Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0.001 Render date: 2024-05-16T19:33:17.437Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Between a republican and a Bengalee state: Confronting exclusionary constitutionalism in Bangladesh

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 June 2023

M A Sayeed*
Affiliation:
1School of Law, University of New England, Armidale, NSW, Australia
Lima Aktar
Affiliation:
2Faculty of Law, Jahangirnagar University, Dhaka, Bangladesh
*
Corresponding author: M A Sayeed; Email: msayeed3@une.edu.au
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The constitutional design of Bangladesh is characterized by an ambivalent choice: it aspires to establish a republican yet a Bengalee state by putting itself in the conflicting terrain within the demos–ethnos binary. This article aims to examine the implication of this problematic choice along all three axes of the constitution’s elemental parts: its identity, rights and structure. While the identity element of the Bangladesh Constitution embodies the ethno-nationalist vision of the Bengalee state that transforms demos into ethnos, its rights and structural aspects reflect its republican promise to transform ethnos into demos. Contemporary scholarship seeks to confront the exclusionary dimension of the ethno-nationalistic choice in Bangladesh but ends up accepting ethnos as a politically superior value. Such an approach brings us to the politics of difference and, with that, undermines the integrationist potential of the republican constitution. In response, this article defends the republican promise of the Bangladesh Constitution while arguing that what we need in Bangladesh is the ‘de-ethnicization’ of the republic, one that can be achieved by transforming ethnos into demos and not the other way around.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

I. Introduction

In The Inclusion of the Other, German philosopher Jürgen Habermas argues for maintaining a distinction between the two figurations of peoplehood: ethnos and demos. Footnote 1 Habermas’s defense of this distinction is directed against the idea of ethnonationalism that collapses the distinction between an ethnos, a pre-political community of ‘shared descent organized around kinship ties’ and a nation constituted as a state.Footnote 2 This collapse suggests that ‘the demos of citizens must be rooted in the ethnos of nationals (volksgenossen) if it is to stabilize itself a political association of free and equal legal consociates’. For Habermas, there is no a priori reason why a constitutional democracy should rest itself on this logic. Instead, he believes that the republican concept of citizenship may better serve the purpose of constitutional integration. In other words, the progressive extension of citizenship to the whole population provides the state not only with a new source of legitimation but also with a new level of abstract, legally mediated social integration.Footnote 3

From a Habermasian perspective, a republican constitution founded on the voluntary association of the demos is therefore more appropriate than the ethno-nationalist or even the liberal-communitarian conception of the nation and democracy.Footnote 4 This is because it allows us to disrupt any convergence – symbolic or historical – between republicanism and nationalism that existed, for Habermas, only as a transitional and historical constellation. As he argues, ‘republicanism is neither conceptually nor practically dependent on nationality, and the twentieth century, in particular, has provided grotesque examples of the dangers of emphasizing the relationship between ethnos and demos’.Footnote 5 In this article, we wish to argue that the constitutional architecture of Bangladesh is caught up in the same danger that Habermas finds in the collapse between republicanism and ethnonationalism. This is evident in Bangladesh’s ambivalent choice in that it aspires to establish a republican yet a Bengalee state, thus placing itself in the conflicting terrain of the demos–ethnos binary.Footnote 6

The purpose of this article is therefore to examine the implication of this problematic choice along all three axes of the constitution’s elemental parts: its identity, rights and structure. In order to do so, we draw on and situate our findings in three different families of constitutional strategies – assimilation, accommodation, and integration – all of which find their place in the constitutional design of Bangladesh.Footnote 7

First, we identify that the original Constitution of Bangladesh adopted the ethno-based Bengalee identity for all, regardless of ethnic difference and diversity.Footnote 8 This ethno-nationalistic paradigm of identity formulation falls prey to being categorized as ‘assimilative constitutionalism.’Footnote 9 In assimilative strategy, unity is achieved through a coercive ‘acculturation’ that ‘involves one community adopting the culture of another and being absorbed into it’.Footnote 10 In that sense, assimilative strategy is only a form of exclusionary constitutionalism. Second, while ethnicizing constitutional identity, which aims to transform ethnos into demos, the Constitution adopted the demos-centric arrangements for other elemental parts: the architecture of rights and electoral and representative structure of the state. This is because it provides for a republican architecture of rights and a unitary governance structure based on territorial constituency rather than ethnic representation. This arrangement of individual rights and de-ethnicized representative structure fits into the ‘integrationist’ approach to constitutionalism,Footnote 11 which promotes a common public identity without demanding ethnocultural uniformity or assimilation.Footnote 12 From this perspective, the integrationist approach comes closer to the promise of the abstract and legally mediated form of civic integration defended by Habermas.

Finally, in the subsequent constitutional arrangements, there has been an oscillation between these two approaches. During the first military regime,Footnote 13 the Constitution was amended (the Fifth Amendment) to redefine the constitutional identity by replacing the ethno-centric Bengalee nationalism with Bangladeshi nationalism, a demos-centric construction of territorial nationalism.Footnote 14 However, the recent Fifteenth AmendmentFootnote 15 has reinstalled, in the name of restoring the original constitution, the previous arrangement of ethno-centric identity of the people, and with that returned to the assimilationists framework. Interestingly, the same amendment has brought a change in relation to its rights arrangement by inserting a new provision for cultural rights of the ethnic groups.Footnote 16 Between the time of the Fifth and the Fifteenth Amendments, the government also signed the Peace Accord to grant certain forms of regional autonomy to the Chittagong Hill Tracts (CHT) people, thus initiating a structural change towards ethnic accommodation.Footnote 17 With these changes, the Constitution seems to adopt an ‘accommodationist’ strategy,Footnote 18 which requires the recognition of ethnic difference and ‘adjustment to the special interests and needs of groups’.Footnote 19

Such accommodationist demands were first raised by Manabendra Narayan Larma, an influential ethnic leader who represented the CHT people at the Constituent Assembly of Bangladesh. Larma demanded that the constitution be designed around ethnic difference and his proposal was more comprehensive, as he argued not only for the recognition of ethnic identity but also for the inclusion of enforceable group rights and a separate legislative council for the CHT people.Footnote 20 However, this demand has not been addressed in the Constitution, although the Peace Accord and the Fifteenth Amendment have already initiated some accommodationist strategy. This brings us the accommodationists’ critique that, despite its recent move to plurality-consciousness, the Constitution is not sufficiently inclusive.Footnote 21 There is also a more forceful argument that the Constitution, with the changes made by the Fifteenth Amendment, has maintained the relations of domination through assimilation of minority identity into the dominant culture.Footnote 22 From this perspective, critics argue for reform along accommodationist strategy while formally opposing coercive assimilation by the majority.

While we share similar concerns about assimilationism to those raised by the accommodationists, we differ in terms of solution. In this article, we defend republican-integration against both assimilationist and accommodationist strategy.Footnote 23 Its main targets are the accommodationists’ response to the failure of the current constitutional model. As we argue, the accommodationist approach seeks to confront ethno-nationalism but ends up accepting ethnos not only as a morally superior value but also as a site of political mobilization. This article responds to these problems while arguing that a truly inclusive constitution in Bangladesh would entail the reversal of such logic. That is, it should involve the de-ethnicization of the Constitution by maintaining neutrality to ethnic difference, which resonates with the republican promise of transforming ethnos into demos. This defence for the republican-integrationist strategy is grounded on the following justifications.

The first justification is contextual. The integrationist approach claims that it functions better when the societies are not deeply polarized and ‘when there is already extensive heterogeneity, hybridity, and mixing’.Footnote 24 Demographically, Bangladesh has only 2 per cent of people identified as ethnic minorities as opposed to the originated majority. The ethnic minorities composed of as many as eleven communities live predominately in the hilly region of Bangladesh (known as Chittagong Hill Tracts), but some part of these communities also inhabit in the plain land.Footnote 25 Moreover, with increasing Bengalee migration to the CHT region,Footnote 26 a demographic shift has taken place, resulting in mixing and hybridity. The implication of this shift is that the multiple ethnic groups living in CHT cannot ‘realistically’ aspire and maintain ‘either territorial autonomy or consociation’.Footnote 27 However, the question may remain whether Bangladesh is still deeply divided along ethnic lines, despite the relatively small size of its ethnic minorities and the demographic mixing in the CHT region. It is important here to emphasize that a society may be ethnically diverse yet not deeply divided. As Benjamin Reilly suggests, for a society to be ethnically divided, its ethnic community must have politically salient cleavages around which interests are organized for political purposes or political mobilization.Footnote 28 Such political mobilization occurs, at an empirical level, through ethnically characterized electoral politics, where political parties respond by organizing themselves on the basis of ethnicity and ethnic individuals cast votes only for their own ethnic political party.Footnote 29 In Bangladesh, ethnic divisions display no such political salience in the polity’s party system.Footnote 30 This indicates that Bangladesh is not deeply divided, at least along an ethnic axis, although a fairly deep division can be found to exist along ideological lines (between Islamists and secularists) or on religious lines (between Muslims and Hindus). Given that such ideological or religious division is beyond the scope of this article, we accept that problem of ethnic exclusion in Bangladesh can be addressed by an integrationist approach that functions better in an ethnically diverse yet not divided society.

The second justification comes from the transformative promise of republican-integration. The republican-integrationist approach shares the goal of unity with blindness to ethnic difference without denying the social existence of ethnic diversity. In this way, it differs significantly from the assimilationists approach, which eliminates difference by establishing one ethnic identity. In contrast, the integrationist approach achieves unity by disestablishing all the ethnic identities, including the majority’s own. This de-ethnicization expands ‘we-ness’, which then underpins the demos-centric, trans-ethnic solidarity within the framework of republican citizenship. At this point, someone may legitimately ask how this promise of republican-integration is to be translated in political terms. To address this concern, we wish to clarify that our aim is not to offer an empirical account of the transformation from ethnos to demos and the ways in which such transformation could make a qualitative difference in the current socio-political milieu. Instead, our prescription is founded on the proposition that constitutions can transform the polity by reducing the gap between the norms and social facts. Therefore, a careful and purposive constitutional design can result in changes in political behavior and practice.Footnote 31 Moreover, as we show in this article, the republican promise of the Bangladesh Constitution prescribes the removal of cultural and socio-economic obstacles. Such prescription will help us to understand the ways in which the Constitution can deal with the difference-sensitive claims in the real world while maintaining a demos-centric, difference-blind normative foundation.

The remainder of this article is developed in the following way. Part II offers a critic of the assimilationists promise as reflected in its adoption of Bengalee nationalism. It argues that the Constitution has not just declared Bengalee nationalism as a rhetorical value, but also sets it as a catalytic force for transforming demos into ethnos. Parts III and IV respond to the accommodationists’ arguments for constitutional reform by way of defending an integrationist approach that meets the republican promise of the Bangladesh Constitution. In Part III, we argue that the recent constitutional amendment has had the effect of shifting to an ethno-centric arrangement from the difference-blind approach of rights provided in the original Constitution. Part IV shows how political contestation over the issue of ethnicity has led to the problematic plan for structural reform that masquerades as a solution. It argues that the ethno-centric reform of representative structure will produce minorities within the minority, thereby bringing us to circular logic of exclusion. The article concludes with a demand for reform along the republican promise of difference-blindness.

II.Bengalee and democratic state’: Exclusion by assimilation?

Joseph Raz once criticized the juxtaposition of Jewish and democratic state as ‘morally indecent’.Footnote 32 The constitutional characterization of Bangladesh as a ‘Bengalee’ yet a democratic state invokes an analogy with such criticism of the Jewish state advanced by Raz. In this section, however, we argue that the idea of Bengalee state is more problematic than what Joseph Raz called ‘morally indecent’. We develop this argument by showing that the current constitutional arrangement entails coercive assimilation through the exclusion of the ethnic ‘other’. In doing so, we first examine the moral relevance of Bengalee state, then move to show how it comes to be the site of assimilative politics. To begin with, the project of assimilative politics has been fortified by the constitutionalization of four political ideals – nationalism, democracy, secularism and socialism (NDSS) – with a definition of nationalism in article 9 that enforced the superiority of Bengalee identity.Footnote 33 The enumeration of these ideals was a much-debated issue from the very moment of drafting the original Constitution. The debates were folded around the reconcilability of two sets of ideals that came in pairs: ‘democracy–socialism’ and ‘socialism–nationalism’. In the Constituent Assembly, it was raised that ‘democracy’ cannot be reconciled with the ideal of socialism.Footnote 34 The other line of critique came to address the problematic relationship between ‘nationalism and socialism’. For example, Serajul Islam Chowdhury has criticized the mixing of nationalism with socialism while identifying the danger that it ‘could result in the production of what has come to be known as Nazism’.Footnote 35 Chowdhury goes further to identify the exclusionary dynamics of Bengalee nationalism while criticizing it in the following constitutional terms:

in their enthusiasm they were oblivious of two ground realities. Firstly, that there were non-Bengali small nationalities living within the territory of Bangladesh, and secondly, that in the modern world a state with a single nationality is not a viable proposition. There is, however, an unconscious display of nationalist chauvinism in the idea advanced in the constitution to the effect that all citizens of the state would be called Bengalis. Footnote 36

This criticism reminds us of Joseph Raz’s ‘moral thesis’ against the idea of a ‘Jewish and democratic state’.Footnote 37 In Raz’s view, any ethnic or national values to be attached to the state are true but only signify ‘false values of national self-aggrandizement and chauvinism’.Footnote 38 Raz argues that such Jewishness of the state gives a ‘false consciousness’ to the people who are non-Jews, but the citizens of that Jewish state.Footnote 39 Hence, democracy cannot be retained by one state simultaneously while declaring its identity as a Jewish state alongside being a so-called neutral state. For him, the principle of democracy, being a true signifier of universal value, does not necessarily require the state to customize or localize that universalism into its own (state in concern) language. In other words, there is no need to declare or identify a particular state with an ideal to be a democratic and moral state, even if it is for the sake of any symbolic meaning.Footnote 40 It can simply act on being the moral state – otherwise, it cannot be a home for other people who do not belong to that particular symbolic ideal.Footnote 41 This leads Raz to claim that morally decent countries need not declare their nationalism to show their character and traditions to the whole world.Footnote 42 Such argument advanced by Raz reveals that ‘the Jewish and democratic elements are morally odd, or at least in tension with each other.’Footnote 43

From this perspective of Raz’s moral thesis, it may appear that the vision of being a ‘Bengalee state is morally odd with the idea of democratic state’. But we will argue that the implication of establishing a Bengalee state is somewhat more sinister than the case of privileging Jewish nationalism in the context of Israel. This is because the Constitution of Bangladesh does not just privilege Bengalee nationalism over other nations, as in the case of Jewish nationalism; rather, it also provides for coercive acculturation of other ethnic communities by denying the possibility of other identities.Footnote 44 The original Constitution institutes this logic of acculturation by declaring that ‘citizens of Bangladesh shall be known as Bengalees’.Footnote 45 That means it imposes ‘Bengalee nationalism’ for all of its citizens irrespective of the distinctive ethnic and cultural background of many other communities.

Interestingly, there was a strong resistance to such constitutional arrangement at the moment of constitution-making. In the Constituent Assembly, Larma, the lone representative of the CHT people, raised his concern against the constitutionalization of Bengalee nationalism in the following words:

You cannot impose your national identity on others. I am a Chakma, not a Bengali. I am a citizen of Bangladesh-Bangladeshi. You are also Bangladeshi, but your national identity is Bengali … They [tribals] can never be Bengali.’Footnote 46

In response, Sajeda Chowdhury, the female member of the Constitution Drafting Committee, argued that the inclusion of tribes as Bangalees placed the hill people in a more dignified position as it recognized them as a nation rather than sub-nation.Footnote 47 The argument advanced by Chowdhury echoes the position of Sheikh Mujibur Rahman, the country’s founding leader, who expressed that the non-Bengali ethnic communities should assume the Bengali identity by shunning their own.Footnote 48 Such abrupt denial of ethnic identity is thought to be founded on the concept of ‘assimilative constitutionalism’.Footnote 49 It performs an inherently exclusionary function in the name of acculturation that amounts to the negation of the existence of other ethnic communities.Footnote 50

This situation assumes a more complex character with the recent enactment of the Fifteenth Amendment,Footnote 51 which has replaced the word ‘citizen’ (as used in the original Constitution) with the word ‘people’, and stipulated that ‘the people of Bangladesh shall be known as Bangalees as a nation’.Footnote 52 This replacement of ‘citizen’ by the ‘people’ reinforced the ethno-nationalist promise of conceiving Bangladesh as the ‘Bengalee state’. This conflation of people as Bengalees is nothing but a forcible transformation of demos into ethnos. Seen from this perspective, the concept of the Bengalee state finds its striking correspondence with one of Haiti’s earliest constitutions of the Black state, where all Haitian citizens were legally defined as Black, regardless of skin colour or prior racial categorization. By securing Haitian citizenship, a person became Black in the eye of the constitution of Haiti;Footnote 53 in a similar way, a non-Bengalee citizen of Bangladesh becomes a Bengalee in the eye of the Bangladesh Constitution.

While intensifying its assimilationist strategy by the Fifteenth Amendment, the Constitution has, however, provided for the ‘soft recognition’ of the existence of communities other than Bengalees. This comes in the form of non-justiciable cultural rights provided under the newly inserted article 23A, which aims to protect and develop the cultural tradition of ‘the tribes, minor races, ethnic sects, and communities’.Footnote 54 In Part III, we will return to article 23A in order to examine its implications for the republican architecture of rights. For now, we wish to engage with the scholarly response to the issue of recognition of ethnic diversity as mentioned above.

One criticism that seems most dominant across disciplines is that the Constitution of Bangladesh is defective in terms of addressing ethnic diversity.Footnote 55 For example, Ridwanul Hoque, coming from the perspective of inclusive constitutionalism, argues that the non-recognition of indigenous peoples in the original Constitution is a ‘genetic defect’Footnote 56 or a ‘grave mistake’.Footnote 57 This echoes the recent acknowledgement from the chairman of the Constitution Drafting Committee that the ‘sense of fulfilment’ for Bengalee nationalism has led to the constitutional exclusion of the other ethnic communities living in Bangladesh.Footnote 58 Hoque, however, appreciates the recent change made by the Fifteenth Amendment as a positive move from non-recognition to an explicit ‘attempt of inclusion’.Footnote 59 For a truly fuller recognition of the ethnic peoples, he argues that Bangladesh needs to ‘shift clearly to an accommodationist approach to these peoples’ distinct identity’.Footnote 60

In contrast, Mohammad Shahabuddin sees the recent amendment as the reinforcement of the dominance and hegemony of Bengalee nationalism through which the hill people of the CHT have become ‘constitutional outcasts’.Footnote 61 He argues that, ‘While this provision finally acknowledges the existence of communities other than Bengalees, it nonetheless underscores that unique cultures of these communities fall outside the “national culture” (defined in line with Bengalee nationalism).’Footnote 62 This argument stems from the fact that, under the current Constitution, the ethnic communities are termed and classified as ‘tribes’, ‘minor races’ and ‘ethnic sects’, not as ‘indigenous’, ‘aboriginal’ or ‘adivasi’, as they demanded or deserved.Footnote 63

The responses advanced by Hoque and Shahabuddin seem to fall into the accommodationist camp, as they insist on the recognition of ‘multiple public (constitutional) identities’ to secure the coexistence of different communities within the same state.Footnote 64 In this sense, they seek to resolve the problem of ethnic exclusion through emphasizing ethnos itself. So, we would suggest, in the name of accommodation, they endorse the identity-based politics, or what Charles Tylor calls the ‘politics of recognition’.Footnote 65 One obvious implication of such politics of difference is that it involves ‘the positive validation of ethno-cultural difference’.Footnote 66 This is why the effectiveness of such strategy is questioned by both the liberal and republican thinkers. For example, David Miller, who is considered a liberal nationalist,Footnote 67 identifies the danger of identity politics and argues that it can be counter-productive (self-defeating) in many ways.Footnote 68 According to him, the advocate of difference would destroy the conditions under which disparate groups in a culturally plural society can coexist with a common goal of social justice. In this sense, identity politics is ‘potentially damaging to the interests of the groups it is meant to serve’.Footnote 69 This led him to defend ‘republican citizenship’, which, according to him, ‘is better able to respond to cultural diversity than these other versions’. It can do so, he argues, ‘by virtue of its ability to draw groups who initially have very different priorities into public debate, and to find compromise solutions to political issues that members of each group can accept’.Footnote 70 In other words, republican citizenship can resolve the problem of ethnic exclusion in a better way than the strategies suggested by the accommodationist (multiculturalist) camp. For Miller, this defence of republican citizenship is, however, linked closely with the defence of nationality because republican virtues ‘are likely to be cultivated only within national borders’.Footnote 71

At stake in Miller’s account is that it speaks of a ‘moderate nationalism’ that is different from race-based or ethnicity-based form of nationalism.Footnote 72 It allows the formation of an autonomous self-constituting political nation based on a territorial rather than ethnically determined figuration of peoplehood.Footnote 73 As we suggest, this idea of territory-based nationalism is consistent with the republican idea of equal citizenship that combines ethnic neutrality with civic solidarity.Footnote 74 For the purpose of this article, we may call it ‘republican nationalism’ as distinct from liberal nationalism.Footnote 75 Our purpose here, however, is not to define or defend Miller as a republican theorist, but rather to draw on the fact that the marriage between republicanism and nationalism represents a defensible alternative to ethno-nationalism.Footnote 76 One advantage of republican nationalism is that it allows a demos-centric integration without assimilation. We will discuss shortly that such demos-centric integration in turn involves ‘disestablishment’ and non-domination, which marks its distinction with liberal neutrality.Footnote 77

Having identified its demos-centric implications, we wish to suggest that Bangladesh should adopt republican nationalism to replace its ethno-nationalist model of assimilation. It is important to mention here that republican nationalism is not a new idea for Bangladesh. A model of republican nationhood was adopted by the constitutional Fifth Amendment, which was recently invalidated by the Supreme Court.Footnote 78 By this amendment, the Constitution introduced the concept of ‘Bangladeshi nationalism’. It changed article 6 of the Constitution by providing that the citizens of Bangladesh shall be known as Bangladeshis instead of Bengalee. While untying the peoplehood with ethnicity, the same amendment did, however, replace secularism with a firm belief in the Islamic faith, forming the part of fundamental principles of state policy. This kind of idealization reduced the inclusionary promise of Bangladeshi nationalism, and leads the critic to dub it an ‘Islamic-nationalist’ political project.Footnote 79 However, such criticism seems to undermine the distinction between constitutional identity defined by article 6 and the fundamental principles articulated in Part II of the Constitution, given that article 6 has greater normative force than the Part II principles, which are non-justiciable in nature.Footnote 80 As we suggest, with the adoption of Islam as a fundamental principle, the Constitution simply engendered the same problem of what Raz refers to as a ‘morally indecent’ state in reference to Israel. Yet such problem of value endorsement should not deter us from appreciating how the Fifth Amendment de-ethnicized the identity of the constitutional subjects. That is, it stripped constitutional identity of any ethnic ingredients, and in this way transformed ethnos into demos. Footnote 81 Looked at from this perspective, Bangladeshi nationalism introduced by the Fifth Amendment was a better choice because it resulted in a ‘fair compromise’ to the issue of ethnic identity. This is because, it did not recognize non-Bengalee identity, but nor did it declare the supremacy of Bengalee ethnicity. This neutrality to ethnic difference corresponds to the republican promise, which involves ‘trans-ethnic solidarity’ through the idea of equal citizenship.Footnote 82

There are at least two aspects that would allow us to distinguish the republican dimension of Bangladeshi nationalism from the idea of a ‘homogenic national state’.Footnote 83 First, while ‘national state’ seems insensitive to diversity and seeks to establish homogeneity through assimilation, Bangladeshi nationalism remained indifferent to ethnic diversity, and symbolized integration without assimilation. Second, ‘national state’ involves the strategy of domination as it grounds national solidarity on the common or shared culture or heritage, which is already always characterized by the predominant historical narrative of nationality. In contrast, Bangladeshi nationalism disestablished the logic of ethno-nationalist assimilation, and with that reflects the policy of non-domination that lies at the heart of republican integration.

At this point, we should elaborate the relationship between ‘disestablishment’ and republican integration. To do so, it seems useful to reflect on the debate concerning the use of laïcité (the principle of secularism) because it involves the issue of republican impartiality and is seen as a yardstick forms of republican integration.Footnote 84 One possible advantage of this is that it will help us respond to the charge raised by the radical advocate of difference (such as Iris Marion Young), who argues that republicanism involves the imposition of oppressive norms in the name of impartiality.Footnote 85

The principle of laïcité was developed as a legacy of the struggle by the French republic to institutionalize the separation of the Catholic Church and the state.Footnote 86 The 1905 republican law separating the church and state articulates the principle of laïcité in a twofold way: first, it guarantees the free exercise of religions; and second, it declares that ‘it [state] neither recognizes nor subsidizes any religion’.Footnote 87 In its original juridical formulation, laïcité requires the neutrality of the state and public authorities, which means no more than the application of this neutrality to religious affairs.Footnote 88 The implication of this principle is that it neither promotes nor combats particular religious practice, and it permits every individual to have or not to have any religion. In this respect, it was different from a principle that aims at competition between religious affiliations and citizenship but was similar to establish a ‘civic religion’.Footnote 89 There is, therefore, a point in questioning the difference-blindness of laïcité regime, insofar as it demonstrates its ‘moral supremacy’ over all religions.Footnote 90 Moreover, from a historical perspective, it also invokes the charge of privileging European cultural majorities while rendering this privilege invisible.Footnote 91 Such criticisms, however, become stronger with the recent use of the laïcité principle as a republican justification for the ban of hijab for Muslims in France. It substantiated the claim that republican difference-blindness can be used to discriminate against those religious minorities whose religious practice is more visible than that of others.Footnote 92 Therefore, it shows that the laïcité principle has undergone a radical shift from its original republican articulation in the 1905 law.

What is striking in this bifurcation of laïcité regime within the republican promise is that it slightly shifts from ‘disestablishment’ of religion to the express imposition of ‘obligation’ at the individual level. The obligation-generating function of the ‘new’ laïcité principle sets out to encourage or discourage a particular practice, such as prohibiting hijab. But “disestablishment” would condemn this kind of policy, as Patten has rightly argued that a disestablishmentarian response to cultural diversity ‘would condemn policies that consciously set out to encourage or discourage particular forms of cultural life’.Footnote 93 Looked at from this perspective, we wish to note that the idea of republican neutrality should not be equated with the new laïcité regime that demands uniformity in public and associational life. Rather, it is the ‘disestablishing’ effect that forms the kernel of republican neutrality, and laïcité can be considered a yardstick of republican integration only if it is taken to imply the condition of disestablishment.

This is why many scholars have attempted to distinguish republican laïcité from the new regime of civic laïcité. Footnote 94 In a carefully written work, Cécile Laborde advances a similar argument about laïcité as she argues that a truly republican laïcité must focus on where actual neutrality remains unrealized in order to address the privileges of some religions and conceptions of the good life over others. Interestingly, such understanding involves a positive prescription towards the reform of what she calls “official republicanism”. This allows her to offer a distinctively critical vision of republicanism that calls for a strategy of non-domination by way of removing socio-cultural obstacles to minority incorporations. As we suggest, this strategy of non-domination echoes the core idea of republican liberty advanced by Phillip Pettit.Footnote 95 Laborde, however, shows how the strategy of non-domination can work through the arrangement of positive rights and disestablishment.

In Part III, we take on and situate Laborde’s argument in the context of Bangladesh. For now, we should reassert to the claim that Bangladeshi nationalism was reflective of republican neutrality that seeks to disestablish the predominant historical narrative of Bengalee nationality. This was warranted by the ‘we-perspective’ used in the preamble of the original Constitution.Footnote 96 At stake in this ‘we-ness’ is that it not only requires de-ethnicization of nationality but also a shift of its foundation from ‘cultural properties’ to ‘civil rights’.Footnote 97 Before the changes made by the Fifteenth Amendment, the Bangladesh Constitution was almost there. But, as shown above, Bangladesh has returned to the idea that the dominant Bengalee majority alone constitutes the people, a construction that transformed demos into ethnos. Footnote 98 Having identified this, we now turn to discuss how this ethno-centric (re)turn has affected other elemental parts of the constitution: rights and structure.

III. Rights-based pluralism and the politics of ‘inclusive exclusion’?

As we noted above, the original Constitution has counterbalanced the ethno-nationalist promise of assimilation by adopting a republican-integrationist architecture of rights that prioritizes demos over ethnos. In this part, we examine how this demos-oriented architecture of rights is contested, reasserted and is being directed to an ethno-centric turn. Interestingly, the contestation over the rights issue exists from the founding moment of constitution-making. While debating in the Constituent Assembly, Larma proposed for a right-based accommodation of the non-Bengalee ethnic communities. He expressed his discontent against the constitutional non-recognition claiming that the Constitution ‘did not reflect the hopes and aspirations of the tribal population’.Footnote 99 But when his recognition-demand was rejected by the assembly leaders, he advanced a stronger demand for special group rights. That is, he demanded special constitutional protection of the social, political, economic and religious security of the ethnic communities.Footnote 100 No such arrangement was made in the original constitution to protect the rights of the ethnic communities; rather, the Constitution has adopted the individualistic model of rights, with commitment to equality and non-discrimination.Footnote 101

On the dawn of long-standing political demand for Indigenous recognition,Footnote 102 the government of Bangladesh recently brought a constitutional reform. In 2011, the Constitution was amended to introduce a new provision – article 23A – that obliges the government to protect and develop the unique local culture and tradition of the non-Bengalee communities.Footnote 103 Therefore, the Constitution now provides for ‘cultural rights’, but the striking point is that such rights have been included in the form of principles (directive) and not as fundamental rights, as originally demanded by Larma.Footnote 104 The implication of this seems profound. This is because, in the context of the Bangladesh Constitution, fundamental rights have stronger justiciability than the fundamental principles (directives) which are ‘contra-judicative’ in nature.Footnote 105 From this perspective, article 23A implies only a ‘weak’ form of constitutional protection of cultural rights. There is, however, an option to consider whether article 23A constitutes a ‘moral tool’ that promotes constitutional ‘negotiation’ among culturally diverse people.

This point was picked up by Tarunabh Khaitan, who sees article 23A as an example of political constitutionalism.Footnote 106 While writing for an entirely different purpose (that is, to offer a perfectionist justification for constitutional directives), Khaitan emphasizes the importance of article 23A in terms of promoting ‘constitutional polyvocality’, which he builds on the Jacobsohnian balance of ‘disharmony.Footnote 107 According to him, article 23A illustrates constitutional directives’ ability to allow ‘unresolved contestations over identity to be reflected in the constitutional text, thereby endorsing value pluralism’.Footnote 108 Interestingly, such an argument corresponds to the demands of the ethnic communities, which feels a moral or strategic need to continue a political dialogue. For example, Raja Debasish Roy, an influential intellectual figure from the ethnic communities in Bangladesh, argues that without ‘even effective negotiations with governments and others, meaningful autonomy will remain as elusive as ever’.Footnote 109

What is striking about such an approach is that it seeks to institute the space of constitutional dialogue within the framework of constitutionalism. We may find a similar argument in the work of James Tully, who emphases constitutional negotiation as a precondition of cultural accommodation. But Tully disagrees that modern constitution can offer such space. In his exemplary work, Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in the Age of Diversity,Footnote 110 he argues that modern constitutionalism is inherently homogenizing, and is unsuitable for the accommodation of diversity. In order to accommodate diversity, the post-imperial constitutional project must acknowledge and act upon the premise that the constitution is ‘not monologue’ but rather a ‘dialogue’ between different groups.Footnote 111 In other words, the accommodation of diversity presupposes the ‘constitutional negotiation’ of diverse groups. As he argues:

A contemporary constitution can recognise cultural diversity if it is conceived as a form of accommodation of cultural diversity. It should be seen as an activity, an intercultural dialogue in which the culturally diverse sovereign citizens of contemporary societies negotiate agreements on their ways of association over time in accord with the conventions of mutual recognition, consent and continuity.Footnote 112

The polyvocality argument that Khaitan situates in relation to article 23A aligns with Tully’s invocation for constitutional dialogue, despite their distinctive approach to modern constitution.Footnote 113 Conceiving article 23A as a political formula of negotiating difference, Khaitan sets out to defend ethnic difference as a moral site of political mobilization. Seen in this light, Khaitan’s reading of article 23A reflects accommodationist (or multiculturalist) approach, endorsing the logic of identity politics or what Charles Taylor advanced as the politics of difference.Footnote 114

Such logic of difference comes to be more problematic if it is emphasized for the purpose of legal constitutionalism as opposed to political constitutionalism. The advocacy for legal constitutionalism can be found in the account of those who seek to protect ethnic minority under the legally enforceable regime of group-differentiated rights. For example, Shahabuddin argues that the omission of any specific guarantee for minority rights in the Bangladesh Constitution reduces the minority groups to the position of individual citizen, thereby assimilating the minority identity into the dominant culture.Footnote 115 He contends that the ‘liberalist-individualist’ architecture of rights is responsible for this problem because ‘the individualist notions of equality and non-discrimination are not merely inadequate for minority protection but are indeed the modus operandi of assimilation and the extinction of group identity’.Footnote 116

Following this argument, Shahabuddin identifies how this assimilative project was reinforced by the court’s adherence to the individualist principle of equality and non-discrimination as enshrined in the Constitution of Bangladesh.Footnote 117 The case of Mohammad Badiuzzaman v. Bangladesh and Others Footnote 118 has been used as an example in this regard. In that case, the CHT Regional Council Act of 1998 was challenged on the ground that such a special arrangement violated fundamental rights to equality and non-discrimination.Footnote 119 The court upheld the framework of equal rights against the idea of special group rights while indicating the need for political settlement towards progressive and innovative constitutional reform. This signifies, for Shahabuddin, the court’s failure to offer ‘legal approval’ to measures necessary for peacebuilding in the CHT region.Footnote 120 In response, Shahabuddin argues for a difference-sensitive arrangement of rights which ‘requires that group rights be accommodated in one form or the other’.Footnote 121 Patten provides a useful account of such rights-arrangement responsive to differentiated citizenship:

a politics of difference extends to all citizens a basic package of standard liberal rights, plus a set of difference- sensitive policies designed to reach out to members of cultural minorities and provide acknowledgement, accommodation, and assistance to their ways of life. The difference model does not abandon the idea of individuals as autonomous seekers of their own conceptions of the good, but it adds to this view of individuals the idea that they are also bearers of a cultural identity that they do not share with all other citizens.Footnote 122

If this ‘difference model’ is what Shahabuddin has in mind, then his critique of a liberal-individualist framework of equal rights provides no good reason to believe that his position was anti-liberal.Footnote 123 This is because such an account of differentiated-rights has successfully been generated by the liberal-multiculturalists, advocating for reconstructing the liberal concept of rightsFootnote 124 and, more radically, the idea of equality itself, as we will see shortly. So, the problem here is simply not that Shahabuddin’s account of differentiated rights offers no greater protection than does the liberal-individualistic framework of rights. Rather, the major problem of his argument lies in the following aspects: first, he fails to recognize the republican promise of Bangladesh Constitution and the ways in which such promise characterised its arrangement of rights;Footnote 125 and second, and most importantly, he subscribes to the danger posed by multiculturalism, which can be described by taking note of the following argument from Habermas:

in the case of multiculturalism, discrimination takes place within the framework of a broadly legitimate constitutional state and takes the more subtle form of domination by a majority culture that has merged with the general political culture. However, against Charles Taylor’s communitarian proposal, I argue that a ‘politics of recognition,’ which is supposed to ensure the equal right of different subcultures and forms of life to coexist within a single republican polity, must reject collective rights and survival guarantees.Footnote 126

Habermas’s response to the multiculturalist argument stems from his republican justification for equal citizenship, which entails the concept of equal rights. Therefore, it raises the legitimate question of whether such an idea of equality denies difference.Footnote 127 Such debate around equality and difference forms a recurring theme across feminism, race theory and, more generally, discrimination theory.Footnote 128 For the purposes of this article, it seems useful to respond briefly to some charges made, especially by the accommodationist critics of equality. Critics coming from the difference theorists mainly attack the idea of formal equality in which ‘equality is equated with sameness’.Footnote 129 For example, Cristine Littletone charges that such sameness-based vision of equality is an exercise of power by and for a white male elite.Footnote 130 Marion Young, while advocating for group-differentiated rights, advances her argument on the ground that equal citizenship institutes sameness: ‘citizenship for everyone, and everyone the same qua citizen’.Footnote 131 If equality is conceived of sameness, for her it adds two different meanings to the universal idea of citizenship: first, it empathizes generality rather than difference (what citizens have in common as opposed to how they differ); and second, it entails universal application of law and rules that are blind to group and individual difference.Footnote 132 Citizenship as generality tends to enforce homogeneity while universality as equal treatment promotes oppression and disadvantages.

The implications of these claims have been profound, for they instigate reform proposals from both the liberal and non-liberal theorists. Some liberal theorists advocate restructuring the individualistic framework of rights, while the difference theorists translate their demand into the idea of ‘true equality’, which is grounded not in sameness but rather in difference.Footnote 133 For example, Sheila Foster offers a powerful account of such ‘true equality’ with respect to difference which sets that ‘the goal of diversity should be to affirmatively include individuals from systematically excluded and disadvantage groups’.Footnote 134 In other words, true equality would enable diversity to erase the negative aspect of difference by eradicating institutional processes that translate into perpetual and systematic disadvantages for individuals with difference. In this respect, equality with respect to difference means no more than equality with the option of affirmative action.

This jurisprudence of positive discrimination, we argue, is consistent with the republican promise of equal rights and disestablishment. Habermas recognizes the potential for a gap between norms and facts – between the formal guarantees of equal rights and their actual worth. This tension requires him to set conditions for overcoming the inherent moment of inertia and inequality and, with that, to insure fairness and stability of political dialogue. For him, such conditions can be fulfilled by taking welfare measures for economic and social equality. More crucially for our purposes, Laborde defends the idea of affirmative action as part of what she calls ‘critical republicanism’. While counteracting the demand for differential treatment along ethnic and cultural lines, she argues that socio-economic disadvantage, rather than ethnic origin, is far preferable to focus. This is because the removal of socio-economic obstacles will facilitate the integration of ethnic minority, without requiring that they may be preferentially promoted.Footnote 135 In this respect, we endorse Laborde’s view and wish to add that the logic of removing social obstacles corresponds with the idea of disestablishment that forms the ethical precondition of republican unity.

At stake in such republican understanding of equality is that it indicates a shift in the meaning of ‘equality’ itself. That is, it draws on its descriptive meaning – ‘the same’ – and operates through its prescriptive meaning. Footnote 136 The equality in its prescriptive meaning involves the application of rightful rules to appropriate characteristics of the individual being ‘adjudged equal’.Footnote 137 In other words, prescriptive equality is comparative and relational than absolute.Footnote 138 We suggest that the republican idea of equal rights embodies both the descriptive and the prescriptive meaning of equality. In this sense, republican equality differs from Young’s understanding of equal citizenship, which builds only on the descriptive meaning of equality. In contrast, republican equality starts with equal status of citizenship but does not end with equal treatment to those with difference – it remains indifferent to ethnic difference but not to socio-economic disadvantages that originate from such difference.Footnote 139

Turning to the arrangement of the Bangladesh Constitution, we can see that it embodies the republican idea of equality as discussed above. The provision of article 28 sets out the principle of equality and non-discrimination along different categories of identity – race, caste, sex, religion and even place of birth. But the same article provides for affirmative action for the advancement of any backward section of citizens.Footnote 140 In a similar way, the Constitution allows the making of special provision in favour of any backward section of citizens to ensure adequate representation in the service of the republic.Footnote 141 The court of Bangladesh has been faithful to this republican idea of equality, as in the case of Mohammad Badiuzzaman. As shown above, Shahabuddin has been critical of Badiuzzaman, and of the arrangement of rights in general, despite the fact that the provisions of equality address much of the concerns raised by the difference theorists. He fails to acknowledge that the problem of the Bangladesh Constitution is not its demos-centric architecture of rights; rather, it is the ethnos-centric construction of nationality that we need to challenge and disestablish.

Far from this promise of disestablishment, the present Constitution, with the insertion of article 23A, has tilted its balance towards ethno-centric nationalism. This turn is reflected in the shifting language of the court on the question of ethnic identity and regional autonomy. Before the insertion of article 23A, the court was reluctant to recognize the ethno-centric arrangement of rights, particularly the right to autonomy under the CHT regulation.Footnote 142 However, the opposite direction towards the ethno-centric interpretation can be found in a recent case of Wagachara Tea Estate Ltd. v Muhammad Abu Taher and Others (2014).Footnote 143 In that case, the court has, by reinterpreting the status of ethnic people and their CHTRC,Footnote 144 recognized the status of ethnic minorities from ‘tribal or ethnic sects’ to ‘Indigenous people’. Moreover, it accepted, reinforced and recognized the ‘special status’ of CHT that makes it a ‘distinct’ region from other parts of Bangladesh as a republic, the point to which we will turn in the next section.

For now, we wish to claim that these arguments offered by the court stem directly from the language of the current Constitution, particularly article 23A. This has legitimized the promise of emphasizing ethnos as enforced by the original Constitution. It did not guarantee non-exclusion, but results in a more ‘subtle form of domination’, often in the form of what can be called ‘inclusive exclusion’.

IV. Structural reform for autonomy: the circularity of exclusion?

In the previous part, we have discussed how the architecture of rights is shifting from demos to ethnos-centric turn. This part examines the structural aspect of the Constitution with a focus on the question of regional autonomy and a special legislative council for the CHT people, a long-standing demand raised by their representative. In doing so, we engage with the two important structural models suggested by the accommodationists: ‘consociationalism’ and ‘centripetalism’.Footnote 145 The purpose of this is twofold. First, it shows how the demand of regional autonomy rests on the concept of differentiated citizenship, and therefore reinforces the ethno-nationalistic aspirations rather than the republican promise; second, it will help us prescribe the ways in which the Constitution can better respond to the minority demand for structural reform without compromising its republican promise.

On this point, it will be useful to briefly introduce the ideas of ‘consociationalism’ and ‘centripetalism’. The consociation model is advanced by Arend Lijphart, who advocates the establishment of an ‘ethnic federation’.Footnote 146 This model argues for a ‘cross-community power-sharing executive’ by which major elite representative from different communities can jointly work for conflict eradication.Footnote 147 However, to achieve consociation, Lijphart prescribes that three important elements need to be present: coalition – complete or concurrent;Footnote 148 proportionality in public sectors – legislative, executive and judiciary;Footnote 149 and autonomy or community self-government.Footnote 150 This way, consociation guarantees a society that will produce homogenous ethnic constituent units though complete ethnic representation. On the other hand, centripetalism is equivalent to words such as ‘convergence’, ‘centrism’ and ‘bringing together’. Major proponents of this model are Donald HorowitzFootnote 151 and Benjamin Reilly.Footnote 152 This model, like consociation, focuses on the institutional accommodation of minorities and how they can contribute towards a more deliberative democracy. However, the centripetal model differs from the consociation model in claiming a unique institutional design to manage democracy in a divided society by deinstitutionalizing the existing ethno-centric representation. That institutional design does not opt to ‘simply replicate existing ethnic divisions in the legislature and other representative organs’;Footnote 153 rather, it aims at depoliticizing ethnicity ‘by putting in place institutional incentives for politicians and their supporters to act towards the accommodation of rival groups’.Footnote 154 Along these lines, Horowitz argued for non-ethnic federalism in which powers would devolve from the central to the local authority. Having identified these differences, let us see what model is adopted in Bangladesh and where it is moving.

From the time of drafting the original Constitution, the demand for structural safeguards was pressed by the representative of the CHT people, both within and outside the Constituent Assembly. On 15 February 1972, Larma led a delegation to meet the key architect of independent Bangladesh, Sheikh Mujibur Rahman, and raised a series of demands for structural autonomy that include the establishment of a special legislative body, continuation of the offices of the tribal chiefs, and constitutional entrenchment of the CHT Regulation 1900.Footnote 155 It seems that such demands by the ethnic leader for a strong regional council echoed the spirit of the consociation model: to formulate an ethnic federation based on the ‘rule by the minority over itself in the area of the minority’s exclusive concern’.Footnote 156 These demands for structural safeguards were rejected on the ground that they were ‘parochial’.Footnote 157 Consequently, the ethnic aspirations for regional autonomy did not find a place in the Constitution. In contrast, the Constitution has established a demos-centric parliament while providing that ‘parliament shall consist of three hundred members to be elected in accordance with law from single territorial constituency by direct election’.Footnote 158

One way to make sense of this territorially distributed electoral structure is to view it as showing ‘difference-blindness’ with regard to ethnic diversities. From this perspective, it was consistent with the republican promise of the Bangladesh Constitution. But this difference-blind aspect of the constitutional structure is overshadowed by the ethno-nationalistic promise of the Bengalee state. This is why the constitutional denial of regional autonomy is often seen as part of the chauvinistic project of subsuming the CHT people through forced assimilation to Bengalee nationalism.Footnote 159 Such understanding is also responsible for the ongoing ethnic conflicts that began in the wake of the constitutional refusal to recognize the regional autonomy of the CHT peoples. The discontent ultimately culminated in the ‘macro-nationalist’ claim for separate nationhood to be known as the ‘Jumma nation’.Footnote 160 By resorting to insurgency, the hill people continued the power-sharing demands, including for regional autonomy. In response to this, a political settlement was reached and the CHT Peace Accord was signed between the CHT region and the government of Bangladesh in 1997.

This Accord provides for the Chittagong Hill Tracts Regional Council (CHTRC), giving certain regional autonomy to the communities living only in CHT regions. It mandates two-thirds ethnic representation and also guarantees an ethnic chairman.Footnote 161 This arrangement, in particular the formation of CHTRC, has been appreciated as a ‘paradigmatic improvement in the style of indigenous people’s participation’ and ‘a means of tacitly recognizing their separate cultural and political identity’.Footnote 162 If we situate the Accord in relation to the models suggested by the accommodationists, we may find it shares the features of both the consociation and centripetal models. On one hand, it provides certain forms of autonomy to a group of territorially concentrated ethnic minorities. However, in terms of representative arrangements, it provides for a cross-ethnic electoral constituency by making it subject to the centralized process of deliberative democracy.Footnote 163

Interestingly, this ‘hybrid arrangement’ provided by the Accord was challenged in the case of Mohammad Badiuzzaman on the ground that the alleged accord violated the basic structure of the Constitution. In this case, the petitioner argued:

the cumulative effect of the various clauses of the impugned acts and the creation of the Regional Council is not only that of violating various provisions of the Constitution as mentioned hereinabove, but also of destroying one of the basic structures of the Constitution, namely, the unitary character of the state by supporting to create a territorial unit which eventually may claim the status of a federating unit.Footnote 164

This argument involves the court deciding on the question of structural reform for regional autonomy. Focusing on the regional aspect of the CHTRC, the court accepted the petitioner’s view. In its judgment, the court was satisfied that promoting the interests of people living in a particular territory would destroy the very fabric of the unitary republic. Moreover, the court emphasized the constitutional principle of equality and non-discrimination principles, as shown in the previous part. The heavy implication of such reliance is that the court did not aspire to accept any constitutional structure that may potentially threaten the republican nature of Bangladesh as a state. Instead, such an approach of the court endorses the ‘difference-blindness’ which is consistent with the concept of republican nationalism that we are defending in this article. However, coming from an accommodationist camp, Ridwanul Hoque criticizes such approach of the court:

In its analysis, the Badiuzzaman court failed to appreciate that indigenous self-determination in a unitary State such as Bangladesh can be achieved through ‘a range of possibilities of institutional re-ordering other than the creation of new states,’ or without undermining state sovereignty’. The CHTRC and the transfer to the CHT district councils of certain indigenous-specific powers are definitely innovations of the type that is within the fold of a unitary constitutional order.Footnote 165

For Hoque, the CHTRC and the new model of enhanced Indigenous participation through the district councils could alternatively be seen as an innovative institutional reordering. However, according to him, this ‘innovative’ arrangement should have been approved from the normative perspective of inclusive constitutionalism, ensuring both the recognition and participation-based inclusion of the CHT people. A similar argument is advanced by Mohammad Shahabuddin, who argues that having confined itself to the state’s unitary character, ‘the court failed to offer legal approval to measures that parties to the Accord accepted as crucial elements of peacebuilding in the region’.Footnote 166 His criticism was therefore directed against the structure of the Constitution that ‘conceives of Bangladesh as a unitary national state, thereby limiting the scope for accommodating ethnic differences’.Footnote 167 From this perspective, the court’s disapproval of the consolidation of indigenous self-governance was nothing but the negation of the ‘rival approach [that] recognizes the right of tribal people[s] as distinct peoples’.Footnote 168

This brings us to the question of whether the approval to the regional council for the CHT people would then promote the politics of difference? If so, could it solve the problem of exclusion along ethnic lines? One interesting way of responding to this question is to view the operation of the regional council as reproducing the ethnic minority within its own framework. For example, the Bengalee people living in the CHT region may be viewed as an ethnic minority if seen from a demographic point of view. Even the member of a non-Bengalee community may find that they are in a marginalized community if they do not belong to the ethnic sect having majoritarian control in the political, cultural and economic activities of the region.Footnote 169 Therefore, regional autonomy would not resolve the problem of exclusion; rather, it would create the circularity of exclusion by producing a ‘minority within a minority’. In other words, Bengalee people and other ethnic sects would form new minority groups in the face of a new majority, where ethnicity would never be a vanishing point. Interestingly, the idea of the Jumma nation has already replicated that same logic and the risk of ethnic exclusion among them that they themselves confront in the name of ethnic difference.Footnote 170 In addition, there are other limitations associated with the concept of regional autonomy – that is, it does not include the autonomy of small ethnic communities living on the plain land.Footnote 171 Seen in this light, the demand for regional autonomy contradicts its own logic of non-exclusion.

This circularity of exclusion along the ethnic line helps us understand the limits of ‘ethnic federalism’ as advanced by the advocate of consociation model. The problem with this model is that it validates the use of ethnicity not only as a morally superior value but also as a subject of political mobilization. The implication of this may be counter-productive. It may be detrimental to the condition of Indigenous people, making them more vulnerable than before. An example of this can be found in the case of Malaysian federalism, as explored by Andrew Harding. By carefully analysing the power, structure and intensity of the newly created autonomy (under the tenets of traditional federalism) of Malaysian Indigenous peoples (Sabah and Sarawak), Harding has demonstrated how ethnic federalism in Malaysia brings discontent and division to an ethnically divided society. He concludes that ‘their status within the federation (both constitutional and political), and federal interventions in state politics that have eroded state autonomy’.Footnote 172 Thus, the demand for regional autonomy in the form of ethnic federalism is unable to resolve the problems of exclusion by the means of structural reform.

It does not, however, rule out the possibility of non-ethnic federalism advanced by Horowitz. For Horowitz, federalism is not only a means of distributing power among majority and minority peoples, but also an effective way of removing absolute ethnic majority in a particular region.Footnote 173 This is why non-ethnic federalism is particularly attractive compared with the more overtly consociational features conventionally proposed.Footnote 174 As we suggest, Horowitz’s argument about federalism comes closer to the republican form of federalism supported by Habermas. As acknowledged by Habermas, federalization may work as a possible tool to safeguard cultural autonomy by decentralizing state power.Footnote 175 Unlike ethnic federalism, it does not require the virtue of formally designing state institutions on the basis of ethnic identities. Such a de-ethicized model of federalism is closely linked to the concept of difference-blindness. Insofar as its structural reform is concerned, Bangladesh can therefore adopt this strategy of non-ethnic federalism.Footnote 176 This choice is crucial because it will settle what the Constitution ultimately prioritizes: ethnos as demanded by the advocates of difference or demos as entailed by its vision of becoming a republic.

V. Conclusion

This article argues for de-ethnicizing the Constitution as a response to the problem of ethnic exclusion in Bangladesh. By using the ethnos–demos binary as an explanatory framework, we argue that the real problem of the Bangladesh Constitution lies not in its structural elements or in the architecture of rights – both of which are based on the idea of demos as opposed to ethnos. Instead, it is the ethno-based formulation of identity that sets out its exclusionary paradigm by transforming demos into ethnos. Therefore, a truly inclusive constitution in Bangladesh would entail reversing such logic. Towards that end, we offer the following suggestion. For the identity part, we call for a complete disavowal of Bengalee nationalism and its replacement by the idea of Bangladeshi nationalism; for the rights part, we seek status quo ante; and finally, for the structure part, we only need the status quo of the original constitutional arrangement or, at best, the adoption of non-ethnic federalism.

This demos-centric prescription has been defended in this article not only against conservative ethnonationalism but also against the accommodationist (or multiculturalist) approach of constitutionalism. On one hand, it offers a critical foil for the ethno-nationalistic paradigm of the Bengalee state that amounts to exclusion in the name of assimilation. On the other hand, it distances itself from the accommodationist approach that confronts ethnic assimilation by relying on the politics of difference. Despite sharing similar concerns about assimilation, we do not agree with the accommodationist claim that difference-blindness amounts to forced assimilation and exclusion. Such an understanding is too simple to do justice to the integrationist potential of a difference-blind constitutional arrangement. This is what we take as the point of our departure: we defend the republican promise of difference-blindness. As we believe, it is the vision of the Bengalee state – not the republican arrangement of rights and structure – that stands between us and a truly inclusive constitution in Bangladesh.

Acknowledgements

This article was presented as part of the ‘Issues in Public Laws’ workshop organized by the Bonavero Institute of Human Rights, University of Oxford. We are very grateful to Tarunabh Khaitan, Gehan Gunatilleke, Rehan Abeyratne and other participants in the workshop for their insightful comments. We also wish to express our gratitude to Rosalind Dixon for her useful comments on the earlier draft. Further, we are highly indebted to the anonymous reviewers, whose deep engagement and questions significantly improved this article.

References

1 Jürgen Habermas, The Inclusion of the Others: Studies in Political Theory (Ciaran Cronin and Pablo De Greif (eds) (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998). For the purpose of this article, we will retain the original Greek terms ethnos and demos, both of which designate an aggregate of individuals. See, for people as ethnos and demos, Ferrara, Alessandro, ‘On the Paradox of Deliberative Democracy’, in Michelman, F and Ferrar, Alessandro (eds), Legitimation by Constitution: A Dialogue on Political Liberalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2022) 4445 Google Scholar.

2 Habermas (n 1) 132.

3 Ibid 111.

4 This article builds on the idea that republicanism and liberalism stand as two distinct traditions. There is a complex and long-standing debate around the possibility of ‘liberal-republican hybrid’ on the one hand and their mutual incompatibility on the other. See, for example, Sandel, Michael J, ‘Liberalism and Republicanism: Friends or Foes? A Reply to Richard Dagger’ (1999) 61(2) The Review of Politics 209 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Craig, David, Republicanism versus Liberalism: Towards a Pre-history (2023) 33(1) Intellectual History Review 101 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Patten, Alan, ‘The Republican Critique of Liberalism’ (1996) 26(1) British Journal of Political Science 25 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Habermas (n 1) xxii.

6 The Constitution of Bangladesh begins with the performative expression ‘We, the People’, which signifies the demos-centric construction of the republic. Further, article 1 of the Constitution declares that ‘Bangladesh is a unitary, independent, sovereign Republic to be known as the People’s Republic of Bangladesh’. See the Constitution of the People’s Republic of Bangladesh 1972.

7 For a detailed discussion of three approaches of constitutionalism, see McGarry, John, O’Leary, Brendan and Simeon, Richard, ‘Integration or Accommodation? The Enduring Debate in Conflict Regulation’, in Choudhury, Sujit (ed.), Constitutional Design for Divided Societies: Integration or Accommodation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008)Google Scholar.

8 According to the Bangladesh Population and Housing Census 2011, the vast majority of the people – 98 per cent – are ethnically Bengalee and other 2 per cent are from other minor ethnic non-Bengalee groups living in Bangladesh. In 2022, new statistics were gathered, but are yet to be released. See Bangladesh Population and Housing Census 2011, vols 1, 2 and 3, prepared by Bangladesh Bureau of Statistics, Statistics and Informatics Division, and Ministry of Planning.

9 For instance, McGarry, O’Leary and Simeon (n 7) 42 state that, ‘Assimilationists seek the erosion of private cultural and other sorts of difference among citizens as well as the creation of a common public identity, through either fusion or acculturation. Fusion involves two or more communities mixing to form something new (A + B = C). Acculturation involves one community adopting the culture of another and being absorbed into it (A + B = A). Assimilation, therefore, erodes both the public and private differences between and among groups.’

10 McGarry, O’Leary and Simeon (n 7) 42.

11 ‘Integrationists believe political instability and conflict result from group-based partisanship in political institutions … To avoid the ethnically partisan state, integrationists counsel against the ethnicization of political parties or civic associations.’ McGarry, O’Leary and Simeon (n 7) 45–46; Lipset, Seymour Martin, Political Man: The Social Bases of Politics (London: Heinemann, 1983) 1213 Google Scholar.

12 Choudhury, Sujit (ed.), Constitutional Design for Divided Societies: Integration or Accommodation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008) 27 Google Scholar.

13 The August 1975 coup paved the way for the emergence of the military rule in Bangladesh. The first regime ruled by the military leader continued from 1975 to 1981. During this regime, some changes were made to the constitution by issuing martial law proclamations. The Fifth Amendment Act was passed by the Jatiya Sangsad on 6 April 1979 to validate all the changes to the constitution. See, Constitution (Fifth Amendment) Act 1979 (Act I of 1979)

14 This amendment has provided that the citizens of Bangladesh shall be known as Bangladeshi while the people will be considered as Bengalees as a nation, regardless of their ethnic differences. The Constitution of Bangladesh, article 6(2) states that, ‘The people of Bangladesh shall be known as Bangalees as a nation and the citizens of Bangladesh shall be known as Bangladeshies.’

15 Constitution (Fifteenth Amendment) Act 2011 (Act XIV of 2011).

16 Constitution of Bangladesh, article 23A.

17 The Chittagong Hill Tracks Peace Accord of 1997 was a political peace agreement signed between the Government of Bangladesh and the United People’s Party of the Chittagong Hill Tracts (the political organisation that controlled the militia in CHT region) on 2 December 1997. This peace accord was adopted as a sign of peace that would address the demand for distinctive structural autonomy to the CHT people. See for detailed background stories on this Peace Accord, Bushra Hasina Chowdhury, Building Lasting Peace: Issues of the Implementation of the Chittagong Hill Tracts Accord Urbana-Champaign, IL: Program in Arms Control, Disarmament, and International Security (ACDIS), University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, 2002); Mohsin, Amena, ‘Chittagong Hill Tracts Peace Accord, 1997’, in Islam, Sirajul, Jamal, Ahmed A (eds), Banglapedia: National Encyclopedia of Bangladesh (Dhaka: Asiatic Society of Bangladesh, 2012)Google Scholar; Shelley, Mizanur Rahman, The Chittagong Hill Tracts of Bangladesh: The Untold Story (Dakhar: Centre for Development Research, Bangladesh, 1992)Google Scholar; Rashiduzzaman, M, ‘Bangladesh’s Chittagong Hill Tracts Peace Accord: Institutional Features and Strategic Concerns’ (1998) 38(7) Asian Survey 653 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

18 For the purpose of this article, we use the accommodationist approach interchangeably with communitarianism and multiculturalism.

19 McGarry, O’Leary and Simeon (n 7) 52.

20 See Manabendra Narayan Larma’s speech in The Bangladesh Constituent Assembly Debates 1972, 2(13) 536. Borhan U Khan and MM Rahman, Protection of Minorities: Regimes, Norms and Issues in South Asia (Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2012) esp. Ch 5.3, 72–83.

21 See, for example, Hoque, Ridwanul, ‘Inclusive Constitutionalism and the Indigenous People of the Chittagong Hill Tracts in Bangladesh’ in Singh, Mahendra Pal (ed.), The Indian Yearbook of Comparative Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016)Google Scholar.

22 See, for example, Shahabuddin, Mohammad, Minorities and the Making of Postcolonial States in International Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2021)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

23 Republican integration may be viewed as a specific variety of communitarianism. Like communitarianism, republicanism values citizenship, or membership in a political community, but such community is ‘distinct from other kinds of community based on pre-political commonality, of, for example, race, religion or culture’. For such distinction between republican and communitarian, see Honohan, Iseult, Civic Republicanism (London: Routledge, 2002) 8Google Scholar.

24 McGarry, O’Leary and Simeon (n 7) 85.

25 See ‘Indigenous Peoples in Bangladesh’, <https://www.iwgia.org/en/bangladesh.html#:~:text=The%20government%20of%20Bangladesh%20does,the%20Bengali%20population%20are%20mentioned>. However, this demographic configuration of minority people can still be said to constitute the national minority in Kymlicka’s term. For the distinction between national minority and multicultural citizenship, see Will Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995)

26 Amena Mohsin, The Chittagong Hill Tracts, Bangladesh: On the Difficult Road to Peace (New York: International Peace Academy, 2003).

27 McGarry, O’Leary and Simeon (n 7) 85: ‘Integration may also be successful with minorities that are small in number and interspersed among others and well-disposed to the strategy.’

28 Reilly, Benjamin, Democracy in Divided Societies: Electoral Engineering for Conflict Management (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001) 4CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

29 Ibid; Reilly, Benjamin and Reynolds, Andrew, Electoral Systems and Conflict in Divided Societies: Papers on International Conflict 2 (Washington, DC: National Academies Press, 1999) 3Google Scholar. Horowitz, Donald L, A Democratic South Africa: Constitutional Engineering in a Divided Society? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000)Google Scholar. For more detailed definition of divided society, see Rabushka, A and Shepsle, K, Politics in Plural Societies: A Theory of Democratic Instability (Columbus, OH: Merrill, 1972)Google Scholar.

30 The ethnic political party has never been a catalyst for political mobilization (such as voting, power mapping or sharing) here. One empirical account of it is that so far only two regional political parties have been formed, which had not influenced that expressly – at least in the national election sphere. More interestingly, the ethnic politicians who have so far competed and won almost all did so from under the banner of mainstream political parties. See <http://www.parliament.gov.bd/index.php/en/mps/role-of-mps>.

31 In this respect, we endorse the view of those scholars who argued that careful and purposive institutional design is a necessary precondition to promote stable democracy in divided societies. See, for example, the argument of Horowitz (n 29). See also Przeworski, Adam, ʻDemocracy as the Contingent Outcome of Conflictsʼ, in Elster, Jon and Slagstad, Rune (eds), Constitutionalism and Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988) 304 Google Scholar.

32 Joseph Raz (comments: Jewish and Democratic State) ‘The State of Israel’, in Michael Walzer, Menachem Lorberbaum and Noam J Zohar (eds), The Jewish Political Tradition: Volume 1– Authority (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press).

33 Constitution of Bangladesh, article 9 states that, ‘The unity and solidarity of the Bengalee nation, which, deriving its identity from its language and culture, attained sovereign and independent Bangladesh through a united and determined struggle in the war of independence, shall be the basis of Bengalee nationalism.’

34 See The Bangladesh Constituent Assembly Debate (1972).

35 Serajul Islam Chowdhury, ‘Beyond Nationalism, Within Aspirations and Achievements’, The Daily Star, 26 March 2014.

36 Ibid.

37 Ruth Gavison, however, provides a defence for the idea of ‘Jewish and democratic state’. She forcefully argues about the reconcilability between the liberal democracy and the Jewish nationalism while claiming that Israel is both ‘proudly Jewish and strongly democratic’. See Ruth Gavison, ‘The Jew’s Right to Statehood: A Defense’ (2003) 5763 AZURE 74.

38 Raz (n 32) 510.

39 Ibid 513.

40 Ibid.

41 Ibid 511.

42 Ibid.

43 Masri, Mizen, The Dynamics of Exclusionary Constitutionalism: Israel as a Jewish and Democratic State (Oxford: Hart, 2017) 4Google Scholar.

44 Jewish nationalism prioritizes people from a Jewish background over non-Jewish Muslim community members living in Israel. However, through Bengalee nationalism, the constitution forcefully obliged non-Bengalee ethnic people to become outright Bengalee.

45 Constitution of Bangladesh, article 6.

46 The Bangladesh Constituent Assembly Debates 1972; Yasmin, L., ‘The Tyranny of the Majority in Bangladesh: The Case of the Chittagong Hill Tracts’ (2014) 20 Nationalism and Ethnic Politics 116 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

47 The Bangladesh Constituent Assembly Debates 1972

48 Hoque (n 21) 224; see also Raja Tridiv Roy, The Departed Melody (Islamabad: PPA Publications, 2003) 330–31. Interestingly, during the debate one of the women-members put a counter-question to such demand of ethnic recognition that ‘today they [the ethnic groups in Bangladesh] are too independent. Is not it more prestigious to be recognized as a nation than as an indigenous? See The Bangladesh Constituent Assembly 1972 ([Mrs Sajeda Chowdhury, 25 October 1972].

49 Hoque (n 21) 224.

50 Margaret Davies situates such exclusionary feature in the image of unified sovereignty. She argues that a constitution subscribing to the idea of modern sovereignty is inherently exclusionary, as it ‘involves a setting apart of one nation and one legal order from neighbouring jurisdictions, and it therefore excludes, and forms identities, nations, and social order through exclusion.’ See Davies, Margaret, ‘Exclusion and the Constitution’ (2000) 25(2) Australian Journal of Legal Philosophy 297 Google Scholar.

51 Constitution (Fifteenth Amendment) Act 2011 (Act XIV of 2011).

52 Constitution of Bangladesh, article 6. See n 14 for details.

53 See Salt, Karen, The Unfinished Revolution Haiti, Black Sovereignty and Power in the Nineteenth-Century Atlantic World (Liverpool: Liverpool University Press, 2019) 13 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Gaffield, Julia, ‘Complexities of Imagining Haiti: A Study of National Constitutions, 1801–1807’ (2007) 41(1) Journal of Social History 81 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Julia Gaffield, ‘Meet Haiti’s founding Father, Whose Black Revolution was Too Radical for Thomas Jefferson’, The Conversation, 30 August 2018, <https://theconversation.com/meet-haitis-founding-father-whose-black-revolution-was-too-radical-for-thomas-jefferson-101963>.

54 Constitution of Bangladesh, article 23A.

55 See, for example, Roy, Raja Devasish, ‘Challenges for Juridical Pluralism and Customary Laws of Indigenous Peoples: The Case of the Chittagong Hill Tracts Bangladesh’ (2004) 21(1) Arizona Journal of International and Comparative Law 113Google Scholar; Shahbuddin, Muhammad, ‘The Myth of Colonial Protection of Indigenous Peoples: The Case of Chittagong Hill Tracts Under British Rule’ (2018) 25 International Journal On Minority and Group Rights 210 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Farhat Jahan, Indigenous Identity Disputes in Democratic Bangladesh (Southern Paper Series, 2015, CLACSO); Raja Devasish Roy, Traditional Customary Laws and Indigenous People in Asia (Minority Rights Group International, 2005); Rajkumari Chandra Kalindi Roy, Land Rights of the Indigenous Peoples of the Chittagong Hill Tracts, Bangladesh (IWGIA Document No. 99, Copenhagen, 2000); Pereira, FaustinaThe Chittagong Hill Tracts Peace Accord and the Long Road to Peace: A Case Study’, in Castellino, Joshua and Walsh, Niamh (eds), International Law and Indigenous Rights (Leiden: Nijhoff, 2005)Google Scholar; Solotaroff, Jennifer L, Kotikula, Aphichoke, Lonnberg, Tara, Ali, Snigdha and Jahan, Ferdous, Voices to Choices: Bangladesh’s Journey in Women’s Economic Empowerment (New York: World Bank, 2019)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sumon, Mahmudul H, Ethnicity and Adivasi Identity in Bangladesh (London: Routledge, 2022)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; King, Elisabeth and Samii, Cyrus, Diversity, , Violence, and Recognition: How Recognizing Ethnic Identity Promotes Peace (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Holden, Livia, Legal Pluralism and Governance in South Asia and Diasporas (London: Routledge, 2016)Google Scholar.

56 Hoque (n 21) 235.

57 Ibid.

58 Hossain, Kamal, Bangladesh: Quest for Freedom and Justice (Dhaka: University Press, 2013), Ch. 9 Google Scholar.

59 He claims ‘the recent arrangement, however deficient it might be, can be seen as an expression of plurality-consciousness from the top policymakers’. Hoque (n 21) 228.

60 Hoque (n 21) 235, 228, 218.

61 Shahabuddin (n 22) 189.

62 Ibid 189.

63 He claims that the denial of the status of an indigenous people results in downgrading these groups legal status and the hill people of the CHT in Bangladesh is a pertinent example of such consequence. Shahabuddin (n 22) 237. See for similar argument, Shahjahan Mondol, ‘Recognition of Indigenous People,’ The Daily Star, 27 August 2014, <https://www.thedailystar.net/recognition-of-indigenous-people-38812>.

64 McGarry, O’Leary and Simeon (n 7) 52.

65 See Taylor, Charles, ‘The Politics of Recognition’, in Gutmann, Amy (ed.), Multiculturalism and Examining the Politics of Recognition (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992).Google Scholar

66 Laborde, Cécile, Critical Republicanism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015) 230 Google Scholar

67 Miller considers himself a liberal nationalist. For his defence of liberal nationalism, see Miller, David, ‘The Coherence of Liberal Nationalism’, in Gustavsson, Gina, and Miller, David (eds), Liberal Nationalism and Its Critics: Normative and Empirical Questions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019)Google Scholar. Despite this, there is also powerful evidence that his nationalism was more republican than liberal. For example, Bojan Ratkovic argues that Miller’s theory forms the foundations of republican nationalism, a unique strand of nationalist theory that is distinct from liberal nationalism. See Bojan, Ratkovic, ‘Republican Nationalism: Nations, Cultures, and Politics’ (2016), <https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/3700>.

68 See, in general, Miller, David, On Nationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995)Google Scholar; Miller, David, Citizenship and National Identity (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2000)Google Scholar; Miller, David, National Responsibility and Global Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

69 Miller, Citizenship and National Identity (n 68).

70 Ibid 3. [Emphasis added].

71 Ibid 5.

72 Helder De Schutter and Ronald Tinnevelt, ‘Is Liberal Nationalism Incompatible With Global Democracy?’ (2009) 40(1) Metaphilosophy 109.

73 The use of ‘nation’ in the context of French republic was based on the concept of demos, which makes it the opposite of ethnic origin. See Jansen, Yolande, Secularism, Assimilation and the Crisis of Multiculturalism: French Modernist Legacies (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2013) 205 Google Scholar.

74 Miller’s idea of republican citizenship comes closer to the Habermasian vision of civic citizenship, although Habermas advances his idea in relation to post-national identity while Miller seeks confines the nationality connection within the national borders. What is common in their approach is that they seek to transform the nationality connection from ‘substantive consensus on values’ to the ‘procedural consensus on legitimacy’.

75 Iseult Honohan’s idea of ‘civic republicanism’ perhaps provides a useful explanation of this difference. She defines republicanism as a middle ground between the extremes in the liberalism–communitarianism divide. He claims that republicanism has a richer salience of political community than libertarian spectrum of liberalism, but is less homogenizing and exclusive than liberal nationalism and other forms of communitarianism. Honohan (n 23) 2-5

76 It may, however, be useful to note that, even if Miller is considered a liberal nationalist, he was against the logic of assimilation in which ‘minority groups should be forced to abandon their native cultures in order to assimilate to a single national culture’. In contrast, he shows how republican nationality offers a procedural check against assimilation and argues that a deliberative system of political representation can prevent the imposition of oppressive norms. Miller, Citizenship and National Identity (n 68) 76.

77 For example, Martha Nussbaum defends ‘nonestablishment’ of religion by appeal to liberal neutrality. Nussbaum, Martha, Liberty of Conscience: In Defense of America’s Tradition of Religious Equality (New York: Basic Books, 2008)Google Scholar.

78 For instances, the original Constitution provided for Bengali nationalism, but the term changed from Bengalee to Bangladeshi during the military regime, which was later given constitutional validation by the Fifth Amendment. This position was later changed and the original Bengali nationalism in the constitution was restored by the Fifteenth Amendment. See also Constitution (Fifth Amendment) Act 1979 (Act I of 1979).

79 Shahabuddin (n 22) 188.

80 Part II (articles 8–25) of the Constitution of Bangladesh specified some principles, such as: nationalism, socialism, democracy, human rights, economic, social and cultural rights. But these principles are mere interpretative aid to the government, and cannot be judicially enforceable. They are not considered as ‘law’ This was reasserted in the case of Kudrat- E-Elahi Panir and Others v. Bangladesh (1992), where Justice Mustafa Kamal held that to equate ‘principles’ [embodied in Part II] with ‘laws’ is to go against the Law of the Constitution itself’ 44 DLR (AD) 1992, 320. From this point of view, article 6 has greater normative force than article 8, which prescribes the Islamic ideal to be a fundamental principle.

81 However, this implication is often undermined by those who could not acknowledge the difference between article 6, which provides a juridical formulation of identity, and article 8, under which Islamization of values remains as a weakly contra-judicative principle. Shahabuddin (n 22).

82 For a powerful account on the relationship between neutrality and republican idea of solidarity, see Laborde (n 66).

83 For an account of national state for this context, Mohammad Shahabuddin, ‘The Ideology of the Postcolonial State in Indian Constituent Assembly Debates (1946–50)’ (2022) 32(1) Dhaka University Law Journal 266.

84 Stéphanie Hennette Vauchez, ‘Is French laïcité Still Liberal? The Republican Project Under Pressure (2004–15) (2017) 17(2) Human Rights Law Review 285.

85 For example, Marion Young argues that republicans are committed to an ideal of impartiality, which enforced homogeneity by acting to the disadvantage of those groups in society she identifies as oppressed, including women and ethnic minorities. See, IM Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1990). From the perspective of republican nationality, David Miller responds to such charge made by Young by arguing that ‘she equates the ideal of national unity with the logic of assimilation’. Miller, Citizenship and National Identity (n 68) 76. See also for a critique of Young on this issue, Fraser, N, ‘Recognition or Redistribution: A Critical Reading of Iris Young’s Justice and the Politics of Difference ’ (1995) 3 Journal of Political Philosophy 166 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

86 See Jansen (n 73) 204.

87 Articles 1 and 2 of the 1905 Law of Separation Between Church and State.

88 Laborde (n 66) 33.

89 Offering a rich genealogical account of the term laïcité, Sylvie Le Grand concludes that, ‘With the emergence of laïcité as a term, a transfer of sacrality takes place, a new republican and laïque form of the sacred is established, a civic religion à la française. Le Grand, Sylvie, ‘The Origin of the Concept of laïcité in Nineteenth Century France’ in Eggert, Marion and Hölscher, Lucian (eds), Religion and Secularity (Leiden: Brill, 2013) 74 Google Scholar.

90 For example, Charles Renouvier argues that laïque morality should explicitly aim to ‘take minds away from superstitious beliefs’. This leads Maclure and Taylor to argue that Renouvier advocated for laïcité’s moral supremacy over all religions. See Maclure, Jocelyn and Taylor, Charles, Secularism and Freedom of Conscience (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

91 Jansen (n 73) 287.

92 See Vauchez (n 84).

93 Patten, Alan, ‘Beyond the Dichotomy of Universalism and Difference: Four Responses to Cultural Diversity’, in Choudhury, Sujit (ed.), Constitutional Design for Divided Societies: Integration or Accommodation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008) 95 Google Scholar.

94 For example, Taylor and Maclure argue to revive the French Republican tradition of laicism as opposed to the civic unity variant. See Maclure and Taylor (n 90).

95 Pettit, Philip, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000)Google Scholar.

96 The preamble of the Constitution of Bangladesh starts with ‘We, the people of Bangladesh, having proclaimed our independence on the 26th day of March, 1971’.

97 Habermas (n 1) 3.

98 The Constitution (Fifteenth Amendment) Act XIV of 2011.

99 Larma’s speech (n 20).

100 Chowdhury, Rokeya, ‘The Doctrine of Basic Structure in Bangladesh: From “Calf-Path” to Matryoshka Dolls’ (2014) 14(1&2) Bangladesh Journal of Law 43 Google Scholar.

101 Constitution of Bangladesh, article 28 states that, ‘the State shall not discriminate against any citizen on grounds only of religion, race, caste, sex or place of birth’, and also that, on these grounds, no citizen shall be ineligible for or discriminated against in respect of any employment or office in the service of the Republic. In addition, article 27 provides for constitutional guarantees of equality before law and equality of opportunities.

102 Historically, the ethnic people have argued for their constitutional rights and demanded them from the different governments from time to time. The political parties also used this as a bargaining tool to gain power in politics. Most recently, in its 2009 election manifestation, the Awami League promised its ethnic demands.

103 Constitution of Bangladesh, article 23A

104 Chowdhury (n 100) 75.

105 Kudrat- E-Elahi Panir and Others v. Bangladesh (1992).

106 Khaitan, Tarunabh, ‘Constitutional Directives: Morally Committed Political Constitutionalism’ (2019) 82(4) Modern Law Review 613 Google Scholar.

107 Jacobsohn, G, ‘Constitutional Identity’ in Choudhry, S, Khosla, M and Mehta, PB (eds), Oxford Handbook of the Indian Constitution (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016)Google Scholar.

108 Tarunabh Khaitan (n 106) 626. He defined constitutional directive more as an ‘obligatory telic norms’ that is ‘deferred to a future date’ for its actual realization. (631) He also described these directives as ‘weakly contra-judicative’ yet the best ‘tool to realize a morally-committed conception of political constitutionalism’. (603) For him, the directive speaks of political constitutionalism because they operate only for ‘initiating and legitimizing political action.’ (632). Tarunabh shows how the right dose of expressive polyvocality, used by the framers, can be able to ‘fine-tune the relative weights they [framers] wish to assign to the identification thesis and its antithesis’ (625).

109 Roy (2004) (n 55); Roy (2005) (n 55); Roy (2000) (n 55).

110 Tully, James, Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

111 Ibid 183.

112 Ibid 184.

113 Tarunabh’s idea of value pluralism is consistent, as he argues, with liberal constitutionalism. But Tully’s argument shows less faith in the reconcilability between pluralism and modern constitutionalism.

114 For instance, see other multiculturalists such as Kymlicka (n 25) and W Norman, ‘Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory’ (1994) 104(2) Ethics 352 for more multiculturalist arguments, where he argued for three types of rights: special representation rights (for disadvantaged groups); multicultural rights (for immigrant and religious groups); and self-government rights (for national minorities).

115 See Shahabuddin (n 22) 71, 196, where he argues in favour of groups or collective rights to mitigate the current ethnic crisis by mentioning the group rights as ‘an effective response to ethnic conflicts that requires that group rights be accommodated in one form or the other’.

116 Shahabuddin (n 22) 72.

117 See Constitution of Bangladesh articles 27, 28 and 29, which in general stated the equality and non-discrimination principles especially article 28(1) which stated that the state shall not discriminate against any citizen on grounds only of religion, race, caste, sex or place of birth.

118 Writ Petition No. 2669 (2000) before the High Court Division of the Supreme Court of Bangladesh. See also Writ Petition No. 6451 (2007), which challenged the legality of the CHT Peace Accord itself.

119 It stipulated the violation of the Act on the following grounds: (i) a non-tribal person shall not be able to contest the election of a District Council; (ii) a person who is not a permanent resident of a district cannot be a voter; (iii) preference will be given to tribal people in the Police Service; and (iv) no land in the CHT will be transferred without prior permission from the Council under section 6 (Uo) of the impugned Acts, 1998, section 11 of the impugned Acts, 1998, section 15 (Kha) of Rangamati and Khagrachari Hill District Acts, 1998 and Section 27 of the Bandarban Hill District Acts, 1998, the new section 64 of the impugned Acts respectively. See Mohammad Badiuzzaman v. Bangladesh and Others, para. 17.

120 He criticized such an approach of court by saying that ‘the court failed to offer legal approval to measures that parties to the Accord accepted as crucial elements of peacebuilding in the region’. See Shahabuddin (n 22)195.

121 Shahabuddin (n 22)196.

122 Patten (n 93) 101. [Emphasis added].

123 Interestingly, Shahabuddin earlier also disagreed with Kymlicka’s view that group rights can be organized under the framework of liberalism. See Mohammad Shahabuddin, ‘Liberal Understanding, Shortcoming, and Controversy apropos Group Rights: Do We Need a Different Paradigm?’ (2007) 16(1) Yokohama Law Review 155.

124 Among other accommodationists, Kymlicka and Raz also want these kinds of arrangements of right. See Joseph Raz, Multiculturalism (2002) 11(3) Ratio Juris 193; Kymlicka (n 25).

125 There are some important differences between the republican and liberal conceptions of rights. See, for example, Miller, Citizenship and National Identity (n 68) 59–60. One such distinction comes from institutional perspective: liberals make the judiciary as the supreme arbiters of constitutional rights, while in the republican model, the arrangement of rights depends on the constitutional politics grounded in public policy and deliberate discussion. This distinction should be read in light of ‘difference-blindness’ as it may be found in liberalism – particularly in the non-communitarian spectrum of it – but it stands on the idea of disestablishment, which makes it different from the non-interventionist logic of liberal rights.

126 Habermas (n 1) xxxvii. [Emphasis added].

127 Habermas, Jürgen, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, trans. Rehg, William (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996) 118–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

128 See John Capps, ‘Pragmatism, Feminism, and the Sameness-Difference Debate’ (1996) 32(1) Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 65; Joan Chalmers Williams, ‘Dissolving the Sameness/Difference Debate: A Post-modern Path Beyond Essentialism in Feminist and Critical Race Theory’ (1991) Duke Law Journal 296; Liff, Sonia and Wajcman, Judy, ‘“Sameness” and “Difference” Revisited: Which Way Forward for Equal Opportunity Initiatives?’ (1996) 33(1) Journal of Management Studies 79 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

129 Kapur, Ratna, ‘Gender Equality’, in Choudhry, Sujit, Khosla, Madhav and Mehta, Pratap Bhanu (eds), The Oxford Handbook of the Indian Constitution (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016)Google Scholar; Kapur, Ratna, ‘Un-Veiling Equality: Disciplining the “Other” Woman Through Human Rights Discourse’, in Emon, Anver M, Ellis, Mark and Glahn, Benjamin (eds), Islamic Law and International Human Rights Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012)Google Scholar.

130 Littletone, Cristine, ‘Restructuring Sexual Equality’, in Bartlett, Katharine T and Kennedy, Rosanne (eds), Feminist Legal Theory (London: Routledge, 1991)Google Scholar.

131 Iris Marion Young, ‘Polity and Group Difference: A Critique of the Ideal of Universal Citizenship’ (1989) 99(2) Ethics 250. [Emphasis added].

132 Ibid.

133 Ward, Cynthia V, ‘On Difference and Equality’ (1997) 3(1) Legal Theory 65 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

134 Sheila Foster, ‘Difference and Equality: A Critical Assessment of the Concept of ‘Diversity’ (1993) 1 Wisconsin Law Review 105.

135 Laborde (n 66).

136 See Weston, P, Speaking of Equality: An Analysis of the Rhetorical Force of ‘Equality’ in Moral and Legal Discourse (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2016)Google Scholar; B Paul Komisar and Jerrold R Coombs, ‘The Concept of Equality in Education’ (1964) 3 Studies in Philosophy and Education 223.

137 See Macmillan, CJB, ‘Equality and Sameness’ (1964) 3(4) Studies in Philosophy and Education 320 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

138 See Foster, Peter, Gomm, Roger and Hammersley, Martyn, Constructing Educational Inequality: A Methodological Assessment (London: Routledge, 1996)Google Scholar.

139 There may, however, be a contrasting argument that ‘difference theorists are necessarily anti-equality’. See Ward, Cynthia V, ‘On Difference and Equality’ (1997) 3(1) Legal Theory 65 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

140 Constitution of Bangladesh, article 28.

141 Constitution of Bangladesh, article 29 (3)(a).

142 In this series of decisions, notably in the Badiuzzaman decision (as discussed in the subsequent section), the court even termed the CHT Regulation a ‘dead law’ and consequently as ‘unconstitutional’.

143 Civil Appeal No. 147 of 2007 (judgement 2 December 2014).

144 It is because the ethnic groups in Bangladesh are not recognized as aboriginals or Indigenous, which is why they are constitutionally called ethnic sects. However, for the first time the court addressed them as ‘Indigenous people’. See Hoque (n 21) 223.

145 Apart from the two models on which we have chosen to focus, ‘communalism’ is also considered an accommodationist strategy to respond to the problem of ethic exclusion. For a useful discussion on these models, see Benjamin Reilly, ‘Political Engineering: Consociationalism, Centripetalism, and Communalism’, in Reilly (n 28). See also McGarry, O’Leary and Simeon (n 7).

146 The major essays of Lijphart can be found in Lijphart, Arend, Thinking About Democracy: Power Sharing and Majority Rule in Theory and Practice (London: Routledge, 2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Arend Lijphart, ‘Typologies of Democratic Systems’ (1968) 1 Comparative Political Studies 3; Arend Lijphart, ‘Consociational Democracy’ (1969) 21 World Politics 207; Arend Lijphart, Democracy in Plural Societies: A Comparative Exploration (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1977); Arend Lijphart, ‘Consociation and Federation: Conceptual and Empirical Links’ (1979) 12 Canadian Journal of Political Science 499; Lijphart, Arend, Power-Sharing in South Africa (University of California Press, 1985)Google Scholar; Lijphart, Arend, ‘The Evolution of Consociational Theory and Constitutional Practices’ (2002) 37(11) Acta Politica 1965 Google Scholar; Lijphart, Arend, ‘The Wave of Power-Sharing Democracy’, in Reynolds, Andrew (ed.), The Architecture of Democracy: Constitutional Design, Conflict Management and Democracy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002)Google Scholar; see generally Lijphart, Arend and Waisman, Carlos H (eds), Institutional Design in New Democracies: Eastern Europe and Latin America (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1996)Google Scholar.

147 McGarry, O’Leary and Simeon (n 7) 58

148 The fundamental point of consociation is to build a common mechanism under which all the ethnic communities will take part in political institutions. However, such political participation does not necessarily mean achieving a complete representation of all groups other than major groups of ethnic representation. In this way, the plurality of consociation is achieved in a divided society.

149 To be more specific, Lijphart advocated for a list proportional representation system, which he believed would facilitate ‘discipline and control’ by party leaders by ‘making the consociational settlement more stable’. Other wings of this model also advocate for a single transferable vote, which they think will be more equipped with maintaining power-sharing processes in the election. See McGarry, O’Leary and Simeon (n 7) 59–60.

150 Community self-government is meant by Lijphart as a functional autonomy by which both the governing system and territorial autonomy will be preserved, such as schooling, operation of personal laws, separate public funds for media and others. See Sujit Book, ‘Bat Ye’or, The Dhimmi: Jews and Christians Under Islam (Maisel, David, Fenton, Paul & Littman, David trans.) (Rutherford, NJ: Fairleigh Dickinson University Press, 1985)Google Scholar; see generally Braude, Benjamin and Lewis, Bernard (eds), Christians and Jews in the Ottoman Empire: The Functioning of a Plural Society: The Arabic Speaking Lands (Princeton, NJ: Holmes & Meier)Google Scholar.

151 Horowitz (n 29); Horowitz, Donald L, Ethnic Groups in Conflict (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1985)Google Scholar.

152 Reilly (n 28); Reilly and Reynolds (n 29) 2.

153 Reilly (n 145) 84–85.

154 Ibid 84–85.

155 See Mohammad Badiuzzaman v. Bangladesh and Others, para. 10; Shahabuddin (n 22) 187.

156 Lijphart, Democracy in Plural Societies (n 146) 41. It is to be noted that the plan of Larma was merely a proposal and was in its initial stage. If the opportunity arose to form a structural autonomy, then the institutional plans might change significantly. However, the outlines and the logical consequence of such plans suggest that that alleged structural autonomy, if accepted, would be able to culminate to change the institutional characteristics along with the associated elements for a strong consociation.

157 Quoted in Mohammad Badiuzzaman v. Bangladesh and Others, para. 10.

158 Constitution of Bangladesh, article 65(2). [Emphasis added].

159 See The Bangladesh Constituent Assembly Debates 1972.

160 Since the mid-1980s, the hill people have been referred to as the ‘Jumma nation’.

161 Part 3 of this Accord provides that a chairman of the CHTRC will be elected indirectly and other members (of which two-thirds will be ethnic representatives) will be elected directly and proportionately from the communities living there. Since there are officially eleven communities with Chakma being the dominant ethnic community, five persons will be elected from the Chakma tribe, three persons from the Marma tribe, two persons from the Tripura tribe, one person from the Murung and Tanchangya tribes, and one person from the Lusai, Bawm, Pankho, Khumi, Chak and Khiyang tribes.

162 Hoque (n 21) 231. See also Ahmmed, Md. Matiul Hoque Masud, Md. Faisal and Md. Niaz Morshed, ‘The Chittagong Hill Tracts Peace Accord in Bangladesh: An Overview’ (2013) 4(4) Mediterranean Journal of Social Sciences 123.

163 However, there are powerful critique advanced by the advocate of difference. See for a critique of deliberative democracy, L Sanders, ‘Against Deliberation’ (1997) 25 Political Theory 347; Young, IM, ‘Communication and the Other: Beyond Deliberative Democracy’, in Benhabib, S (ed.), Democracy and Difference (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar; Young, IM, ‘Difference as a Resource for Democratic Communication’, in Bohman, James and Rehg, William (eds), Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press)Google Scholar.

164 Writ Petition No. 2669 (2000) before the High Court Division of the Supreme Court of Bangladesh. See Shahabuddin (n 22) 193–94.

165 Hoque (n 21) 232. [Emphasis added].

166 Shahabuddin (n 22) 195. He does, however, have a differing position about the Peace Accord. While acknowledging that the Peace Accord offered some regional autonomy, he has criticized it on the ground that it denied any constitutional recognition of the distinct identity of the hill communities. This is because the Accord uses the term ‘tribal’ (Upojati in Bengali, meaning sub-nation).

167 Shahabuddin (n 22) 137.

168 Hoque (n 21) 232.

169 A careful analysis reveals deeper aspects of the problem and its consequences. First, the electoral system is gerrymandered in such a way that it only absorbs the ethnic elite community in its system and excludes other less-dominant community automatically from being elected in that region. For instance, the past statistics of the elected parliament members’ lists for the last eleven parliaments show that most members are elected from the predominant elite-ethnic groups and also from same lineage. Thus, the ethnic political participation and representation from CHT regions fundamentally comes from the elite-pedigree relationship. Therefore, this system automatically has facilitated the partial and total exclusion of the less-predominant ethnic communities and the plain land communities from its ethnic political participation and representation respectively.

170 This is because one minority group invoking the right to self-determination within a state may produce another minority group, which may in turn invoke the same logic of ethnicity to claim its right to self-determination. This circularity of right to self-determination ultimately constitutes circularity of exclusion.

171 It is important to note that the CHT peace treaty only mentions eleven ethnic communities living in the CHT region, with Chakma constituting the dominant ethnic group. However, there are other ethnic communities residing in the northern part of Bangladesh – for instance, Sonthals. Although there is no official statement regarding the number of ethnic groups living in Bangladesh, a mainstream Indigenous organization claims about 54 ethnic communities. See <https://www.iwgia.org/en/bangladesh.html#:~:text=The%20government%20of%20Bangladesh%20does,the%20Bengali%20population%20are%20mentioned>.

172 Harding, Andrew, ‘“A Measure of Autonomy”: Federalism as Protection For Malaysia’s Indigenous Peoples’ (2018) 46 Federal Law Review 570 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

173 McGarry, O’Leary and Simeon (n 7) 55.

174 Pildes, Richard H, ‘Ethnic Identity and Democratic Institutions: A Dynamic Perspective’, in Choudhury, Sujit (ed.), Constitutional Design for Divided Societies: Integration or Accommodation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008) 198 Google Scholar.

175 Habermas, Jürgen, ‘The Struggles for Recognition in the Democratic Constitutional State’, in Gutmann, Amy (ed.), Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press) 128 Google Scholar.

176 However, we should note that article 7B of the Constitution of Bangladesh entrenched (made unamendable) some of the important fundamental features of the constitution. These unamendable features also include the unitary nature of the state, thus making the possibility of transforming Bangladesh into a federation more difficult. These features were initially identified by the famous case Anwar Hossain Chowdhury v. Bangladesh (1989), which would later be constitutionalized by the Fifteenth Amendment of the Constitution.