean anything from ‘exploit as much as desired without infringing on the future ability to exploit as much as desired’ to ‘exploit as little as necessary to maintain a meaningful life’” (Vucetich & Nelson Reference Vucetich and Nelson2010, p. 539). Thus, different stakeholder groups are likely to talk past each other when discussing sustainability (Peterson et al. Reference Peterson, Peterson and Peterson2005). Whereas it is relatively clear when discussing the preservation of biodiversity that the focus is on maintaining species and ecosystems, business leaders who discuss sustainability could be focused primarily on long-term economic viability and social responsibility rather than environmental conservation (Svensson et al. Reference Svensson, Høgevold, Ferro, Varela, Padin and Wagner2016). Therefore, although the concept of sustainability could prove very valuable in some contexts, it might not work well as a complete replacement for the concept of biodiversity.

Food security

Another concept that immediately highlights the relationships between humans and nature is ‘food security’. In the course of his discussion of Indigenous groups and their ambivalent or hostile attitude towards the concept of biodiversity, Dowie (Reference Dowie2011) suggests that they are much more likely to resonate with concepts that view nature as being intertwined with human well-being, including as a source of food. He points out that concepts such as ‘wild’, ‘wilderness’ and ‘biodiversity’ – all of which tend to distinguish humans from nature – do not even make sense in many Indigenous cultures, as illustrated by the perspective of a Khomani hunter who said, “The Kalahari is like a big farmyard … It is not wilderness to us” (Dowie Reference Dowie2011, p. 19). Indeed, the O’odham Native American tribe’s word for wilderness is related to their terms for health, wholeness and livelihood, and the closest approximation for the word ‘biodiversity’ among the Yupik people of Alaska is their word for ‘food’ (Dowie Reference Dowie2011, p. 19). Given the discussion of relational values in the ‘“Biodiversity” and environmental ethics’ section above, it is noteworthy that terms such as ‘livelihood’, ‘food’, ‘health’ and ‘wholeness’ all foster more or less explicit links between human and environmental well-being. Dowie argues that many Western conservation organizations have gone astray when working in other parts of the world because they have not understood the ways in which concerns for food security and other basic human needs have fostered effective environmental conservation in local communities for centuries.

Nevertheless, as with the concept of life support systems, the concept of food security focuses only on a limited range of ways in which humans relate to nature. It would be a mistake to think that people around the world care about the environment only because of the ways in which it supplies basic needs, such as food. Especially in wealthy Western societies, most people’s access to food is so disconnected from the natural systems that produce it that they may not appreciate the importance of protecting the environment for the sake of ensuring adequate food production. In fact, contemporary industrial agricultural systems are themselves major threats to conservation (Thompson Reference Thompson2017). Thus, food security could work very effectively when there are clear connections between biodiversity protection and the food supply, but it might not work well as a general replacement for the biodiversity concept.

Environmental justice

In recent years, the concept of environmental justice has garnered a great deal of attention (e.g., see Shrader-Frechette Reference Shrader-Frechette2002, Mohai et al. Reference Mohai, Pellow and Roberts2009, Schlosberg Reference Schlosberg2009). Robert Bullard defines environmental justice as the notion that “all people and communities are entitled to equal protection of environmental and public health laws and regulations” (Bullard Reference Bullard1996, p. 493, emphasis in original). The current focus on environmental justice arose largely because of a growing realization in the 1980s that people of colour in the USA faced disproportionate risks from landfills, incinerators and other sources of pollution (Chavis & Lee Reference Chavis and Lee1987, Bullard Reference Bullard2000). Since then, the environmental justice movement has broadened to address global issues as well, including the transfer of waste from the Global North to the Global South, as well as the global injustices associated with climate change (Mohai et al. Reference Mohai, Pellow and Roberts2009). The concept of environmental justice can be used to capture many of the same concerns as the concept of biodiversity because biodiversity loss often disproportionately impacts poor, marginalized and Indigenous communities around the world; they are often the most dependent on environmental resources for obtaining food, shelter, fibre and other basic needs.

A benefit of this concept is that justice is one of the most important ethical values in most societies. Speaking in terms of justice demonstrates that environmental issues are central to human well-being and not merely peripheral ‘side issues’. It also brings attention to the concerns of historically marginalized groups and helps to correct for a history in which environmental issues were too often framed in terms of the interests of relatively privileged groups who wanted to conserve nature primarily for recreational purposes (Shrader-Frechette Reference Shrader-Frechette2002). During a time of global protests against racial injustice, it is advisable from both an ethical and a pragmatic perspective to draw connections between environmental injustices and the many other forms of injustice in society. However, a potential weakness of this concept is that there are likely to be a variety of cases in which biodiversity losses are not clearly tied to environmental injustice. In fact, disadvantaged groups might face pressures in the short term to use natural resources in ways that are not sustainable or that threaten species populations (e.g., see Rolston Reference Rolston1998). In addition, it can be difficult to establish the existence of disproportionate risks for different groups of people, which can make it more difficult to document environmental injustice than to demonstrate the loss of biodiversity. One potential way to alleviate these weaknesses is to extend the concept of environmental injustice in a non-anthropocentric direction and to identify injustices in the ways humans relate to other living beings.

Caring for nature

Another alternative to focusing on the conservation of biodiversity is to encourage ‘caring for nature’. Whereas most of the other concepts discussed in this section emphasize the ways in which the environment can benefit humans, this concept reverses the focus and considers how humans appreciate and desire to benefit the environment. ‘Care for nature’ can involve feelings of awe, wonder, love, emotional closeness, interconnectedness and responsibility towards the environment (Perkins Reference Perkins2010). It is also often associated with the ascription of intrinsic value to nature (Rolston Reference Rolston2006, Perkins Reference Perkins2010). Research suggests that developing an attitude of care towards elements of nature, such as a charismatic species, can make people more willing to take action on behalf of the things they care about (Skibins & Powell Reference Skibins and Powell2013).

An advantage of the ‘caring for nature’ concept is that it resonates with the relational ways in which many people, including many Indigenous cultures, connect with nature (Chan et al. Reference Chan, Balvanera, Benessaiah, Chapman, Díaz and Gómez-Baggethun2016, Diaz et al. Reference Díaz, Pascual, Stenseke, Martín-López, Watson and Molnár2018). Whereas many of the other concepts discussed in this paper take the human-focused perspective that is typical of Western ethics, the notion of caring for nature has the potential to resonate with a broader array of worldviews. Nevertheless, the idea of caring for nature also has weaknesses. Those who do not have a significant emotional connection with nature are likely to have difficulty resonating with it. In addition, like the concept of sustainability, it is sufficiently vague that it might generate some conservation-related activities while leaving others neglected, or it could be used as a cover for activities that do not actually preserve biodiversity. For example, Skibins and Powell (Reference Skibins and Powell2013) found that visiting a zoo could increase people’s level of care for particular species. That feeling of care translated into a willingness to take action on behalf of those species, but it did not translate into a willingness to take action on behalf of biodiversity in general. Thus, the notion of caring for nature might not work well as a complete replacement for the biodiversity concept, but it could be a more appropriate concept for communicating with those who focus on relational values in nature.

The upshot

A brief conceptual analysis like this one is only a starting point for investigating different conceptual schemes. Further social scientific analyses are needed to determine how these terms influence people’s attitudes and motivations in different contexts. Nevertheless, this analysis suggests some promising ways in which different terms could augment or replace discussions of biodiversity in specific settings. For example, concepts such as life support systems or sustainability might be especially useful as a replacement for the biodiversity concept in settings where there is little appreciation for the intrinsic value of nature. Similarly, when conservationists are working with groups that emphasize relational value systems and that have become suspicious of Western conservation efforts focused on biodiversity (see Dowie Reference Dowie2011), terms such as food security and care for nature might prove particularly valuable. And when social movements arise around specific issues (e.g., racial justice, healthcare or worker rights), conservationists should be ready to employ concepts such as environmental justice that highlight potential connections between conservation and these other pressing issues. Conservation scientists and practitioners should not be afraid to explore different conceptual schemes; rather, they should look for opportunities to employ concepts that reach the widest possible array of stakeholders.

Conclusion

The global loss of biodiversity is one of the most important challenges facing humanity. A wide variety of efforts are needed to address this problem. One step that conservationists can take is to make sure they are framing biodiversity loss in ways that communicate effectively to as many stakeholders as possible. This paper has argued that the concept of biodiversity may have limitations in this regard because of its strong conceptual ties to the intrinsic value of nature. Thus, conservation scientists and practitioners should work in a collaborative manner to develop a suite of concepts that can help reach people who approach nature with alternative value frameworks. As a starting point for this task, the paper briefly analysed five alternative concepts that illustrate some of the major avenues open to conservationists. For example, the concepts of life support systems and sustainability are broad concepts that have many similarities with the biodiversity concept, but they are more closely tied to instrumental and relational ways of valuing nature. Other concepts, such as food security and environmental justice, have a somewhat more narrow focus, but they could be particularly effective for motivating some aspects of biodiversity protection. The concept of caring for nature illustrates that one can employ terms that connect with alternative value systems while still emphasizing nature’s intrinsic value. By attending to the value-laden features of the concepts they employ and the stakeholders with whom they communicate, conservationists can do a better job of framing biodiversity protection in ways that are compelling to people who hold different value orientations. This is a worthy effort, given the magnitude and significance of the problem they are working to address.

Acknowledgements

I am very grateful to the organizers of the Biodiversity Revisited initiative for inviting me to participate in their project, which helped me generate and hone many of the ideas in this paper. I am also thankful for the valuable feedback that Carina Wyborn and three excellent reviewers provided on previous versions of this manuscript.

Financial support

None.

Conflict of interest

None.

Ethical standards

None.

References

Afeissa, H-S (2009) Intrinsic and instrumental value. In: Encyclopedia of Environmental Ethics and Philosophy, eds Callicott, J, Frodeman, R (pp. 528531). Farmington Hills, MI, USA: Macmillan Reference USA.Google Scholar
Brown, M (2020) Science and Moral Imagination: A New Ideal for Values in Science. Pittsburgh, PA, USA: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Bullard, RD (1996) Environmental justice: it’s more than waste facility siting. Social Science Quarterly 77: 493499.Google Scholar
Bullard, RD (2000) Dumping in Dixie: Race, Class, and Environmental Quality, 3rd edn. Boulder, CO, USA: Westview.Google Scholar
Burch-Brown, J, Archer, A (2017) In defence of biodiversity. Biology & Philosophy 32: 969997.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cardinale, B, Duffy, J, Gonzalez, A, Hooper, D, Perrings, C, Venail, P et al. 2012. Biodiversity loss and its impact on humanity. Nature 486: 5967.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
CBD (1992) Convention on Biological Diversity. Rio de Janeiro, Brazil: United Nations.Google Scholar
Cetas, ER, Yasué, M (2017) A systematic review of motivational values and conservation success in and around protected areas. Conservation Biology 31: 203212.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chan, KM, Balvanera, P, Benessaiah, K, Chapman, M, Díaz, S, Gómez-Baggethun, E et al. (2016) Opinion: Why protect nature? Rethinking values and the environment. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 113: 1462–1465.Google Scholar
Chavis, BF, Lee, C (1987) Toxic Wastes and Race in the United States. New York, NY, USA: United Church of Christ.Google Scholar
Cox, R (2007) Nature’s ‘crisis disciplines’: does environmental communication have an ethical duty? Environmental Communication 1: 520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crist, E (2019) Abundant Earth: Toward an Ecological Civilization. Chicago, IL, USA: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crompton, T (2011) Values matter. Nature Climate Change 1: 276277.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Boeck, H, Bloor, J, Kreyling, J, Ransijn, J, Nijs, I, Jentsch, A, Zeiter, M (2018) Patterns and drivers of biodiversity–stability relationships under climate extremes. Journal of Ecology 106: 890902.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devictor, V, Meinard, Y (2020) Empowering biodiversity knowledge. Conservation Biology 34: 527529.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Díaz, S, Pascual, U, Stenseke, M, Martín-López, B, Watson, RT, Molnár, Z et al. (2018) Assessing nature’s contributions to people. Science 359: 270272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Díaz, S, Settele, J, Brondízio, E, Ngo, H, Guèze, M, Agard, J et al. (2020) Summary for policymakers of the global assessment report on biodiversity and ecosystem services of the Intergovernmental Science-Policy Platform on Biodiversity and Ecosystem Services [www document]. URL https://ipbes.net/sites/default/files/inline/files/ipbes_global_assessment_report_summary_for_policymakers.pdf Google Scholar
Douglas, H (2009) Science, Policy, and the Value-Free Ideal. Pittsburgh, PA, USA: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dowie, M (2011) Conservation Refugees: The Hundred-Year Conflict between Global Conservation and Native Peoples. Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dupré, J (2007) Fact and value. In: Value-Free Science? Ideals and Illusions, eds Kincaid, H, Wylie, A, Dupré, J (pp. 2741). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elliott, K (2009) The ethical significance of language in the environmental sciences: case studies from pollution research. Ethics, Place & Environment 12: 157173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elliott, K (2017a) A Tapestry of Values: An Introduction to Values in Science. New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elliott, K (2017b) The plasticity and recalcitrance of wetlands. In: Research Objects in Their Technological Setting, eds Bensaude-Vincent, B, Loeve, S, Nordmann, A, Schwarz, A (pp. 136149). London, UK: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elliott, K (2018) A tapestry of values: response to my critics. Philosophy, Theory, and Practice in Biology 10: 11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Escobar, A (1998) Whose knowledge, whose nature? Biodiversity, conservation, and the political ecology of social movements. Journal of Political Ecology 5: 5382.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Faber, NR, Jorna, RJ, van Engelen, JML (2005) The sustainability of ‘sustainability’: a study into the conceptual foundations of the notion of ‘sustainability’. Journal of Environmental Assessment Policy and Management 7: 133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glavic, P, Lukman, R (2007) Review of sustainability terms and their definitions. Journal of Cleaner Production 15: 18751885.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grouzet, FM, Kasser, T, Ahuvia, A, Dols, JMF, Kim, Y, Lau, S et al. (2005) The structure of goal contents across 15 cultures. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 89: 800816.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hautier, Y, Tilman, D, Isbell, F, Seabloom, E, Borer, E, Reich, P (2015) Anthropogenic environmental changes affect ecosystem stability via biodiversity. Science 348: 336340.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Holt, A (2006) Biodiversity definitions vary within the discipline. Nature 444: 146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hooper, D, Chapin, F III, Ewel, J, Hector, A, Inchausti, P, Lavorel, S et al. (2005) Effects of biodiversity on ecosystem functioning: a consensus of current knowledge. Ecological Monographs 75: 335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
IUCN, UNEP & WWF (1980). World Conservation Strategy: Living Resources Conservation for Sustainable Development. Gland, Switzerland: IUCN.Google Scholar
Johns, D, DellaSala, DA (2017) Caring, killing, euphemism and George Orwell: how language choice undercuts our mission. Biological Conservation 211: 174176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kareiva, P, Marvier, M, Lalasz, R (2012) Conservation in the Anthropocene. Beyond solitude and fragility. The Breakthrough Institute [www document]. URL https://thebreakthrough.org/journal/issue-2/conservation-in-the-anthropocene Google Scholar
Kellert, S (2010) For the love and beauty of nature. In: Moral Ground: Ethical Action for a Planet in Peril, eds Moore, KD, Nelson, MP (pp. 373378). San Antonio, TX, USA: Trinity University Press.Google Scholar
Kourany, J (2010) Philosophy of Science after Feminism. New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krimsky, S (2000) Hormonal Chaos: The Scientific and Social Origins of the Environmental Endocrine Hypothesis. Baltimore, MD, USA: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Lacey, H (1999) Is Science Value Free? London, UK: Routledge.Google Scholar
Larson, B (2011) Metaphors for Environmental Sustainability: Redefining Our Relationships with Nature. New Haven, CT, USA: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Layzer, J (2016) The Environmental Case: Translating Values into Policy, 4th edn. Thousand Oaks, CA, USA: CQ Press.Google Scholar
Longino, H (1990) Science as Social Knowledge. Princeton, NJ, USA: University of Princeton Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCann, K (2000) The diversity–stability debate. Nature 405: 228233.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McKaughan, D, Elliott, KC (2013) Backtracking and the ethics of framing: lessons from voles and vasopressin. Accountability in Research 20: 206226.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Meinard, Y, Coq, S, Schmid, B (2019) The vagueness of ‘biodiversity’ and its implications for conservation practice. In: From Assessing to Conserving Biodiversity: Conceptual and Practical Challenges, eds Casetta, E, Marques da Silva, M, Vecchia, D (pp. 353374). Cham, Switzerland: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mohai, P, Pellow, D, Roberts, JT (2009) Environmental justice. Annual Review of Environment and Resources 34: 405430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morar, N, Toadvine, T, Bohannan, BJM (2015) Biodiversity at twenty-five years: revolution or red herring? Ethics, Policy & Environment 18: 1629.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nisbet, M, Mooney, C (2007) Science and society. Framing science. Science 316: 56.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Norton, B (2008) Toward a policy-relevant definition of biodiversity. In: Saving Biological Diversity: Balancing Protection of Endangered Species and Ecosystems, eds Askins, R, Dreyer, G, Visgilio, G, Whitelaw, D (pp. 1120). New York, NY, USA: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perkins, HE (2010) Measuring love and care for nature. Journal of Environmental Psychology 30, 455463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, M, Peterson, M, Peterson, T (2005) Conservation and the myth of consensus. Conservation Biology 19: 762767.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pielke, R (2007) The Honest Broker: Making Sense of Science in Policy and Politics. New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rolston, H (1989) Environmental Ethics: Duties to and Values in the Natural World. Philadelphia, PA, USA: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Rolston, H (1998) Saving nature, feeding people, and the foundations of ethics. Environmental Values 7: 349357.Google Scholar
Rolston, H (2006) Caring for nature: what science and economics can’t teach us but religion can. Environmental Values 15: 307313.Google Scholar
Rounsevell, MM, Harfoot, P, Harrison, T, Newbold, RG, Mace, G (2020) A biodiversity target based on species extinctions. Science 368: 11931195.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Routley, R (1973) Is there a need for a new, an environmental, ethic? Proceedings of the XVth World Congress of Philosophy 1: 205–210.Google Scholar
Sandifer, P, Sutton-Grier, A, Ward, B (2015) Exploring connections among nature, biodiversity, ecosystem services, and human health and well-being: opportunities to enhance health and biodiversity conservation. Ecosystem Services 12: 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Santana, C (2014) Save the planet: eliminate biodiversity. Biology & Philosophy 29: 761780.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Santana, C (2019) Natural diversity: how taking the bio- out of biodiversity aligns with conservation priorities. In: From Assessing to Conserving Biodiversity: Conceptual and Practical Challenges, eds Casetta, E, Marques da Silva, J, Vecchia, D (pp. 401414). Cham, Switzerland: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarkar, S (2002) Defining ‘biodiversity’; assessing biodiversity. Monist 85: 131155.Google Scholar
Sarkar, S (2019) What should ‘biodiversity’ be? In: From Assessing to Conserving Biodiversity, eds Casetta, E, Marques da Silva, J, Vecchia, D (pp. 375399). Cham, Switzerland: Springer.Google Scholar
SCB (2011) 2011–2015 SCB Strategic Plan: Enhancing the Impact of Conservation Science. Washington, DC, USA: Society for Conservation Biology.Google Scholar
Schlosberg, D (2009) Defining Environmental Justice: Theories, Movements, and Nature. New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sheldon, KM, Nichols, CP, Kasser, T (2011) Americans recommend smaller ecological footprints when reminded of intrinsic American values of self-expression, family, and generosity. Ecopsychology 3: 97104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shrader-Frechette, K (2002) Environmental Justice: Creating Equality, Reclaiming Democracy. New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skibins, JC, Powell, RB (2013) Conservation caring: measuring the influence of zoo visitors’ connection to wildlife on pro-conservation behaviors. Zoo Biology 32: 528540.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Soulé, M (1985) What is conservation biology? BioScience 35: 727734.Google Scholar
Svensson, G, Høgevold, N, Ferro, C, Varela, JCS, Padin, C, Wagner, B (2016) A triple bottom line dominant logic for business sustainability: framework and empirical findings. Journal of Business-to-Business Marketing 23: 153188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Takacs, D (1996) The Idea of Biodiversity: Philosophies of Paradise. Baltimore, MD, USA: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Thompson, P (2007) Agricultural sustainability: what it is and what it is not. International Journal of Agricultural Sustainability 5: 516.Google Scholar
Thompson, PB (2017) The Spirit of the Soil: Agriculture and Environmental Ethics, 2nd edn. New York, NY, USA: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toepfer, G (2019) On the impossibility and dispensability of defining ‘biodiversity’. In: From Assessing to Conserving Biodiversity: Conceptual and Practical Challenges, eds Casetta, E, Marques da Silva, J, Vecchia, D (pp. 341351). Cham, Switzerland: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
UNESCO-EOLSS (2020) Definition of Life Support Systems in the Context of the EOLSS [www document]. URL https://www.eolss.net/Eolss-Definition-Context.aspx Google Scholar
Vaske, JJ, Manfredo, MJ (2012) Social psychological considerations in wildlife management. In: Human Dimensions of Wildlife Management, eds Decker, DJ, Riley, S, Siemer, FW (pp. 4357). Baltimore, MD, USA: The Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Vucetich, JA, Bruskotter, JT, Nelson, MP (2015) Evaluating whether nature’s intrinsic value is an axiom of or anathema to conservation. Conservation Biology 29: 321332.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Vucetich, J, Nelson, MP (2010) Sustainability: virtuous or vulgar? BioScience 60: 539544.Google Scholar
Wang, S, Loreau, M, (2016) Biodiversity and ecosystem stability across scales in metacommunities. Ecology Letters 19: 510518.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
White, L (1967) The historical roots of our ecologic crisis. Science 155: 12031207.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilson, KA, Law, EA (2016) Ethics of conservation triage. Frontiers in Ecology and Evolution 4: 112.Google Scholar
Worm, B, Barbier, E, Beaumont, N, Duffy, J, Folke, C, Halpern, B et al. (2006) Impacts of biodiversity loss on ocean ecosystem services. Science 314: 787790.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wyborn, C, Kalas, N, Rust, N (2019) Seeds of change: provocations for a new research agenda. Biodiversity Revisited Symposium Conference Proceedings, 11–13 September 2019, Vienna, Austria [www document]. URL https://doi.org/10.13140/RG.2.2.22170.59848/3 Google Scholar