Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-dfsvx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-29T19:24:05.034Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Teaching Critically within a Modern Legal Genre*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 July 2014

William E. Conklin
Affiliation:
Faculty of Law/Department of Philosophy, University of Windsor

Abstract

This paper argues that the effort to teach law critically from the external viewpoint reinforces the ideological and social function of a professional law school in a modern state. One should realize that law is a language, a secondary language that conceals suffering as it parasitically assimilates all primary discourses. The professional law school of a modern state aids in the production of such concealment. Examples are offered from different areas of legal discourse as well as from the author's experiences. The suffering arises from the concealment of the languages of embodied subjects, whose harm can only be recognized through the chains of authoritative signifiers that the professor pro-fesses. The secondary legal language either excludes the primary languages or redefines the subject's experience. Further, the legal language is inculcated into the subject's language to the point that the citizen must identify with the secondary legal language or, if not, may be authoritatively en-forced to do so. The second sense of suffering aggravates the first.

Résumé

Cet article expose que l'effort fourni pour enseigner le droit de façon critique d'un point de vue externe renforce la fonction idéologique et sociale des facultés de droit dans un État moderne. Il y a lieu de réaliser que le droit est un langage. Il s'agit d'un langage secondaire qui dissimule la souffrance en assimilant de façon parasitaire les discours primaires. L'école professionnelle de droit de l'État moderne participe pas à la mise en oeuvre d'une telle dissimulation. Tant mes propres expériences que les diverses facettes du discours juridique regorgent d'exemples. La dissimulation des discours de sujets concrets, dont la souffrance ne peut être reconnue qu'à partir des chaînes de signifiants autoritaires que le professeur enseigne, engendre la souffrance. Quant au langage secondaire juridique, soit qu'il exclut les langages primaires ou qu'il redéfinit l'expérience du sujet. De plus, le langage juridique est intégré dans le langage du sujet à un point tel que le citoyen doit s'identifier à ce langage secondaire juridique ou, s'il s'y refuse, il (elle) pourra être obligé de le faire de façon péremptoire. Ce deuxième sentiment de souffrance ne vient qu'aggraver le premier.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Law and Society Association 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Consultative Group on Research and Education in Law, Law and Learning (Ottawa: Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council, 1983)Google Scholar (Chair: H. Arthurs), especially at 155, paras. 3–4. This may not always have been the case, for the report may have served as the situs for a retrenchment discourse by the core of some faculties.

2. See, e.g., Conklin, W. E., “The Legal Theory of Horkheimer and Adorno” (1985) 5 Windsor Yearbook of Access to Justice 230Google Scholar.

3. I reached this conclusion during the late 1970s and tried to describe the phenomenon in ibid.

4. See esp. Adorno, T. W., “After Auschwitz” in Negative Dialectics (New York: Continuum, 1983)Google Scholar; Horkheimer, M. & Adorno, T., The Dialectic ofthe Enlightenment, trans. Cumming, J. (New York: Continuum, 1944, 1972)Google Scholar.

5. See, e.g., Gabel, P., “The Phenomenology of Rights-Consciousness and the Pact of the Withdrawn Selves” (1984) 62 Texas L. Rev. 1563Google Scholar; Gabel, P. & Kennedy, D., “Roll-Over Beethoven” (1984) 36 Stanford L. Rev. 3CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Unger, R., “The Critical Legal Studies Movement” (1983) 96 Harv. L. Rev. 561CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Gabel, , “Reification in Legal Reasoning” (1980) 3 Research in Law and Sociology 25Google Scholar; and Kennedy, D., “Toward an Historical Understanding of Legal Consciousness: the Case of Classical Legal Thought in America, 1840–1940” (1980) (Spitzer, S., ed.) 3 Research in Law and Sociology 3Google Scholar.

6. See, e.g., the admittedly early writing on feminist legal theory in DuBois, E. C. et al. , “Feminist Discourse, Moral Values, and the Law—A Conversation” (1985) 34 Buffalo L. Rev. 11Google Scholar; MacKinnon, C. A., “Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State: An Agenda for Theory” (1982) 7:3Signs 515CrossRefGoogle Scholar and (1983) 8:4Signs 635CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For a more recent example, see Matsudu, M., “Public Response to Racist Speech: Considering the Victim's Story” (1989) 87 Mich L. Rev. 2128Google Scholar; and Looking to the Bottom: Critical Legal Studies and Reparations” (1987) 22 Harv. C.R.—C.L. Rev. 402Google Scholar.

7. de Saussure, F., Course in General Linguistics, trans. Baskin, W., intro. Culler, J. (New York: Philosophical Library, 1959)Google Scholar.

8. I show in another manuscript that legal language in a modern state ignores the phonemes or meaning forming process with which the lawyer constitutes the association of forms with signifiers.

9. See esp. Bakhtin, M. M., “Discourse on the Novel” in Emerson, C. & Holquist, M., ed., The Dialogic Imagination: Four Essays (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1981)Google Scholar and “The Problem of Speech Genres” in Speech Genres and Other Late Essays, trans. McGee, V. W. (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1986)Google Scholar.

10. Bakhtin, “The Problem of Speech Genres,” ibid. at 61–62, 65–66, 98–99.

11. Ibid. at 62.

12. Ibid. at 98.

13. More than any contemporary legal theorist, Stanley Fish has described the genre-like character of law. Once a student is introduced into the genre in a professional law school, Fish suggests, s/he is no longer “free” to choose arguments that are considered unacceptable to the genre. S/he surrenders her/his freedom. S/he begins to learn the implicit expectations and implicit understandings that go with her/his future juridical role as an officer of the court. A set of pre-existing interpretive practices both enable and constrain the act of beginning. As a consequence, a sense of an intentional, self-conscious human actor within the legal genre is missing. The lawyer thinks within, not about, established interpretive practices. Fish, S., Doing What Comes Naturally: Change, Rhetoric and the Practice of Theory in Literary and Legal Studies (Durham: Duke University Press, 1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14. In other schools of narratology, these are given different names and divided into three: story, narrative, discourse. I attempt to work the role of stories and the narrative within the secondary genre below.

15. The term is Bal's, Mieke in Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of Narrative, trans. van Boheeman, C. (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1985) at 5Google Scholar.

16. Rimmon-Kenan, S., Narrative Fiction: Contemporary Poetics (London: Methuen, 1983) at 125CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17. I sometimes feel as if the professor is no longer expected to exercise a practical judgment in the evaluative process. Rather, I sense that the genre expects me to administer grades. The class average is rigorously regulated and enforced, administrators claim authority to alter grades that do not jibe with the posited class average, the examination methods are regulated and reviewed prior to implementation, the evaluation must be administered anonymously, objectively, and formally through written forms, and the rigorous appeal process ensures that objectivist answers have been the source of evaluation. The pro-fessor is a juridical official whose authority is grounded in regulations imposed by a committee of the Faculty Council, whose authority, in turn, is founded in regulations of the Senate whose authority …

18. Canada A. G. v. Attorney General of Ontario, Labour Conventions Case, 1937 [1937] A.C. 327; 3 Olmsted 180 (per Lord Atkin).

19. I believe this is explained in another manuscript of mine tentatively entitled “The Legal Language of Authority.”

20. Derrida makes the point in several essays that every language of metaphysics presupposes a center. He does not connect this claim to legal language, nor does he make any claim about an invisible author of authority, to my knowledge.

21. For the constituent of finalization in a dialogic relation, see Rimmon-Kenan, supra note 16 at 76–78.

22. Lyotard discusses this in another context in “A Memorial of Marxism: For Pierre Souyri” in Peregrinations: Law, Form, Event (New York: Columbia University Press, 1988) at 46Google Scholar.

23. Lyotard, F., The Differend: Phrases in Dispute, trans. Abbeele, G. van den (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1988), vol. 46Google Scholar in Theory and History of Literature, at 26.

24. Volosinov, V. N., Marxism and the Philosophy of Language, trans. Matejka, L. & Titunik, I. R. (New York: Seminar Press, 1973) at 115–24Google Scholar.

25. Again, this is the enterprise of constitutional lawyers, an enterprise that is fleshed out in more detail in Conklin, W. E., Images of a Constitution (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1989) c. 1Google Scholar. The notion of an “image” is pushed to that of a “spectacle” in Guy Debord, , Society of the Spectacle (Detroit: Black & Red, 1983)Google Scholar, and Comments on the Society of the Spectacle (Imrie, Malcolm, transl; London/New York: Verso, 1990)Google Scholar.

26. Volosinov, supra note 24 at 129.

27. Gadamer, H.-G., Truth and Method (New York: Crossroad, 1985) at 235–74Google Scholar.

28. A similar provision was also included in the Joint Parliamentary Committee Report issued on 2 March 1992. The latter provided that the Constitution should “guarantee” “the fundamental right of the aboriginal peoples to self-government.”

29. See esp. Commission on the Political and Constitutional Future of Quebec, Report (Quebec: The Commission, 1991)Google Scholar (Co-chairs: Bélanger/Campeau) and Quebec Liberal Party, Constitutional Committee, A Quebec Free to Choose: Report of the Constitutional Committee of the Quebec Liberal Party (The Liberal Party, 1991)Google Scholar (also known as the Allaire Report).

30. Citizens Insurance Co. v. Parsons; Queen Insurance Co. v. Parsons, (1881) 7 A.C. 96, 1 Olmsted 94 (P.C. per Sir Montague Smith); Ont. A.G. v. Can. A.G., [1896] A.C. 348, 1 Olmsted 343 (P.C. per Lord Watson).

31. Liquidators of the Maritime Bank of Canada v. Receiver General of Canada, [1892] A.C. 437, 1 Olmsted 263 (P.C. per Lord Watson).

32. In re The Board of Commerce Act, 1919, and The Combines and Fair Practices Act, 1919, [1922] 1 A.C. 191, 11 Olmsted 245 (P.C. per Lord Haldane).

33. [1932] A.C. 54, 11 Olmsted 709 (P.C. per Lord Sankey).

34. This pronouncement was actually made with respect to a substantially weaker version of the limitations clause. See Government of Canada, The Constitutional Amendment Bill, 1978: Explanatory Document (Ottawa: Info Canada, 1978) at 812Google Scholar; A Time for Action: Toward the Renewal of the Canadian Federation (Ottawa: Info Canada, 1978) at 8Google Scholar; A Time for Action: Highlights of the Federal Government's Proposals for the Renewal of the Canadian Federation (Ottawa: Info Canada, 1978) at 2, 9Google Scholar. For a discussion of the clause, see Conklin, W. E., In Defence of Fundamental Rights (Alphen aan den Rijn: Sijthoff & Noordhoff, 1979) AppendixGoogle Scholar.

35. Between 1937 and 1970, the American Supreme Court had used the signifier to sustain the constitutionality of all but one state statute challenged under the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. The anomalous case was Morey v. Doud 354 U.S. 457, 77 S.Ct 1344 (1957).

36. See generally W. E. Conklin, supra note 25. For a judge who did examine such issues, see the discussion in that work at 252.

37. The Poetics of Prose, trans. Howard, R. (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1977) at 72Google Scholar.

38. Supra note 25.

39. The Dialogic Imagination, supra note 9 at 336.

40. Foucault, M., I Pierre Rivière, having slaughtered my mother, my sister, and my brother …: A Case of Parricide in the 19th Century, trans. Jellinek, F. (Lincoln/London: University of Nebraska Press/Random House, 1975)Google Scholar.

41. See Vygotsky, L. S., Haufmann, E. & Vaker, G., trans. & ed., Thought and Language (Boston: MIT Press, 1962)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; von Uexkull, J., Theoretical Biology, trans. Mackinnon, D. L. (London: Kegan Paul, 1926)Google Scholar; and Todorov, T., Mikhail Bakhtin: The Dialogic Principle (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984), vol. 13Google Scholar in Thought and History of Literature, at 79.

42. See the studies of Sarat, A. & Felstiner, W. L. F., “Law and Social Relations: Vocabularies of Motive in Lawyer/Client Interaction” (1988) 22 Law and Society Rev. 737CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Stange, C., “Wounded Womanhood and Dead Men: Chivalry and the Trials of Clara Ford & Carrie Davies” in Iacovelter, F. & Valverde, M., eds., Gender Conflicts (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1992) 149–88Google Scholar; and Hay, D., “Time, Inequality and Law's Violence” in Sarat, A. & Kearns, Th. R., Law's Violence (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1992) 141–74Google Scholar.

43. Gates, H. L. Jr., ed. The Classic Slave Narratives, with intro. (Markham, ON & New York: Penguin/New American Library, 1987)Google Scholar.

44. Foucault, supra note 40.

45. See the effort in Conklin, W. E. & Morison, J., “Public Issues in a Private Law World: The Case of the Appointment of a Receiver” (1987) 25 Osgoode Hall L.J. 45Google Scholar.

46. Williams, P., “The Obliging Shell: An Informal Essay on Formal Equal Opportunity” (1989) 87 Mich. L. Rev. 2320CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Alchemical Notes: Reconstructing Ideals from Deconstructed Rights” (1987) 22 Harvard C.R.—C.L. Rev. 402Google Scholar.