Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-pftt2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-17T23:08:07.267Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

32 - Graviton BECs: A New Approach to Quantum Gravity

from Part V - Condensates in Astrophysics and Cosmology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 May 2017

G. Dvali
Affiliation:
Arnold Sommerfeld Center for Theoretical Physics, Department für Physik
C. Gomez
Affiliation:
Arnold Sommerfeld Center for Theoretical Physics, Department für Physik
Nick P. Proukakis
Affiliation:
Newcastle University
David W. Snoke
Affiliation:
University of Pittsburgh
Peter B. Littlewood
Affiliation:
University of Chicago
Get access

Summary

We outline an alternative view to quantum gravity, based on the idea that a black hole can be understood as a Bose-Einstein condensate of gravitons (quanta of gravitational energy) at the critical point of the quantum phase transition, with black hole radiation and evaporation being a manifestation of how the graviton many-body system maintains itself at criticality. Within this approach, the de Sitter invariance is quantum mechanically broken as a (1/N) effect, where N is the number of gravitons.

Introduction

Although classical General Relativity (GR) has had enormously interesting experimental predictions, going from the deflection of light to the expansion of the universe, we are still missing an efficient way to consume the marriage between GR and quantum mechanics.

We can easily identify the two main reasons that make this desired marriage extremely difficult. Quantum mechanics, as well as Quantum Field Theory (QFT), is based on notions such as particle and interaction that are defined relative to an absolute space-time. They can be extended to curved backgrounds, but when the geometry starts to affect concepts such as global time, paradoxes unavoidably appear. Moreover, the main message of GR, namely that geometry itself is a dynamical notion, creates its own set of conceptual problems. Should we think of geometry as on an equal footing as we think of other fields such as Yang Mills that we quantize on a privileged absolute Minkowski space-time? And, if that is the right way to proceed, how should we deal with the problems of renormalizability and unitarity that this naive approach immediately creates?

As it is well known the root of these perturbative problems lies in the dimensions of the coupling (the Newton constant) defining the strength of the gravitational interaction. In Wilsonian terminology, the gravitational interaction is defined by an irrelevant operator that flows nicely into the infrared (IR) but goes out of control in the ultraviolet (UV) whenever we go beyond the Planck scale, a length scale that acquires the Wilsonian meaning of a natural cutoff.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2017

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] G., Dvali and C., Gomez: Black hole's quantum N-portrait, Fortsch. Phys., 61 (2013) 742–767Google Scholar
[2] G., Dvali and C., Gomez: Black hole's 1/N hair, Phys. Lett. B 719 (2013) 419–423Google Scholar
[3] G., Dvali and C., Gomez: Black holes as critical point of quantum phase transition, Eur. Phys. J. C 74 (2014) 2752Google Scholar
[4] G., Dvali, D., Flassig, C., Gomez, A., Pritzel, and N, Wintergerst, Scrambling in the black hole portrait, Phys. Rev. D 88 (2013), 124041Google Scholar
[5] G, Dvali and C, Gomez: Quantum compositeness of gravity: black holes, AdS and inflation, JCAP(2014) 01, 023Google Scholar
[6] G, Dvali, C., Gomez, R. S., Isermann, D, Lst, and S, Stieberger Black hole formation and classicalization in ultra-Planckian 2N scattering, Nucl. Phys. B 893 (2015) 187–235Google Scholar
[7] G., Dvali and C., Gomez: Quantum exclusion of positive cosmological constant? Ann. Phys. (Berlin) 528, 68–73 (2016)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×