Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-nr4z6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-15T08:21:03.124Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Empathy, Primitive Reactions and the Modularity of Emotion

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Get access

Extract

Are emotion-producing processes modular? Jerry Fodor, in his classic introduction of the notion of modularity (Fodor 1983), holds that its most important feature is cognitive impenetrability or information encapsulation. If a process possesses this feature, then, as standardly understood (Currie and Sterelny 2000), “what we want or believe makes no difference to how [it] works” (147).

In this paper, we will start with the issue of the cognitive impenetrability of emotion-producing processes. It turns out that, while there is abundant evidence of emotion-producing processes that are not cognitively impenetrable, some nonetheless are. We will look at two sorts of case. The first concerns emotional reactions to observed faces, and the second involves what we can call “primitive emotions,” emotions that can be activated by non-doxastic input into regions of the brain we share with more primitive animals.

In seeing how some emotion-producing processes can be cognitively impenetrable while others are not, we need to use two commonsensical theses. First, a discussion of modularity must in general operate with a taxonomy that allows for sub-processes or stages of processes.

Type
2. Modularity and Basic Emotions
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Archibald, S. 2006. Mirror image. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 7(1): 44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Avenanti, A., D., Bueti, G., Galati, and S. M., Aglioti. 2005. Transcranial magnetic stimulation highlights the sensorimotor side of empathy for pain. Nature Neuroscience 8(7): 955-60.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bickle, J. 2003. Philosophy and Neuroscience: A Ruthlessly Reductive Account, Studies in Brain and Mind, vol. 2. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bohannon, J. 2005. Faulty “emotional mirror” may help explain autism. Science Now: 12.Google Scholar
B. G, Breitmeyer, T., Ro, and N., Singhal. 2004. Unconscious priming with chromatic stimuli occurs at stimulus-not percept-dependent levels of visual processing. Psychological Science 15: 198202.Google Scholar
Brewer, B. 2005. Does perceptual experience have conceptual content? European Journal of Philosophy 14(2): 165-81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cools, R., A. J., Calder, A. D., Lawrence, L., Clark, E., Bullmore, and T. W., Robbins. 2005. Individual differences in threat sensitivity predict serotonergic modulation of amygdala response to fearful faces. Psychopharmacology 180(4): 670.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Crane, T. 2003. The Mechanical Mind: A Philosophical Introduction to Minds, Machines, and Mental Representation. 2nd ed. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Currie, G., and K., Sterelny. 2000. How to think about the modularity of mind-reading. Philosophical Quarterly 50(199): 145-60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Decety, J., and P. L., Jackson. 2006. A social-neuroscience perspective on empathy. Current Directions in Psychological Science 15(2): 54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1983. The Modularity of Mind: An Essay on Faculty Psychology. Cambridge (Mass.): MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1998. In Critical Condition: Polemical Essays on Cognitive Science and the Philosophy of Mind, Representation and Mind. Cambridge (Mass.): MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gallese, V. 2004. Intentional Attunement: The Mirror Neuron system and its role in interpersonal relations. Review of reviewed Item. Interdisciplines. http: I I www.interdisciplines.org I mirror I papers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. I. 2006. Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University.Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. 1997. What Emotions Really Are: The Problem of Psychological Categories. Chicago: University of.Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. 2004. Is emotion a natural kind? In Thinking About Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions, ed. Soloman, R.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. 1995. Rewriting the Soul: Multiple Personality and the Sciences of Memory. Princeton (N.J.): Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hatfield, E., J. T., Cacioppo, and R. L., Rapson. 1994. Emotional Contagion, Studies in Emotion and Social Interaction. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Heilman, K. M. 2000. Emotional Experience: A neurological model. In Cognitive Neuroscience of Emotion, ed. Lane, R. D. and Nadel, L., 328-44. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
R. K, Hofbauer, P., Rainville, G. H., Duncan, and M. C., Bushnell. 2001. Cortical representation of the sensory dimension of pain. Journal of Neurophysiology 86(1): 402-11.Google Scholar
Hume, D., D. F., Norton, and M. J., Norton. 2000. A Treatise of Human Nature, Oxford Philosophical Texts. Oxford: Oxford University.Press.Google Scholar
Iacoboni, M., I., Molnar-Szakacs, V., Gallese, G., Buccino, J. C., Mazziotta, and G., Rizzolatti. 2005. Grasping the intentions of others with one's own mirror neuron system. PLoS Biology 3(3): 529-37.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
P. L, Jackson, A. N., Meltzoff, and J., Decety, 2005. How do we perceive the pain of others? A window into the neural processes involved in empathy. Neurolmage 24(3): 771.Google Scholar
Jacobson, AJ. 1992. A problem for naturalizing epistemologies. Southern Journal of Philosophy 30(4): 3149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacobson, AJ. 1993. A problem for causal theories of reasons and rationalizations. Southern Journal of Philosophy 31(3): 307-21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacobson, AJ. 2003. Mental representations: What philosophy leaves out and neuroscience puts in. Philosophical Psychology 16(2): 189203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacobson, AJ. 2005. Is the brain a memory box? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 3: 271-78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacobson, AJ. 2006. Hume's theory of ideas. In The Pre-History of Cognitive Science, ed. Brook, A., 97114. New York: MacMillan/Palmgrave.Google Scholar
James, W. 1884. What is an emotion? Mind 9: 188205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
LeDoux, J. 2000. Cognitive-emotional interactions: Listen to the brain. In Cognitive Neuroscience of Emotion, ed. Lane, R. D. and Nadel, L.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. H. 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Montague, R. 2006. Why Choose this Book? How We Make Decisions. New York: Penguin.Google Scholar
Oberman, L., E. M., Hubbard, McCleery, J.P., E. L., Altschuler, V. S., Ramachandran, and J. A., Pineda. 2005. EEG evidence for mirror neuron dysfunction in autism spectrum disorders. Cognitive Brain Research 24(2): 190-98.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Peacocke, C. 1992. Anchoring conceptual content: Scenarios and perception. In Cognition, Semantics and Philosophy, ed. Ezquerro, J., 293322. Norwell, MA: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prinz, J. J. 2004. Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotion, Philosophy of Mind Series. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sebanz, N., G., Knoblich, L., Stumpf, and W., Prinz. 2005. Far from actionblind: Representation of others’ actions in individuals with autism. Cognitive Neuropsychology 22(3-4): 433.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wicker, B. 2003. Both of us disgusted in my insula: The common neural basis of seeing and feeling disgust. Neuron 40(3): 655755.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
L. M, Williams, B. J., Liddell, A. H., Kemp, R. A., Bryant, R. A., Meares, A. S., Peduto, and E., Gordon. 2005. Amygdala-prefrontal dissociation of subliminal and supraliminal fear. Human Brain Mapping 27: 652-61.Google Scholar
Zajonc, R. B. 1980. Feeling and thinking: Preferences need no inferences. American Psychologist 35: 151-75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar