Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-nr4z6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-09T05:12:34.293Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Political Solidarity and Religious Plurality: A Rortian Alternative to Liberalism and Communitarianism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 April 2015

Extract

There are two very different sets of questions that thoughtful intellectuals ask. On the one hand, we ask those questions like whether there is a God, how many gods there are, who or what God is, and where God exists. On the other hand, we ask those questions like whether women are essentially subordinate to men, whether blacks are by nature inferior to whites, and whether the poor are necessarily secondary to the rich. Despite some strong protests from religious fundamentalists, slowly but constantly, as a society, we are becoming more and more used to thinking that universally agreed answers to the first set of questions are unlikely, unnecessary, and perhaps undesirable. For different people may, and indeed should be allowed and even encouraged to, have their own opinions about, and ways of living with their understanding of God. By contrast, despite some persistent dissents by cultural and moral relativists, gradually but steadily, we are becoming more and more convinced that consensus must be sought on the second set of questions. For we cannot imagine a well ordered society that allows people who have conflicting political convictions (those who believe in human equality and those who don't, for example) to freely exercise their respective ideals. In short, despite some resistance that cannot be ignored, with difficulty, we are eventually coming to realize that religious plurality and political solidarity must co-exist. The question is how.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Center for the Study of Law and Religion at Emory University 1994

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Rawls, John, Political Liberalism xvixvii (Columbia U Press, 1993)Google Scholar and Habermas, Jurgen, 2 The Theory of Communicative Action, Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functionalist Reason 109 (Beacon, 1987)Google Scholar.

2. For example, Hauerwas concedes that his view is “less effective in helping people come to rational agreement.” Hauerwas, Stanley, A Nonviolent Proposal for Christian Participation in the Culture Wars, 75 Soundings: An Interdisciplinary Journal 477, 483 (1992)Google Scholar. For a critique of the communitarians's lack of an adequate politics, see Wallach, John R., Liberals, Communitarians, and the Tasks of Political Theory, 15 Political Theory 581, 591–96 (1987)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3. Rorty, Richard, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity 8 (Cambridge U Press, 1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4. Id.

5. Rorty, Richard, Human Rights, Rationality, and Sentimentality, 81 Yale Rev 1, 7 (1993)Google Scholar.

6. Id at 6.

7. Id at 7.

8. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity at 8 (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

9. Rorty, , 81 Yale Rev at 13 (cited in note 5)Google Scholar.

10. Id at 12.

11. McCarthy, Thomas, Ideals and Illusions: On Reconstruction and Deconstruction in Contemporary Critical Theory 33 (MIT Press, 1991)Google Scholar.

12. Rorty, Richard, Truth and Freedom: A Reply to Thomas McCarthy, 16 Critical Theory 633, 635 (1990)Google Scholar.

13. Rorty, Richard, Religion as Conversation Stopper 3 Common Knowledge 1 (1994)Google Scholar.

14. Rorty, Richard, Universality and Truth 1, 12 (unpublished manuscript, 1994)Google Scholar.

15. This view is identified as undiscriminating Augustinianism, which “is bound to be unremittingly critical of all and any human arrangements, any actual and even any imaginable forms of social order.” Markus, R.A., Saeculum: History and Society in the Theology of St. Augustine 168 (Cambridge U Press, 1970)Google Scholar.

16. Rorty, , Universality and Truth at 12 (cited in note 14)Google Scholar.

17. Rorty, Richard, Intellectuals at the End of Socialism, 80 Yale Rev 1 (1992)Google Scholar.

18. Dworkin, Ronald, Pragmatism, Right Answers, and True Banality 359, 361 in Brint, Michael, Weaver, William, eds, Pragmatism in Law and Society (Westview, 1991)Google Scholar. Similarly, according to Frank B. Farrell, after his disenchantment of the world, Rorty can only appeal to the fashion model for political justification: “Rules of argument, human rights, liberal institutions, ethical habits will, like fashions in clothing, have their only backing in our activity of backing them, an activity that could just as well have settled on many other preferences.” Farrell, Frank B., Subjectivity, Realism, and Postmodernism-the Recovery of the World 143 (Cambridge U Press, 1994)Google Scholar.

19. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity at 57 (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

20. Hutchinson, Allan C., The Three ‘Rs’: Reading/Rorty/Radically, 103 Harv L Rev 555, 566 (1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

21. Rorty, Richard, Cosmopolitanism Without Emancipation: A Response to Jean-Francois Lyotard 211, 212 in 1 Objectivity, Relativism and Truth: Philosophical Papers (Cambridge U Press, 1991)Google Scholar.

22. Id at 212.

23. Will Kymlicka, however, argues that, for Rorty, “‘the notions of community and shared values mark the limits of practical reason,’ [and] not just its point of departure.” Kymlicka, Will, Liberalism and Communitarianism, 18 Canadian J Phil 181 (1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For a similar charge of Rorty's confusion of the starting point with the ending point of political discourse, see Nielsen, Kai, After the Demise of the Tradition: Rorty, Critical Theory, and the Fate of Philosophy 150 (Westview Press, 1991)Google Scholar.

24. Rorty, , Cosmopolitanism Without Emancipation at 212 (cited in note 21)Google Scholar. Wittgenstein holds a similar view. For a language game to go on, he argues, there must be a number of beliefs beyond doubt. Yet, “it seems impossible to say in any individual case that such-and-such must be beyond doubt if there is to be a language-game.” Anscombe, G.E.M. and von Wright, G.H., eds, On Certainty § 519 (Harper Torchbook, 1972)Google Scholar.

25. Rorty, , Objectivity, Relativism and Truth at 14 (cited in note 21)Google Scholar.

26. Rorty, Richard, Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism at 197Google Scholar in Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth (cited in note 21). Thus, Comay is certainly wrong to characterize Rorty as saying that “to compare the present to the possible, so as to create a new future-is to flee time and history.” Comay, Rebecca, Interrupting the Conversation: Notes on Rorty at 85 in Simpson, Evan, ed, Anti-foundationalism and Practical Reasoning: Conversations Between Hermeneutics and Analysis (Academic Printing, 1987)Google Scholar. For Rorty encourages people to compare the present with an imagined future, a possible Utopia. He only believes that we cannot compare the present with an impossible one like Habermas' and Putnam's “unconditionaltty.”

27. Rorty, , Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism at 197 (cited in note 26)Google Scholar.

28. Rorty, Richard, Feminism and Pragmatism, 30 Mich Q Rev 231, 239 (1991)Google Scholar.

29. Id.

30. Rorty, , Universality and Truth at 18 (cited in note 14)Google Scholar.

31. Rorty, Richard, Putnam and the Relativist Menace, 90 J Phil 443, 451–52 (1993)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32. Rorty, , Universality and Truth at 12 (cited in note 14)Google Scholar.

33. Rorty, , Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism at 200 (cited in note 26)Google Scholar.

34. Kymlicka, , 18 Canadian J of Phil at 199200 (cited in note 23)Google Scholar. For a similar uneasiness with Rorty's use of “we-intention,” see Bernstein, Richard J., The New Constellation: The Ethical-Political Horizons of Modernity/Postmodernity 246, 247 (MIT Press, 1992)Google Scholar and Bhaskar, Roy, Philosophy and the Idea of Freedom 9495 (Blackwell, 1995)Google Scholar.

35. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity at 5960 (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

36. Rorty, Richard, On Ethnocentrism: A Reply to Clifford Geertz at 203, 240 in 1 Philosophical Papers (cited in note 21)Google Scholar.

37. Compare Wittgenstein's conception of philosophy as leaving everything as it is, a conception that Nielsen criticizes also as conservative. Yet for Wittgenstein, everything, like an old city, changes every day. Thus, to leave everything as it is, is to allow everything to change as it does. If you want to provide an unconditional foundation for everything, you are amounting to protecting everything from any further change. For Wittgenstein's conception of philosophy, see Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Investigations § 124 (Macmillan, 1953)Google Scholar. For Nielsen's criticism, see Nielsen, Kai, Challenge of Wittgenstein: An Examination of His Picture of Religious Belief 3 Studies in Religion 29 (1973)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

38. Indeed, as Lynn A. Baker points out, the liberal culture that Rorty has in mind is not exactly the same as the existing one but “a liberal Utopian” or “an ideal liberal society” in which suffering and cruelty will be diminished, freedom will be maximized, and chances for self-fulfillment will be equalized. Baker, Lynn A., “Just Do It”: Pragmatism and Progressive Social Change at 99, 107 in Brint, and Weaver, , eds, Pragmatism in Law and Society (cited in note 18)Google Scholar. William Buscemi also agrees that “it is not American institutions and policies as they currently exist which Rorty supports… It is, rather, those entities as they might become.” Buscemi, William J., The Ironic Politics of Richard Rorty, 55 The Rev of Pol 141, 149 (1993)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

39. As I indicated, although the criticism of Rorty as a conservative is overwhelming, Lynn A. Baker stands out by arguing that Rorty is a social progressivist. Baker, , “Just Do It” at 99108 (cited in note 38)Google Scholar. However, I disagree with Baker's attempt to separate Rorty's progressive social proposal from his ethnocentric criticism of liberals' aspiration of unconditionality. According to Baker, such a foundational conception of unconditionality, just like Rorty's own anti-foundational conception of ethnocentricity, can support both a progressive and a conservative political proposal. Id at 108-115.

40. Kymlicka, , 18 Canadian J of Philos at 181 (cited in note 23)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Wallach, , 15 Political Theory 581 (cited in note 2)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

41. Hauerwas, Stanley, Freedom of Religion: A Subtle Temptation 72, Soundings: An Interdisciplinary Journal 317, 333 (1989)Google Scholar.

42. Rorty, , Cosmopolitanism Without Emancipation at 221 (cited in note 21)Google Scholar.

43. Sandel, Michael J., Democrats and Community: A Public Philosophy for American Liberalism, 198 New Republic 20 (1988)Google Scholar.

44. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity at 190 (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

45. Rorty, , Postmodernism Bourgeois Liberalism at 200 (cited in note 26)Google Scholar.

46. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony and Solidarity at 192 (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

47. Rorty, , Cosmopolitanism Without Emancipation at 216 (cited in note 21)Google Scholar.

48. David L. Hall, in his otherwise very sympathetic study of Rorty, has confused Rorty's view of politics and his view of religion when he asserts that, in contrast to Habermas' overarching consensus, “Rorty's pluralism cannot lead to convergence but divergence. There is neither the expectation of, nor any necessity for, consensus.” Hall, David L., Richard Rorty, Prophet and Poet of the New Pragmatism 150 (State U of New York Press, 1994)Google Scholar.

49. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity at 196 (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

50. Hauerwas, Stanley and Willimon, William H., Resident Aliens, Life in the Christian Colony: A Provocative Christian Assessment of Culture and Ministry for People Who Know That Something Is Wrong 42, 43 (Abingdon Press, 1989)Google Scholar.

51. Bernstein, , The New Constellation at 248 (cited in note 34)Google Scholar.

52. Id at 279.

53. Putnam, Hilary, Why Reason Can't Be Naturalized at 222, 232 in Bayes, Kenneth, Bohman, James and McCarthy, Thomas, eds, After Philosophy: End or Transformation? (MIT Press, 1987)Google Scholar.

54. Rorty, , Cosmopolitanism Without Emancipation at 213 (cited in note 21)Google Scholar.

55. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony and Solidarity at xvi (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

56. Rorty, , Cosmopolitanism Without Emancipation at 212–13 (cited in note 21)Google Scholar.

57. Id at 219. Lynn A. Baker thus insightfully points out that, for Rorty, “[i]ncreased human solidarity … is not synonymous with an ‘us’ admitting a ‘them’ to membership through an act of nobless oblige. Rather, according to Rorty, the narrative process of interpretive description encompasses the nonoppressed as well as the oppressed.” Baker, , “Just Do It” at 101 (cited in note 38)Google Scholar.

58. Rorty, Richard, The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy in Rorty, , 1 Philosophical Papers at 175, 195 (cited in note 21)Google Scholar.

59. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity at 59 (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

60. Id at 67-68.

61. Bernstein, , The New Constellation at 245 (cited in note 34)Google Scholar.

62. Rorty, , Cosmopolitanism Without Emancipation at 213 (cited in note 21)Google Scholar. David Hall, however, believes that for Rorty, one needs solidarity and community because of one's sense of existential loneliness (the absence of connectedness with other finite beings) and loss of solitude (sense of singularity and uniqueness of one's own finite being). Hall, , Richard Rorty: Prophet and Poet at 171–72 (cited in note 48)Google Scholar.

63. Rorty, , On Ethnocentrism at 206 (cited in note 36)Google Scholar.

64. MacIntyre, Alasdair, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory 172 (U of Notre Dame Press, 1981)Google Scholar.

65. For this distinction of justice as virtue and vice, see Sandel, Michael J., Liberalism and the Limits of Justice 35 (Cambridge U Press, 1982)Google Scholar. For a liberal response, see Baker, E. Edwin, Sandel on Rawls: Justice as a Vice, 133 U of Pa L Rev 917 (1985)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

66. Stephen Mulhall and Adam Swift hold that, since most if not all communitarians do not hold a representational and ahistorical conception of good, Rorty's criticism of them are completely invalid. Mulhall, Stephen and Swift, Adam, Liberals and Communitarians 232–47 (Blackwell, 1992)Google Scholar. Yet, Rorty criticizes communitarianism as foundational not because it is representational or ahistorical, but because it believes that our historical conception of Good must come before the rest of our beliefs.

67. Rorty, , 81 Yale Rev at 5 (1993) (cited in note 5)Google Scholar.

68. Rorty, Richard, Pragmatism, Relativism, and Irrationalism in his Consequences of Pragmatism (Essays: 1972-1980) 168 (U of Minnesota Press, 1982)Google Scholar.

69. Id at 167.

70. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony and Solidarity at xiiixiv (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

71. Id at xiii.

72. Id at xv.

73. Fraser and Bhaskar hold that Rorty's view of the public and private relationship is not consistent. He shifts from the view that they are complementary to the view that they are antithetical and finally to the view that they are separate. Fraser, Nancy, Solidarity or Singularity? Richard Rorty Between Romanticism and Technocracy in her Unruly Practices: Power, Discourse, and Gender in Contemporary Social Theory 93, 96102 (U of Minnesota Press, 1989)Google Scholar. Bhaskar, Roy, Philosophy and the Idea of Freedom 8591 (Blackwell, 1991)Google Scholar. It seems to me, however, Rorty has consistently held that, if we want to find a single unified version of the public and the private, they are antithetical. However, if we separate them into different spheres, they are complementary.

74. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity at 8485 (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

75. Id at 91-92.

76. Id at 145.

77. Id at xiv.

78. Rorty, , The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy at 175 (cited in note 58)Google Scholar.

79. Habermas, , 2 The Theory of Communicative Action at 52 (cited in note 1)Google Scholar.

80. After Philosophy and Science have been subsequently seen as reliable substitutes for religion to be the foundation of a society, Rorty notes, now the American cultural left, influenced by Paul de Man, is proposing literature, understood as ever-renewed understanding or naming, as such a foundation. For just as we were told about fifty years “that life and politics would become better if only we could adopt the attitude and the habits of natural scientist[,] [we] are now being told the same sort of thing about the attitude and habits of the literary critic.” Rorty, Richard, De Man and the American Cultural Left in his 2 Essays on Heidegger and Others: Philosophical Papers 129 (Cambridge U Press, 1991)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

81. Rorty, , The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy at 179 (cited in note 58)Google Scholar.

82. Rorty, , Religion as Conversation Stopper at 2 (cited in note 13)Google Scholar.

83. Rorty, , The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy at 192 (cited in note 58)Google Scholar.

84. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity at 94 (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

85. Rorty, , Religion as Conversation Stopper at 2 (cited in note 13)Google Scholar.

86. Rorty, , The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy at 175 (cited in note 58)Google Scholar.

87. Id.

88. Rorty, , Religion as Conversation Stopper at 3 (cited in note 13)Google Scholar.

89. Carter, Stephen L., The Culture of Disbelief: How American Law and Politics Trivialize Religious Devotion 73 (Basic Books, 1993)Google Scholar.

90. Id at 41.

91. Rorty, , Religion as Conversation Stopper at 3 (cited in note 13)Google Scholar.

92. Rorty, , Consequences of Pragmatism at xiixiiv (cited in note 68)Google Scholar.

93. Kaufman, Gordon D., In Face of Mystery: A Constructive Theology 3940 (Harvard U Press, 1993)Google Scholar.

94. Rorty, , Religion as Conversation Stopper at 4 (cited in note 13)Google Scholar.

95. Id at 4.

96. Id at 5.

97. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity at 54 (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

98. Rorty, , Religion as Conversation Stopper at 4 (cited in note 13)Google Scholar.

99. Comay, , Interrupting the Conversation at 95 (cited in note 26)Google Scholar.

100. Fraser, , Solidarity or Singularity? at 102 (cited in note 73)Google Scholar.

101. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity at xiv (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

102. Id at 91-92.

103. Id at 91.

104. This is a confusion also made by some religious communitarians, but in an opposite way. From the view that one's religious conviction is related to the public life, they conclude that religious conviction must be shareable with all.

105. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity at 120–21 (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

106. Rorty, , Postmodern Bourgeois Liberalism at 199 (cited in note 26)Google Scholar.

107. Rorty answers this question in a comment on an earlier version of this essay by saying that “decisions [are] yet made without a self making them.” The self that Rorty has in mind seems to be a Rawlsian one: a substance with attributes. The self I have in mind in posing the question, however, is a Rortian one: a web of beliefs.

108. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity at 120 (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

109. In this sense, Joan C. Williams is right that “if our goals are egalitarian, making progress on race, class, and gender inequalities is necessarily part of our personal projects of self creation.” Williams, Joan C., Rorty, Radicalism, Romanticism: The Politics of the Gaze in Brint, and Weaver, , eds, Pragmatism in Law and Society at 155, 173 (cited in note 18)Google Scholar.

110. Rorty, , Universality and Truth at 24 (cited in note 14)Google Scholar.

111. Rorty, , The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy at 183 n 23 (cited in note 58)Google Scholar.

112. Id at 193.

113. Id at 184.

114. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity at 197 (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

115. For both Putnam and Bernstein, however, this shadow is Rorty's conception of the meaninglessness of metaphysical controversy. Bernstein, , The New Constellation at 236 (cited in note 34)Google Scholar. Putnam, , Why Reason Can't Be Naturalized at 222 (cited in note 53)Google Scholar.

116. The following is a Quinean picture of the web of beliefs: “any statement can be held true come what may, if we make drastic enough adjustments elsewhere in the system. Even a statement very close to the periphery can be held true in the face of recalcitrant experience by pleading hallucination or by amending certain statements of the kind called logical laws. Conversely, by the same token, no statement is immune to revision.” Quine, Willard van Orman, From a Logical Point of View 20 (Harper and Row, 1961)Google Scholar.

117. Rorty, , Postmodern Bourgeois Liberalism at 199 (cited in note 26)Google Scholar.

118. Buscemi, , 55 The Rev of Pol 144 n 6 (cited in note 38)Google Scholar.

119. Rorty, , On Ethnocentrism at 208 (cited in note 36)Google Scholar.

120. Rorty, , Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity at 194 (cited in note 3)Google Scholar.

121. Fraser holds that Rorty's Tanner Lecture at the University of Michigan “Feminism and Pragmatism” indicates the birth of a new Rorty. In this lecture, she claims, Rorty has given up all his earlier dichotomies “between the public and the private, the community and the individual, the political and the aesthetical,” and allows “far-reaching redescription of social life.” Fraser, Nancy, From Irony to Prophecy to Politics: A Response to Richard Rorty, 30 Mich Q Rev 259, 262 (1991)Google Scholar. Such an observation is wrong not only because, as we have seen, Rorty has already allowed such redescription of social life in many works before this lecture. It is wrong also because Rorty still holds these dichotomies, even in his very recent article Religion as Conversation Stopper (cited in note 13).