Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-22dnz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T19:47:18.386Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

‘Were it not against our laws’: oppression and resistance in Shakespeare's Comedy of Errors

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2018

Eric Heinze*
Affiliation:
Faculty of Laws, Queen Mary University of London

Abstract

The Comedy of Errors, always loved on the stage, has long been deemed less substantial than Shakespeare's ‘mature’ works. Its references to private and public law have certainly been noted: a trial, a breached contract, a stand-off between monarchical and parliamentary powers. Yet the play's legal elements are more than historical curios within an otherwise light-hearted venture. The play is pervasively structured by an array of socio-legal dualisms: master–servant, husband–wife, native–alien, parent–child, monarch–parliament, buyer–seller. All confront fraught transitions from pre-modern to early modern forms. Those fundamentally legal relationships fuel character and action, even where no conventionally legal norm or procedure is at issue. ‘Errors’ in the play serve constantly to highlight unstable and shifting relationships of dominance and submission. Law undergoes its own transition from feudal–aristocratic to commercial forms. Through a theatrical framing device, it thereby re-emerges to remind us that those dualisms, even in their new incarnations, will remain squarely within law's ambit.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Society of Legal Scholars 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 May, HG and Metzger, BM (eds) The New Oxford Annotated Bible (New York: Oxford University Press, 1962) pp 14211422.Google Scholar

2 See report reprinted in Shakespeare, William (edited by Foakes, RA) The Comedy of Errors second series (London: Arden, 1962) pp 115117 Google Scholar at p 116 (original source:

3 Martin, R ‘Introduction’ in William Shakespeare (edited by Wells, S) The Comedy of Errors (London: Penguin, 2005) pp xxilxii Google Scholar at p xxiii.

4 See, eg, P Edmondson ‘The play in performance’ in Shakespeare, above n 3, pp lxiii–lxxiii at p lxv.

5 See A Barton, introductory notes to The Comedy of Errors, in Levin, H et.al (eds) The Riverside Shakespeare (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co, 1974) pp 7982 Google Scholar at p 79.

6 Foakes, above n 2, p xl.

7 Barton, above n 5, p 79.

8 See, eg, Foakes, above n 2, p xl. See also, eg, G Waller ‘Much joy, some terror: reading Shakespeare's comedies today’ in Waller, G (ed) Shakespeare's Comedies (London: Longman, 1991) pp 128 Google Scholar (noting changing perspectives on the comedies since Shakespeare's time).

9 Freedman, B Reading errantly: misrecognition and the uncanny in The Comedy of Errors ’ in Miola, RS (ed) The Comedy of Errors: Critical Essays (New York: Garland, 1997) pp 261297 Google Scholar at p 264. See also, eg, at p 56 (commenting critically on earlier approaches).

10 For example, Tim Supple's 1996 Royal Shakespeare Company performance ‘had Egeon chained to a stake in a market-place as the audience entered the auditorium’: Edmondson, above n 4, pp lxviii–lxix.

11 ibid, pp lxiii–lxiv.

12 S Greenblatt, introductory notes to The Comedy of Errors, in Norton pp 717–723 at p 722.

13 See generally, eg, Miola, above n 9.

14 For an early attempt at a systematic account, see, eg, White, EJ Commentaries on the Law in Shakespeare (St Louis: FH Thomas Law Book Co, 1911)Google Scholar ch 14 (reprinted by Kessinger Legacy Reprints).

15 See, eg, Ward, I Shakespeare and the Legal Imagination (London: Butterworths, 1999)Google Scholar ch 5; see also, generally, Bruster, D Drama and the Market in the Age of Shakespeare (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

16 Heinze, E Power politics and the rule of law: Shakespeare's first historical tetralogy and law's “foundations”’ (2009) 29 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies (forthcoming).Google Scholar

17 ‘If happiness is activity in accordance with excellence, it is reasonable that it should be in accordance with the highest excellence’: Aristotle [WD Ross (transl)]Nicomachean Ethics X.vii.1177a12–13, rev'd by JO Urmsom in Barnes, J (ed) The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translations vol 2 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984) pp 17291867 Google Scholar at p 1860.

18 See, eg, Politics III.xiv.1285a17 [B Jowett (trans)] in ibid, pp 1986–2129 at p 2039 (arguing that ‘foreigners [are] more servile in character than Hellenes’). See also Politics III.i.1275a5–12 in ibid, at p 2023 (distinguishing citizens from resident aliens).

19 See generally, eg, Politics I.iii–vii in ibid, at pp 1988–1992. See also Politics I.13.1260 a12 in ibid, at p 1999 (arguing that ‘the slave has no deliberative faculty at all’).

20 See, eg, Politics I.xiii.1260a12 in ibid, at p 1999 (claiming that Greek women have a deliberative faculty, ‘but it is without authority’).

21 See generally, eg, Cartledge, P The Greeks (Oxford: Oxford University Press, rev'd edn, 1993).Google Scholar

22 See, eg, Nicomachean Ethics I.3.1095b1–13, above n 17, at p 1731 (arguing that understanding of ethics requires upbringing in ‘good habits’).

23 See, eg, Plato Republic II.376d in Cooper, JM (ed) Plato: Complete Works (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1997) pp 9711223 Google Scholar at p 1015 (advocating a regime of conditioning through education).

24 ‘[W]hen we are dealing with definite and ordered products of nature, we must not say that each is of a certain quality because it becomes so, rather that they become so and so because they are so and so, for the process of becoming attends upon being and is for the sake of being, not vice versa ’: Aristotle [A Platt (transl)] Generation of Animals V.i. 778b2–6 in Barnes, above n 17, vol 1, pp 1111–1218 at p 1204 (emphasis in Platt).

25 See, eg, Rousseau, J-J Du contrat social ’ in Gagnebie, B et.al (eds) Oeuvres completes vol 3 (Paris: Gallimard, 1964) pp 346470 Google Scholar at p 353 (criticising Aristotle).

26 See, eg, Martin, TR Ancient Greece: From Pre-Historic to Hellenistic Times (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1996) pp 116121.Google Scholar

27 See, eg, Halio, JL ‘Introduction’ in William Shakespeare (edited by Halio, JL) The Merchant of Venice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998) pp 183 Google Scholar at pp 24–27.

28 See, eg, Hegel, Gwf Phänomenologie des Geistes vol IV.A (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1999) pp 109116.Google Scholar

29 See, eg, Hegel, Gwf Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts sections 165–166 (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1999) pp 154155 Google Scholar (subordinating women to men).

30 Ibid, at p 109: ‘Another self-consciousness confronts self-consciousness; it has emerged from itself’.

31 See, eg, Hegel, Gwf Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie vol I.2.A (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1999).Google Scholar

32 Sidney, P The Defense of Poesy (Glasgow: Urie, 1752) p 51 Google Scholar. Cf Greenblatt, above n 12, p 722.

33 The words ‘Comical’ or ‘Comicall’ appear in some early versions (though not in the Folio) in the title of The Merchant of Venice – the only real rival to Comedy of Errors in unsettling socio-legal norms of dominance and exclusion. See Norton, p 3343.

34 See also Martin, above n 3, p xxvi (linking ‘error’ to the Latin errare, which hints at the play's themes of wandering and uprootedness).

35 Cf, eg, Barber, CL Shakespeare's Festive Comedy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1959) p 29 Google Scholar (examining the simultaneously comic and subversive elements of Cade's rebellion, in Henry VI, Part II, as a form of Saturnalia). See also ibid at p 206 (examining Saturnalian elements in the second tretralogy).

36 On the concept of ‘error’ in The Comedy of Errors, see, eg, Hale, JK The Shakespeare of the Comedies: A Multiple Approach (Bern: Peter Lang, 1996) pp 3032 Google Scholar. See also, generally, Salingar, L Shakespeare and the Traditions of Comedy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1974) pp 76128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

37 On the play's subversive elements, see, eg, Parker, above n 9. On subversive elements in performance, see, eg, Quince, R Crinkles in the Carnival: Ideology in South African Productions of The Comedy of Errors to 1985’ (19901991) 4 Shakespeare in Southern Africa 73.Google Scholar

38 Cf Greenblatt, above n 12, p 719 (describing The Menaechmi as ‘a brilliant, energetic farce, fast-paced, funny’ but ‘cold at heart’).

39 Cf Parker, above n 9, p 57 (identifying similar elements elsewhere in Shakespearean comedy).

40 On antiquarianism in Shakespeare, see Rackin, P Stages of History: Shakespeare's English Chronicles (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1990)Google Scholar ch 1.

41 Crucial to recent understandings of social ‘discipline’ in Shakespeare has been Foucault, M Surveiller et punir (Paris: Gallimard, 1975).Google Scholar See generally, eg, ch 5.

42 See Heinze, E Heir, celebrity, martyr, monster: legal and political legitimacy in Shakespeare and beyond’ (2009) 20(1) Law & Critique (forthcoming).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

43 Martin, above n 3, p xxiii.

44 See, eg, Wilson, above n 41, pp 131–139.

45 See above n 18.

46 Parker, above n 9, p 56.

47 Glossing the notion of ‘stubborn Jewry’ in Richard II, 2.1.55, Charles Forker notes the traditional idea (also arising in the Tudor-era Homily against Disobedience and Wilful Rebellion ) of ‘the stony-hearted inhabitants of Judea who resisted Christianity’: William Shakespeare (edited by Forker, CR) Richard II third series (London: Arden, 2002) p 247.Google Scholar

48 See S Wells ‘Commentary’ in Shakespeare, above n 3, pp 85–144 at p 96. According to Norton, ‘Many Londoners lived above their places of business’: Norton, p 730 n 5. See also Foakes, above n 2, p 16.

49 Foakes, above n 2, p 16.

50 Cf Shakespeare, above n 2, p 49; Shakespeare, above n 3, p 33.

51 Wells, above n 48, pp 115–116.

52 See, eg, Parker, above n 9, p 58 (commenting on earlier approaches).

53 See, eg, Plato Protagoras 329b in Cooper, above n 23, pp746–790 at p 762; Plato Gorgias 449b in ibid, pp 791–869 at pp 794–795.

54 See generally Aristotle [W Rhys Roberts (transl)] Rhetoric III.xiv in Barnes, above n 17, pp 2152–2269 at pp 2258–2261 (examining introductions to oratorical addresses).

55 Rhetoric III.xiv.1415a13-14 in ibid, p 2259.

56 ‘We may describe wrong-doing as injury voluntarily inflicted contrary to law’: Rhetoric I.x. 1268b7–8 in ibid, p 1278. Accordingly, if injury contrary to law was not voluntarily, then it is not legal wrong-doing. Cf. Rhetoric I.xiii.1373b28–29 in ibid, p 2187.

57 Charles Whitworth writes, ‘Storm, shipwreck and loss at sea, the very stuff of romance, become metaphors for spiritual and emotional incompleteness, hopelessness, self-doubt, loss of one's identity’: C Whitworth ‘Introduction’ in William Shakespeare, The Comedy of Errors (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002) pp 179 Google Scholar at p 51, and, one might add, for economic and socio-political transformation from an older, aristocratic time, into a brave new world.

58 Artistotle Rhetoric I.ii.1356a1–7 in Barnes, above n 17, p 2155.

59 Rhetoric I.ii.1356a7 in ibid.

60 Rhetoric II.i.1377b24-26 in ibid, p 2194.

61 Rhetoric II.i.1378a6–9 in ibid.

62 See J Candido ‘Dining out in Ephesus: food in The Comedy of Errors ’ in Miola, above n 9, pp 199–225.

63 Rhetoric II.viii, 1385b13–15 in Barnes, above n 17, p 2207. Cf, eg, Beiner, G Shakespeare's Agnostic Comedy: Poetics, Analysis, Criticism (Rutherford: Farleigh Dickenson University Press, 1993) p 95 Google Scholar (noting the rhetorical device of force beyond one's control visiting disaster upon a benign individual).

64 Rhetoric II.viii.1386a10 in ibid, p 2208.

65 Cf Parker, above n 9, p 57 (calling the ‘harsh law’ a ‘familiar beginning of Shakespearean comedy’).

66 See, eg, Whitworth, above n 57, pp 49–50. But on the literary and historical significance of Ephesus, see, eg, Parker, above n 9, pp 55–57; L Maguire ‘The girls from Ephesus’ in Miola, above n 9, pp 355–391 at 360–366.

67 See, eg, Maguire, ibid, pp 360–366; Leggatt, A Shakespeare's Comedy of Love (London: Methuen, 1974)Google Scholar ch 1.

68 William Shakespeare The Comedy of Errors (James Cellan Jones, director, BBC Time-Life, 1983). See also, eg, JG Fink (1983) 35 Theatre Journal 415 (reviewing Robert Woodruff's production, 1983); C Whitworth (1983) 24 Cahiers Elisabéthains 116 (reviewing Adrian Noble's production, 1983).

69 Norton, p 738 n 8. The concepts of ‘devil’ and ‘diabolical’ derive from the Greek ‘diaballein ’, which means, literally, to ‘throw across’, from dia- ‘across, through’ and ballein ‘to throw’. Together with references to ‘spirits’, ‘sprites’ and ‘goblins’, references to the devil (4.2.33, 4.3.46) form part of the play's lexicon of subversion.

70 Norton, p 738 n 2.

71 See generally, eg, Freedman, above n 9; Whitworth, above n 57, pp 51–56. See also, eg, MacCary, T The Comedy of Errors : a different kind of comedy’ (1978) 9(3) New Literary History 525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

72 On the motif of beatings in the play, see also, eg, Anderson, L A Kind of Wild Justice: Revenge in Shakespeare's Comedies (Newark: University of Delaware Press, 1987) p 26.Google Scholar

73 Norton, p 731.

74 On stage directions in the Folio, see ‘Textual note’ in Greenblatt, S et.al The Norton Shakespeare (New York: Norton & Co, 1st edn, 1997) p 689.Google Scholar

75 See, eg, Macdonald, RR William Shakespeare: The Comedies (New York: Twayne Publishers, 1992) pp 69.Google Scholar

76 Punning on ‘last’, which also means ‘a wooden model of a foot used in making leather shoes’: Norton, p 733 n 9 (col 1).

77 Cf ibid, p 733 n 8.

78 Cf Parker, above n 9, pp 66–67 (examining Dromio's physical descriptions of Nell).

79 See n 74 above.

80 Norton, p 734 n 3.

81 Ibid, p 734 n 4.

82 See, eg, Hall, J Anxious Pleasures: Shakespearean Comedy and the Nation-State (Madison: Associated University Press, 1995) pp 3952 Google Scholar (examining the role of mercantile capitalism in The Comedy of Errors ); Maguire, above n 66, pp 361–364 (noting the role of Ephesus as a commercial centre). See also Whitworth, above n 57, pp 48–49.

83 Cf Hall, ibid, pp 42–43. Cf also, eg, Macdonald, above n 75, p 2 (noting an ‘opportunistic venality’ in the merchant world).

84 Punning on ‘common’ in the sense of ‘[l]and belonging to the whole community’, hence Antipholus' suggestion that ‘Dromio maintains an egalitarian spirit at inappropriate times’: Norton, p 734 n 6.

85 Ibid, p 734.

86 See S Freud Zur Psychopathologie des Alltagslebens, in Gesammelte Werke vol 4 (Frankfurt a.M: Fischer Verlag, 1999) (explaining the systematic and meaningful quality of seemingly random errors). See also, eg, Freeman, above n 9, pp 284–293 (discussing psychoanalytic readings of the play). Waller notes that ‘Shakespearean comedy is a dramatization of common wish-fulfilment fantasies’: Waller, above n 8, p 10. However, in limiting that dimension to the more obvious elements of the comedies – ‘we want our love affairs to be fulfilling, our families to experience harmony and...young men and women to overcome their anxieties... and find their own kinds of happiness’ (p 10) – Waller overlooks Freud's fundamentally subversive notion of wish fulfilment.

87 ‘[M]an is a political creature’: Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics IX.ix.1169b18–19 in Barnes, above n 17, p 1848, but the legitimately dominant (ie Greek) male most completely so. See text accompanying n 12 above.

88 See, eg, Aristotle Generation of Animals II.iii.736b27, above n 24, p 1143 (identifying ‘reason alone’, most present in the legitimately dominant (ie Greek) male, as the element of the soul that is ‘divine’).

89 Heidegger, M Sein und Zeit (Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag, 1979) p 165 Google Scholar: ‘The later conceptualising of this definition of the human being in the sense of animal rationale, “living thing having reason”, is indeed not “false”, but conceals the phenomenal ground from which that definition of Dasein [“being-there”] is derived’.

90 Ibid.

91 Whitworth, above n 57, p 43. Cf above n 74.

92 Norton, p 735 n 2.

93 For critical analysis of the débat scene, see, eg, Wolfensperger, P Shakespeare: Impartial and Partial – Strategies of Persuasion in the Comedies (Tübingen: A Francke Verlag, 1994) pp 2743.Google Scholar

94 See Maguire, above n 66, pp 366–373 (examining women and marriage in The Comedy of Errors from literary and historical perspectives).

95 See Dusinberre, J Shakespeare and the Nature of Women (New York: Barnes & Noble, 1975) pp 7782.Google Scholar

96 See Candido, above n 62, p 208 (criticising Luciana's ‘didactic and self-assured’ attitude).

97 See Wolfensperger, above n 93, pp 21–26 (noting misogynist and dismissive interpretations of Adriana).

98 GR Elliott ‘Weirdness in The Comedy of Errors ’ in Miola, above n 9, pp 57–69 at p 63.

99 Dorsch, TS ‘Introduction’ in William Shakespeare, The Comedy of Errors (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988) pp 1–38Google Scholar at p 15 (emphasis added).

100 Tillyard, Emw Shakespeare's Early Comedies (London: Athlone Press, 1965) p 58.Google Scholar

101 Ibid.

102 Ibid.

103 Ibid.

104 WT MacCary ‘The Comedy of Errors’ in Waller, above n 8, p 33.

105 Ibid.

106 Cf Parker, above n 9, p 66 (noting the role of Luce).

107 Hall, above n 82, p 40.

108 Candido, above n 62, p 208.

109 Maguire notes that The Comedy of Errors ‘provides a range of examples of womankind: wife, sweetheart, kitchen maid, courtesan, mother/nun/priestess’: Maguire, above n 66, pp 360–361.

110 Cf Parker, above n 9, p 80 (noting Emilia's ‘superintendant’ role).

111 Cf ibid, p 80 (noting Adriana's role in imprisoning her husband).

112 Hegel, above n 28, p 111 (original emphasis): ‘Decisive for the relationship of these two self-conscious beings is that they prove themselves and each other through a struggle of life and death. They must enter into this struggle, since they must elevate, as to the other and to themselves, their certainty of being for themselves ’.