Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-75dct Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-28T23:10:27.736Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Gap-2 morasses of height ω

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

Dan Velleman*
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, Amherst College, Amherst, Massachusetts 01002

Extract

In [3] we have shown how the simplification of gap-1 morasses introduced in [4] can be extended to gap-2 morasses. As in the gap-1 case, the definition of simplified (κ, 2)-morasses (gap-2 morasses of height κ) makes sense for κ = ω, although the smallest size for Jensen's original gap-2 morasses was κ = ω1. The existence of simplified gap-1 morasses of height ω is provable in ZFC (see [2]), but the same cannot be true for gap-2 morasses, since the top level of a simplified (ω, 2)-morass is a simplified (ω1, 1)-morass, and the existence of simplified (ω1, 1)-morasses is not provable in ZFC. In this paper we prove the best existence theorem for simplified (ω, 2)-morasses that we can hope for:

Theorem 1.1. There is a simplified (ω, 2)-morass iff there is a simplified (ω1, 1)-morass.

Before giving the proof we briefly summarize the definition of simplified (ω, 2)-morasses. For a more thorough treatment, and proofs of some of the basic properties of simplified gap-2 morasses which will be used below, we refer the reader to [3]. Suppose ‹‹φζζω1›, ‹ζξξ < ξω1›› is a simplified (ω1, 1)-morass. (We are using the “expanded” version of the definition.) We assume the morass is neat (see [4]). For each ζ < ω1 let σζ be the split point of ζ, ζ + 1; i.e., ζ, ζ + 1 is a pair {id, b}, where id is the identity function, bσζ = id and b(σζ) = φζ. A simplified (ω, 2)-morass will describe the construction of this simplified (ω, 1)-morass from finite pieces. The finite pieces will be the initial segments of the morass picked out by an increasing sequence of natural numbers ‹nii < ω ›. We call this piece level i of the (ω, 2)-morass, and we call the full simplified (ω1, 1)-morass level ω. To make sure the pieces are really finite, we require that φx and xy are finite for x < y < ω.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1987

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

[1]Velleman, D., Morasses, diamond, and forcing, Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 23 (1982), pp. 199281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2]Velleman, D., ω-morasses, and a weak form of Martin's axiom provable in ZFC, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 285 (1984), pp. 617627.Google Scholar
[3]Velleman, D., Simplified gap-2 morasses, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic (to appear).Google Scholar
[4]Velleman, D., Simplified morasses, this Journal, vol. 49 (1984), pp. 257271.Google Scholar