Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-01T05:47:12.743Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Territorial Challenge: From Constitutional Patriotism to Unencumbered Agonism in Bosnia and Herzegovina

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Constitutional patriotism is on the ascent among contemporary constitutional theories. Its objective is to re-orient the loyalty of citizens away from particularistic attachment to a Nation, and towards the Constitution. In promoting political justice, constitutional patriotism relies on citizens’ acceptance of a particular constitutional order not as an embodiment of particularistic ethnocultural, or even statist values, but rather as an expression of universal political principles. In other words, a constitutional order ought not to be seen as an instrument for a nation's political self-actualization, but rather as a framework for institutions and a repository of values that enable a diverse body of citizens to critically rework their particular traditions in light of universalist principles of political justice.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © 2012 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

1 For the intellectual history of the concept, see Müller, Jan-Werner, Constitutional Patriotism 15–45 (2007).Google Scholar

2 Shabani, Omid Payrow, Who's Afraid of Constitutional Patriotism? The Binding Source of Citizenship in Constitutional States, 28 Social Theory and Practice 419, 435 (2002); Elsa van Huyssteen, 'The Glowing Fire of our New Patriotism': The Constitutional Court, Civil Society and Constitutional Patriotism in South Africa in Gathering Voices: Perspectives on the Social Sciences in Southern Africa (Teresa Cruz María & Silva Ari Sitas eds., 1998); Gerard Delanty, Habermas and post-national identity: Theoretical perspectives on the conflict in Northern Ireland, Irish Political Studies 1, 11 (1996); Esad Zgodić, Ustavni patriotizam za Bosnu I Hercegovinu (Constitutional Patriotism for Bosnia and Herzegovina), 1 Godišnjak Bošnjačke zajednice kulture “Preporod“ 13 (2010).Google Scholar

3 For a prudential critique of constitutional patriotism in the context of the European Union see Kumm, Mattias, Why Europeans will not embrace constitutional patriotism, 6 ICON 117 (2008). For a critique in the Canadian context, see Jean-François Gaudreault-DesBiens, The Fetishism of Formal Law, the Circumstances of Constitutional Patriotism, and the Fate of Complex Polities in Nation Über Alles: Process of Redefinition and Reconstruction of the Term Nation in Central Europe (Michal Vasecka ed., 2008). For a critique in the context of Northern Ireland, see Schwartz, Alexander, Patriotism or Integrity? Constitutional Community in Divided Societies, 31 Ox. J. Leg. S. 503 (2011).Google Scholar

4 See Laborde, Cecile, From Constitutional to Civic Patriotism, 32 B. J. Pol S. 591 (2002); Antonino Palumbo, Patriotism and pluralism: identification and compliance in the post-national polity, 2 Ethics and Global Politics 321 (2009); Ephraim Nimni, Constitutional or Agonistic Patriotism? The Dilemmas of Liberal-Democratic States in Constituting Communities: Political Solutions to Cultural Conflict 94 (Per Mouritsen & Knud Erik Jorgensen eds., 2008).Google Scholar

5 See Schwartz, supra note 3.Google Scholar

6 See Lerner, Hanna, Constitution-writing in deeply divided societies: the incrementalist approach, 16 Nations and Nationalism 68 (2010).Google Scholar

7 For the consociationalists’ rejection of the Arab intellectuals’ invocation of constitutional patriotism in the context of Iraq's constitutional transformation, see O'Leary, Brendan, McGarry, John & Salih, Khaled, The Future of Kurdistan in Iraq 30 (2005).Google Scholar

8 In contrast, the recent upsurge of interest in deeply divided societies among constitutional lawyers and political scientists focuses on the choice between “integration” and “accommodation.” See generally, Sujit Choudhry ed., Constitutional Design for Divided Societies: Integration or Accommodation? (2008). Those who consider secession a legitimate option seek to discourage it through constitutionalizing, a rather cumbersome procedure, see Norman, Wayne, Negotiating Nationalism: Nation-Building, Federalism and Secession in the Multinational State 204 passim (2006).Google Scholar

9 Habermas, Jürgen, Constitutional Democracy: A Paradoxical Union of Contradictory Principles?, 29 Political Theory 766, 776 (2001).Google Scholar

10 Habermas, Jürgen, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, 133 (William Rehg (tr., 1998).Google Scholar

11 Habermas, Jürgen, Struggles for recognition in democratic constitutional state in 8 The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory, 203, 213 (Ciaran Cronin & Pablo DeGreiff, eds., 1999).Google Scholar

12 Habermas, supra note 9, at 772.Google Scholar

14 Honig, Bonnie, Dead Rights, Live Futures: A Reply to Habermas's “Constitutional Democracy,” 29 Political Theory 792, 797 (2001).Google Scholar

15 Id. at 797.Google Scholar

16 Id. at798.Google Scholar

17 Habermas, supra note 9, at 775 [emphasis author's].Google Scholar

18 Müller, Jan-Werner, A European Constitutional Patriotism? The Case Restated, 14 Eur. Law J. 542, 547 (2008).Google Scholar

19 Shabani, supra note 2, at 435.Google Scholar

20 Id. at 436.Google Scholar

21 Id. at 437.Google Scholar

22 Kymlicka, Will, Multicultural Citizenship 108 (1996).Google Scholar

23 Kymlicka, Will, Reply and Conclusion in Can Liberal Pluralism Be Exported? Western Political Theory and Ethnic Relations in Eastern Europe 345, 362 (Will Kymlicka & Magda Opalski, eds., 2001).Google Scholar

24 Id. at 354 [emphasis added].Google Scholar

25 Kymlicka, Will, Politics in the Vernacular: Nationalism, Multiculturalism and Citizenship 118 (2001).Google Scholar

26 Kymlicka, Western Political Theory and Ethnic Relations in Eastern Europe in 13 Kymlicka, supra note 23, at 27.Google Scholar

27 Kymlicka, supra note 23, at 390.Google Scholar

28 At this point the answer might be that multinational federalism is an expression of the compact between self-determining peoples, which implies the right to secession. In words of Jacob Levy, “if … ethnically-sensitive federalism is justified on grounds that the group gaining control of a province is a national and if nations have a prima facie right to self-determination, then moving toward such federalism seems to grant a key premise of a future argument for secession.” Jacob T. Levy, National Minorities Without Nationalism in The Politics of Belonging: Nationalism, Liberalism, and Pluralism 155, 156 (Alain Dieckoff ed.,2004).Google Scholar

29 A potential way around this difficulty is to say that ethnocultural justice is important only domestically, because only domestically does it impact individual autonomy and flourishing. The fact that a member of a national community does not have a unit to call her own in an international setting does not subtract from the possibilities for her individual autonomy.Google Scholar

30 Kymlicka, supra note 25, at 101.Google Scholar

31 The national symbols featured in the coat of arms of Republika Srpska and the Federation of Bosnia and Herzegovina were based on “distinction, exclusion, restriction or preference based on race, color, descent, or national or ethnic origin which has the purpose or effect of nullifying or impairing the recognition, enjoyment or exercise, on an equal footing, of human rights and fundamental freedoms in the political, economic, social, cultural or any other field of public life.” U-4/04, Partial Decision on the Merits, 31 March 2006, (Constitutional Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina) at para. 124, available at: http://vlex.com/vid/-59929523 (last accessed: 23 December 2011).Google Scholar

32 Kymlicka treats this possibility as a way to dilute the political power of the ethno-national group, but the territorial pattern of distribution of this group may be such that it would not be possible to include the majority of them within a single territorial unit without wronging the other ethnic group within a multinational polity.Google Scholar

33 Nagel, Thomas, Legitimacy and Unanimity in 3 Equality and Partiality 33, 34 (1995).Google Scholar

34 Karol So łtan, Constitutional Patriotism and Militant Moderation, 6 Icon 96, 99, 103 (2008).Google Scholar

35 Bobbio, Norberto, In Praise of Meekness in In praise of meekness: essays on ethics and politics (2000).Google Scholar

36 Id. at 26.Google Scholar

37 Id. at 30.Google Scholar

38 Id. at 29.Google Scholar

39 Id. at 29.Google Scholar

40 Id. at 28.Google Scholar

41 Weiler, Joseph H.H., In defense of the status quo: Europe's constitutional Sonderweg in 1 European Constitutionalism beyond the State 7, 18 (Joseph H.H. Weiler & Marlene Wind eds., 2003)Google Scholar

42 Müller, Jan-Werner, A general theory of constitutional patriotism, 6 Icon 72, 82 (2008).Google Scholar

43 Id. at 76.Google Scholar

44 Müller, Jan-Werner, Three Objections to Constitutional Patriotism, 14 Constellations 195, 199 (2007).Google Scholar

45 Müller, supra note 42, at 76.Google Scholar

46 Id. at 79.Google Scholar

47 Id. at 89.Google Scholar

48 Hague, William & Ashdown, Paddy, Broken Bosnia needs western attention, Financial Times, Dec. 29, 2009, available at: http://www.ft.com/intl/cms/s/0/bf60a826-f4af-11de-9cba-00144feab49a.html#axzz1eM2×8sa8 (last accessed: 23 December 2011).Google Scholar

49 Stranka Za Bosnu I Hercegovinu, Programska orijentacija Stranke za Bosnu i Hercegovinu (Program Orientation for the Party for Bosnia and Herzegovina), available at: http://www.zabihsana.com/sadrzaj/programska-orjentacija-stranke-za-bih.html (last accessed: 23 December 2011).Google Scholar

50 Akcije, Stranka Demokratske, Political Declaration as adopted on the 5th Party Congress, available at: http://sda.ba/download/PROGRAM_DECLARATION_5TH_CONGRESS.pdf (last accessed: 23 December 2011).Google Scholar

51 Interview with Professor Zdravko Grebo, “Potrebno je samo da s poštovanjem kažemo da smo gradani ove zemlje,” (“You just have to respectfully say that we are citizens of this country,”) Radio Studio 88, Nov. 25, 2008, available at: http://www.studio88.ba/bh/38/bih/11804/ (last accessed: 23 December 2011).Google Scholar

52 Karabeg, Omer, BiH-zemlja zamrznutog konflikta (Bosnia and Herzegovina: A country frozen in conflict), Radio Free Europe, http://www.slobodnaevropa.org/content/article/1371186.html (last accessed: 23 December 2011).Google Scholar

53 Tuzle, Forum Gradjana, available at: http://www.forumtz.com/bos/vijest21.html (last accessed: 23 December 2011).Google Scholar

54 Müller, Jan-Werner & Scheppele, Kim Lane, Constitutional Patriotism: An Introduction, 6 ICON 67, 67 (2008).Google Scholar

55 Eldin Hadžović, Reisov Manifest [Reis's Manifesto], 619 BHDANI„ Apr. 24, 2009, available at: http://www.bhdani.com/default.asp?kat=kol&broj_id=619&tekst_rb=1 (last accessed: 23 December 2011).Google Scholar

56 Some constitutionalists, for example, use the two terms indistinguishably. See Choudhry, Sujit, After the Rights Revolution: Bills of Rights in the Post-Conflict State, 6 Annual Review of Law and Social Science 301, 316 (2010).Google Scholar

57 See Shabani, supra note 2, at 441.Google Scholar

58 This hegemonic invocation doesn't need to have a solely domestic side. If constitutional patriotism is defined against its ethnic other, and if that ethnic other is constructed through the external endorsement of a particular territorial distribution, then, in a particular context constitutional patriotism serves the purposes of those who, from the outside, have an interest (and not only an unselfish desire) to maintain a territorial status quo. The practical consequences of such a stance may be good or bad, but at least—at a theoretical level—we would do well to acknowledge that constitutional patriotisms structurally depend on ‘invisible’ actors who enable it to configure itself as an alternative to vicious ethnic nationalism.Google Scholar

59 Sołtan, supra note 34, at 96.Google Scholar

60 Perhaps, for this reason, recent writings on constitutional patriotism among Sarajevo intellectuals offer only qualified support for the constitutional patriot project. For Esad Zgodic, constitutional patriotism can equally be grafted onto the Dayton constitution of Bosnia and Herzegovina, which, for him, would be morally unacceptable given the war crimes and ethnic cleansing that led to the current internal territorial division of the country, entrenched in this constitution. Instead, his understanding of constitutional patriotism's promise—echoing Shabani's theme of reasonableness—gestures towards patriotism's potential to liberate the country from “malevolent irrationalism” of nationalism and “‘custom-based’ patriotism.” See Zgodić, supra note 2, at 23–4.Google Scholar

61 Interview with Dodik, Milorad, “Mi svoj put znamo,” Fokus, Banja Luka, published on the Government of Republika Srpska website, available on file with the author.Google Scholar

62 Tully, James, The Unfreedom of the Moderns in Comparison to Their Ideas of Constitutional Democracy, 65 MLR 204, 219 (2002).Google Scholar

63 As Patchen Markell rightly argued “[t]he maxim, ‘it's not whether you win or lose,’ only goes so far, especially in politics.” Patchen Markell, Bound by Recognition 33 (2003).Google Scholar

64 Tully, James, 1 Public Philosophy in a New Key: Democracy and Civic Freedom 139, 141, 154 (2008).Google Scholar

65 Id. at 175.Google Scholar

66 Christodoulidis, Emilios, Constitutional Irresolution: Law and the Framing of Civil Society, 9 ElJ 401, 416 (2003).Google Scholar

67 Id. at 426.Google Scholar

68 Armitage, David, Probing the Foundations of Tully's Political Philosophy, 39 Political Theory 2011, 124, 127 (2011).Google Scholar

69 Second Report of Republika Srpska to the United Nations Security Council on the Situation in Bosnia and Herzegovina, 2219/09 (2009).Google Scholar

70 “Sulejman Tihić repeated the position of SDA that the OHR has to stay in Bosnia and Herzegovina until it is … capable to function independently and fulfill its obligations on the road towards the full membership in NATO and the EU.” [translation mine] Official Website, Party of Democratic Action, available at http://www.sda.ba/vijest.php?id=626 (last accessed: 23 December 2011).Google Scholar

71 I won't elaborate further on the idea of ‘democratic reductionism’ in this article. However, I will remark that support for it may come from diverse political and legal traditions. Hans Kelsen, a legal positivist, known cosmopolitan and a pacifist, argued for the satisfaction of national demands wherever possible. See for example, Hans Kelsen, Law and Peace in International Relations, The Oliver Wendell Holmes Lectures, 1940–41, 141, 163 (1948). From within a liberal tradition, on the other hand, Richard Flathman constructs the concept of ‘willful liberalism’ that embraces the legitimacy of under-argued, opaque political desires. See Flathman, Richard, Willful Liberalism: Voluntarism and Individuality in Political Theory and Practice (1992). Finally—and more directly relevant to the project—there are theories of secession that build on the idea of individual autonomy to justify reconfiguration of political boundaries. See generally Wellman, Christopher, A Theory of Secession (2005).Google Scholar

72 Tully, supra note 52, at 212.Google Scholar

73 Id. at 177.Google Scholar

74 Theorists of agonism are generally keen to distinguish themselves from more rabid nationalists. Agonism, for Chantal Mouffe, for example, is a progressive step away from ant-agonism, implicit in nationalist sectarian struggles. See Mouffe, Chantal, The Return of the Political 117, 133 (2005).Google Scholar

75 Responding to speculation about a potential decision about holding a referendum on secession of Republika Srpska, Bosnian Serb politician Nikola Špirić, currently the Bosnian prime minister, said: “What would such a referendum mean anyway, if nobody recognized it?” Radiotelevizija Srbije (Jan. 20, 2010), available at: www.rts.rs (last accessed: 23 December 2011).Google Scholar

76 Tully, supra note 52, at 181, 183.Google Scholar

77 For an interesting neo-republican articulation of a community of fate, a community of individuals connected not through normative ideals but rather by a simple fact of being ‘stuck’ together, see Herman R. van Gunsteren, A Theory of Citizenship: Organizing Plurality in Contemporary Democracies (1998).Google Scholar

78 Id. at 147, 163.Google Scholar

79 So łtan, supra note 34, at 99.Google Scholar

80 One argument could be that even if the scope of territorial solidarity would diminish, it would be offset by the larger involvement of the nascent polity in providing international aid. Pre-empting the objection of selfishness seems to animate the position of the Scottish National Party, which advocates the secession of Scotland from the United Kingdom. The SNP International Development spokesperson has, for example, claimed that “SNP share[s] [the] ambition and look to the example of other small nations such as the Norwegians, the Irish and the Danes who punch way above their weight in making a positive contribution. “It's Time for a Say on International Aid,” The Scottish National Party Official Website (Mar. 27, 2007), available at: http://www.snp.org/press-releases/2006/it2019s-time-for-a-say-an-international_aid/view?searchterm=international (last accessed: 23 December 2011) [emphasis added].Google Scholar

81 So łtan, supra note 34, at 98.Google Scholar