Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-9pm4c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-29T17:58:10.221Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Music Thinking Process: Unfolding the creation of the piece Résonances manifestes

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 November 2020

Hubert Gendron-Blais*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, McGill University, Montreal, QC, Canada
Get access
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Beyond the social and even the human, sound opens onto the intertwining of movements animating the lived experience. A sonic epistemology considers not only that the acoustic ecologies are enunciative of social relations and power dynamics, but also that they tell about the way reality is lived, experienced, organised: they are expressive, in themselves. This means, for an epistemology of phonosophy, that every perception of a sound implies a conceptual movement, which carries a mental dimension that could become the material for another thinking practice, for a sophia. This article approaches music as thinking in itself: a thought of the sonic. This affirmation will be expanded through the contribution of process philosophy (Whitehead, Deleuze and Guattari, Manning, etc.), which allows a musical event to be considered as an ecology, produced by the encounter of a multiplicity of bodies (human, sonic, technological, etc.). The processes of capture of forces involved and the different techniques required to increase the expressive potentialities of the musical assemblage will be unfolded through the case of Résonances manifestes, a comprovised music piece based on a sound score composed of field recordings from autonomous demonstrations.

Type
Articles
Copyright
© Cambridge University Press, 2020.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

1. introduction

It takes time

to find something you’re

thinking of, but in the course

of looking for it all sorts of

things come up that one was

not looking for. You might

call living in chaos an

exteriorization of the mind.

It is as though the things in

the room, in the world, in the

woods, were the means of thinking.

(John Cage Reference Cage1961)

Almost thirty years ago, during a conference in Los Angeles, philosopher, activist and psychoanalyst Félix Guattari illustrated his concept of ethical-aesthetical paradigm by showing how performance art could be of help in analysing the then raging Gulf War. The ethical-aesthetical paradigm consists broadly in an epistemological perspective starting from the knowledge elaborated in the domain of the arts to study other domains (politics, history, science, etc.) (Guattari Reference Guattari2011).Footnote 1 Considering the level of complexity attained by many contemporary problems (may they be on the political, cultural, or social level), and among others the explicitation of the crucial role of affect and aesthetics in recent world politics, the aesthetic-ethical paradigm could be increasingly useful when approaching issues related to community, expression, identity and the relation to the environment.

The ethical-aesthetical paradigm proposed by Guattari is not only a philosophical posture: it is a political and ethical affirmation that pushes us to rethink research-creation as a transversal proposition that generates new forms of experience and knowledge by putting emphasis on the creative aspects of the different practices at play, and on the agencementsFootnote 2 that enunciate the diverse collective expressions in a given environment. The project of research-creation that will be unfolded here seeks to activate conjunctively the creative potentialities of thought and the reflexive dimensions of music in such a way that both influence, reverberate and resonate with each other in a surprising and constantly renewed way, in a pragmatic and speculative movement of thought close to the event, its ineffable and extra-linguistic dimensions.

This approach allows us to consider music as a form of thought in itself. If music implies a refinement of the perception of sounds, a creative work of organisation of some sonic elements of reality, it may also then be considered as a thinking in its own right: a thought of the sonic. The practice of music thus appears as a way to propose sensible (and potentially significant) elements from the sounds that populate the world, to carry the unheard to the experiential knowledge. This phonosophic conception not only mobilises the processes of music creation in new directions, but also has important epistemological, ethical and political implications.

2. A sonic epistemology

As Jacques Attali (Reference Attali1977: 12–14) states in his influential book Noise, music as a tool of knowledge is haloed by a theoretic indiscipline that troubles the modes of thinking mainly expressed through language. Part of this unruliness comes from the fact that the thoughtful dimension of music emanates from the capacity of sounds to carry sense. Accordingly, conceiving music as a mode of thought involves the formation of a sonic epistemology.

Through sound, a whole social life expresses itself in its multiplicity, so that the noises produced by/emerging from a given society constitute a type of soundtrack of the vibrations that animate it (Attali Reference Attali1977: 12). But beyond the social and even the human, sound opens onto the intertwining of movements, ambiances, gestures and actions marking the lived experience. A sonic epistemology considers not only that the acoustic ecologies are enunciative of social relations and power dynamics, but also that they tell about the way reality is lived, experienced and organised: they are expressive, in themselves. They express in the actuality of their effective manifestations as in the potentialities of the multiple meanings, narratives, rhythms and relations that emanate from them.

This implies, on a political level, that paying attention to ambient noises could allow us to grasp otherwise unperceived dimensions of politics. The buzzing of the ventilation systems of downtown buildings having taken the place of the clamour of the working-class districts, the statements transmitted by the loudspeakers in different public spaces, the construction noises imposing the concrete deployment of urban planning on every surrounding activity, etc. If, as the Invisible Committee (Comité invisible 2014: 83) underlines, the structure of contemporary power takes the form of the material, technological and physical organisation of the world, in short if power is the very order of things, this environmental order could sometimes be more perceptible in ambient noises rather than in the analysis of the explicit statements of the administration. Yet the movements of struggle are no exception to this: the uproar of a demonstrating crowd, the judicious use of loudspeakers to manifest the presence of a particular political perspective (or, in the case of counter-demonstrations, to supplant a hostile gathering), the rhythm of a marching swarm, or even intoxicated revellers who break up the nightly tranquillity of early risers in a gentrified neighbourhood. The attention to the sensible common that goes beyond formal discourses provides access to the informal field of desire that is the real motor of all movements of struggle: the various recording devices come to capture and then amplify this desire to make heard its smallest folds, the ecology of the presences that are expressed there. As the Ojibwe artist and activist Marcella Ernest (Rector and Ernest Reference Rector and Ernest2017) affirmed, ‘understanding the sonic elements of protest helps us to better understand how protest and politics is heard and felt’.

A sonic epistemology brings knowledge into a pragmatic and experimental mode, where intuitions, attention to the small details of everyday life, furtive sensations and plurivocal relationships to meaning are part of the research. In this sense, it could inspire practices of study, understood following Stefano Harney and Fred Moten (Reference Harney and Moten.2014: 110) as a speculative practice of thought driven by sensitivity to the world, emphasising the plurality and diversity of modes of reflection that populates the lived experience, and which are just as important – sometimes even more, depending on the subject of study, the context and the approach – as the recognised forms of intellectual production. This conception offers a particular understanding of the academic field labelled ‘sound studies’: at this point, two people sitting in a park and noticing that the birdsongs are more and more covered by the combined sounds of traffic and urban works act as true ‘sound students’. The elaboration of a phonosophic epistemology should never undermine this pluralistic approach which valorises the already-reflexive dimension of many daily practices, pointing to the thinking foam of what’s organising, what moves the collective even before the formal organisation begins.

3. What thinks in the sonic experience

Sound gives access to the often-unperceived senses that circulate in a given ecology: it proposes matters of knowledge of the actual world. The philosophy of process of (and inspired by) the philosopher and mathematician Alfred N. Whitehead allows us to extend this at the deepest level of the lived experience.

For Whitehead (Reference Whitehead1978: 227), hearing a sound is first and foremost a physical feeling, that is, a physical prehension of an actual occasion of experience.Footnote 3 But this hearing also always occurs as a tending towards the realisation of a conceptual feeling, which marks the qualitative difference of the event by shaping the texture of what is not actualised but is nevertheless felt. The conceptual feeling comes from the mental pole of experience, which can never be detached from the physical pole: the contrast between the two poles is where the relationship between the actual and potential nature of the vibrations that animate the deep movements of the world is played out (Manning Reference Manning2020). Because as it has been shown by many phonosophers,Footnote 4 quantum physics has demonstrated that the material world is movement, ‘movement of movements’, composed of extremely fast oscillations (Bergson Reference Bergson1966: 165). Reality presents itself in the form of a continuous fluctuation, driven by the periodic rhythmicity of (sub-)atomic activity: matter is in this sense intrinsically vibratory: ‘We find ourselves in a buzzing world’ (Whitehead Reference Whitehead1978: 50, 79). The sound being, in its physical reality, a vibratory movement, matter is, as such, sonic.

In fact, the mental operations related to the conceptual pole of experience allow the subject of the feeling to make some elements of its/her/his objective physical datumFootnote 5 consist by the (conceptual) prehension of eternal objects,Footnote 6 that is to say of pure potential. These conceptual prehensions are therefore essential in the sensory perception of sound, since it is the ingression (the relation/the coming-into the concrete world) of eternal objects that brings definition and nuance to what is perceived as sense-data in the experience. Indeed, although the mentality of the occasion always emerges from the material-sensitive experience, the physical data – here the measurable characteristics of a sound (frequency, intensity, etc.) – never completely determine what feels/is felt in the sonic experience (Whitehead Reference Whitehead1978: 85, 248). In other words, when a sound is perceived (and sometimes identified) as such, it is because a conceptual prehension (of an eternal object) has come to qualify and through this specify the physical sound stimulus captured by the perceptual apparatus. This means, for an epistemology of phonosophy, that every perception of a sound implies a conceptual movement, which carries a mental dimension that could become the material for another thinking practice, for a sophia.

The speculative and pragmatist philosophy of Whitehead thus allows us to perceive sound in its ecological dimension, or rather in the deep inter-relationality of the different ecologies that make it (ré)sonner as such. Yet, at some point, an entity in subjective position still has to be able to perceive these differences through experience. Because if we thus come to realise that the mental (psycho-metaphysical) and physical-organic (sensory) mechanisms of perception are inextricably linked, a conception, however abstract it may be, always starts from a (sensory) perception, as Bergson (Reference Bergson1966: 145) recalled. The importance of the mental pole in the experience of sound should therefore not obscure the fact that the actual feeling of a sonic element comes from a physical sensation, able to generate an emergent ecology.

4. Music as a thinking practice

Through conceptual prehensions, the pure potential of felt relation (eternal objects) provides a definition, but moreover adds a quality to the physical feeling of a sound (Whitehead Reference Whitehead1978: 227). This is how music is perceived from more or less clear sounds, through conceptual valuations. Perhaps this is what John Cage (Reference Cage1961: 94), who contributed eminently to the reception of the sounds of the world in Western music, foresaw when he maintained that the field of music is the mind of the listener. In Whiteheadian terms, this means that what is identified as ‘music’ comes from a perceptual experience where the mental-conceptual pole determines the qualification of the sounds actually heard, and thus their ‘musical’ dimension.

Of course, the situation becomes more complex when the perceived sound is a chord, a note in a melodic sequence, or a textural composite of noises emitted simultaneously: the same complex process of physical and mental interrelations applies nevertheless, in a game of prehensions where relations of whole/parts, of harmony/dissonance determines the sensitive experience of sound, consequently forming a more or less contrasted pattern, with varying degrees of intensity. Perhaps this is what it means to entendre the music: to perceive the rhythmic contrasts, to pay attention to the differences of tonalities, to appreciate the (dis)harmonic movement of inter-related singularities, in any situation, at various levels. Whitehead’s speculative materialism details the game of innumerable prehensions through which musical processes emerge, emphasising the deep inter-relation of mentality and physicality in every aspect of the perceived reality. This complex game is marked by a series of harmonies, bifurcations, divergences: multiple captures. Music thus consists, following Deleuze (2002: 57; Reference Deleuze1988: 111), in an operation of capture of the forces that mobilise, cut and crystallise the world. In this sense, it appears to be a concentration, an intensification of the acoustic experience by capturing the surrounding forces to sonorise them. Taking on what lingers around, what is woven below formal organisations, conventional attentions and representations: a series of micro-political captures turned towards the tiny rhythms through which the elementary movement of things is felt.Footnote 7

The processes of musical creation not only involve the capture of elements from their surroundings, but also organise them into new blocks of sensations. Such blocks of sensations are composed from the materials at hand, from the perceptions and affections felt in each situation, which are aggregated into percepts and affects; in short, in compositions of relations of forces that alter the way we (can) feel and perceive. But for Deleuze and Guattari (Reference Deleuze and Guattari1980: 363–05) it is only when these actual compositions leave their territory of emergence, when they deterritorialise from the lived actuality to trace a diagonal which crosses heterogeneous components to make them hold together, that these unheard sound blocks become new musical creations. Indeed, this take-off from the sensitive to the expressive is what allows the properly creative operation of music, and which makes the created work an event as such, having its proper life, independently from all human subjects participating in the different stages of its process (Deleuze and Guattari 1980: 271, 630; Reference Deleuze and Guattari2005: 167). This is what the author and composer Hildegard Westerkamp (Reference Westerkamp2002: 52, 56) underlies when she insists on the need for a soundscape composition to be able to become a ‘new place’ from the environmental sounds from which it is (partially) derived.Footnote 8 And for this to happen, something has to think itself in its own process of emergence.

5. Technicity of the vibrant ecologies

The contribution of process philosophy to the thought of the musical experience leads us to consider the musical event as an ecology: each musical event is the result of a multiplicity of human and non-human agents forming an immanent agencement of productive forces, that is, an experience of trans-individual intensity associating all kinds of material, ambient, social, technical, spiritual components, and more (the instruments, their level of maintenance and reaction to the microclimate of the place, the musicians, their mood, the relationships between them, the ambiance of the room, the lighting, the size and attitude of the audience, etc.). This contingent association of disparate elements must be seen as that which creates, produces the music, and that which expresses through it (Nesbitt Reference Nesbitt, Criton and Chouvel2015: 187–9).

The quality of the expression that will emerge then depends not so much on the degree of inspiration of the soloist, the genius of the composer or the arranger, or even on the harmony of the group, but rather, it depends on the configuration of the agencement that is present, presence in which all these variables participate, with a multiplicity of others. And the importance of ‘minor’ variables in the bifurcation of the agencements should not be underestimated, since a musical agencement is subject to the tiniest changes, according to the movement of circumstances. From then on, a whole attention to the conditions of musical creation opens itself.

As ecology, the musical event arises from the contingent, ephemeral and often ambiguous encounter between multiple elements, which contribute in varying degrees to the expressive quality of the music produced. The quality of a musical performance is thus an issue of encounter between/with the different bodies (human, sonic, technological, etc.) participating in the event: attempting to provoke encounters that will compose an ensemble capable of capturing and making heard unheard forces, a more powerful agencement, able to make tremble together ‘beings’ and ‘things’. There is no relativism here: the process of musical creation requires an increase in the expressive capacities/potentialities of the ensemble, and this power of a musical agencement to affect (or be affected) comes from a fine match of a series of countless conditional factors (and, at some point, a certain margin of luck).

This requires specific techniques. Always singular, a technique is a commitment with the expressive modalities that a practice invents for itself, a (counter-)method Footnote 9 of rigorous experimentation marking a specific turning point in the combination of the creative conditions which determine the quality of the experience (Manning and Massumi Reference Manning and Massumi2014: 89–91; Manning Reference Manning2013: 34). Such a combinatorial art is a question of deploying the uses Footnote 10 that will allow the collective to reach the greatest margin of its expressive potential, and especially to learn about/through these uses. A technique often implies a certain level of repetition: each successive operation incorporates a part of the implicit which underlies the ecology of experimentation opening up, and this requires a patient exploration of how a practice comes better to itself (Manning Reference Manning2013: 33–5).

But one should not think that a technique is the initiative of (a) creative subject(s). As Whitehead’s process philosophy have shown, subjectivity is constituted in the very moment of subjective experience: if there is a subject of the musical creation, it is the creative process as such and only it that can really claim this title: an ecological subjectivity. This has important implications on the process of music creation, but also on the conception of politics. In both cases, the emergence of novelty does not come so much from the intervention of one of the actors involved, but rather from the abstract machine Footnote 11 which catalyses the agencement in its process of expression, like a kind of thinking-motor taking on specific potentialities to make them stand out in the event. For Deleuze and Guattari (Reference Deleuze and Guattari1980: 126–7), collective agencement and abstract machine are not separate: in music (and in politics) there always coexists a singular abstract and a collective concrete. We can feel it particularly in moments of great musical intensity: the experiential effect then comes from the expression of a ‘coming-together of the parts [involved, and] not [from] the parts themselves or their structure’ (Massumi Reference Massumi2011: 149). At this moment, a machinic agencement is expressing itself, making feel the energetic ‘taking’ of a musical ecology. ‘No-one knows who’s playing it: maybe we all are. Perhaps it’s just playing itself. Perhaps it is playing us’ (Gilbert Reference Gilbert, Buchanan and Swiboda2004: 118): what plays then comes under a technical-machinic operation – the machinic involves a series of technical operations; it is by their technical element (their technicity Footnote 12) that the agencements become machines – which capture heterogeneous expression materials in order to associate them in a consistent manner.

One of the key modalities within the techniques of relation that comes to catalyse and modulate the interaction of the components of the musical agencement is the enabling constraint, understood, following Erin Manning (Reference Manning2013: 111), as the setting of the establishment of a series of conditions favouring a limitation of the field of experience while allowing the emerging event to remain open to invention. The concept of enabling constraint encourages the precision of techniques in an open field of experimentation, which can imply the invention of new techniques of collective alignment that go beyond the pure habit of movement (Manning and Massumi Reference Manning and Massumi2014: 91–2). Transposed in the field of improvised music, the concept of enabling constraints resonates with the one of comprovisation.

6. Résonances manifestes: a proposition of phonosophic practice

These aesthetical and epistemological considerations offer much to experiment with: and this is what Résonances manifestes (Devenir-ensemble 2020), a comprovised music piece based on a sound score composed of field recordings from various autonomous demonstrations that shook the streets of Montreal in the recent years, attempted to do. Résonances manifestes is the musical expression of a process of research-creation – at the confluence of music, philosophy and political thought – aiming to understand how sound and music contribute to the (trans)formation of affective communities, these communities in movement which do not stand on pre-established identities or shared interests, but are moved by the intensity and the density of the affects that circulate among them. Footnote 13 Work on the piece has been mobilised by the thoughtful dimension of sound and music elaborated in the previous parts of this article (as it has troubled and contributed to its conceptualisation), at the artistic, philosophical and political level, and appears to be in this sense an original case of phonosophic practice (Sound example 1).

How does a practice orient itself among the countless components of the event? What techniques are required by the creative process to maximise the expressive potentialities of the musical agencement? How does a community emerge in a given acoustic ecology? Such musical and political issues stemming from the creation of the piece Résonances manifestes have found a relevant avenue of exploration in the concept of comprovisation. Footnote 14 Comprovisation is here approached, following author and composer Sandeep Bhagwati (Reference Bhagwati and Paquet2010: 10), as a set of compositional techniques for practices of collective improvisation that rely on singular indications able to orient the musicians without repressing their ‘spontaneous’ expression. The indications could be understood as virtual rules Footnote 15 that inflect contingency through the relative stabilisation of certain elements of the context to act as a support for the musical coming-into-relation of the different components forming the agencement that creates the performance (Nesbitt Reference Nesbitt, Criton and Chouvel2015: 189–92). But the relationships between the various components of the musical agencement are not, as such, the only desires mobilising the production of a piece and/or a performance: what is at stake is also the search for the aesthetic quality, that is, the maximisation of the expressive capacities of the musical agencement.

Always singular and immanent, each musical agencement begins from a problem to be unfolded through the (comprovised) performance: and it is this problem that will determine the type of virtual rule/enabling constraint chosen. These virtual rules coming to support the current expression of the bodies composing the musical agencement often takes the form of a score. The good score is thus the one that makes it possible to address the affective issues related to the singular problem that mobilises the formation of the agencement. Good, in a Spinozist-Deleuzian ethical sense, that is to say as a structure (shaped from the singularity of the (musical) event) of composition of the lived relationships increasing the expressive power of the agencement.

Among the multiple actualisations of the affective community, autonomous political demonstrations appeared as privileged moments through which communities get consistency from the collective perception of sonic elements. It is very often when such gatherings take to the streets that we can see how the affective power of sound acts like a magnetic force, and comes to make us feel the collective in a kind of sensitive immediacy. Such emotional power is evidently at work in certain musical practices. What happens in these moments that take bodies in spite of themselves, before any reflection? The use of recorded ambient sounds appeared particularly relevant to address such a problem focused on the porosity of the common to the environment. So relevant that it appealed to the composition of a sound score.

The score of the piece Résonances manifestes is composed of sounds of demonstrations that have been captured through a sound study realised in the streets of Montreal between 2015 and 2018. This sonic inquiry on the affective communities occurring during the demonstrations has involved hours of recording, listening and note taking, in a continual cycle of composition Footnote 16 that have set the rhythm of the study. A sound study that was not only an opportunity to capture the main materials for the sound score of the piece, but that was also crucial in the development of its internal organisation. Indeed, the reflections that emerged from this process of inquiry oriented the structuring of the piece in nine movements, each expressing an affective tonality Footnote 17 experienced in autonomous demonstrations. These affective tones are sometimes linked to specific moments (e.g., the sudden riot police attack linked to fear-anger affects), but are never totally dependent on them (Sound example 2).

The elaboration of the sound score required a patient sound editing studio work in order to highlight the contrasts and reduce the impact of some disturbances while preserving the roughness that characterises the (sonic) experience of the demonstrations. This editing work was a technical issue in itself: it was a matter of accentuating the qualities already present to support the indicative function of the sounds, rather than authorising all possible alterations, which would have risked breaking the link to the recording context, and therefore one of the specificities of the piece. Footnote 18 In other words, too much sound editing work could have dissipated part of the affective force of these sounds by blurring their physical-actual dimensions, which would have made certain conceptual operations of perception (through which these sounds can be associated with the demonstrations) difficult, thereby lowering their charge of potential. On the other hand, the creation of the piece was mobilised by a non-representational relationship to politics: it was therefore not a question of generating a documentary, or even touristic (‘as if you were on the demo’) relationship to the demonstrations, but rather to share the affective tonalities which marks these singular moments of the common,Footnote 19 to start from these materials to compose new blocks of sensations with their own life. This was achieved through different editing interventions, like the parsimonious use of some sound effects on specific passages of the score to amplify a singular sonic quality, which was a way to alter the sonic recognition and the identification of the lived events to put the attention on what was implied by the sounds, their potential affective charge (Sound example 3).Footnote 20

These technical considerations bring back on another angle the ambivalent dimension of the positions of subject and object stressed by process philosophy: an ecological perspective cannot limit itself to fixed positions such as the ‘subjectivity’ of the composer and the ‘objectivity’ of the sound environment. Sound materials preserve autonomy, they always resist, at some point, the operations of capture. Even more, they can act as the true subjects of a musical event. And that is what they do in the piece Résonances manifestes: the field recordings composing the sound score not only have their own musicality – with which the musicians of the ensemble have to play – but also this musical expression is effectively productive: it provokes, catalyses, extends, pushes the bodies touched by it to consider these sounds not only as objects, but also as true subjects taking part in the performance. ‘As’ the musicians, they can indeed change the mood, contribute to the melodic lines or counterpoints, impose or instil a specific rhythm, etc.: they participate in the phonosophic practice that is then occurring.

Such an agency does not necessarily dissolve all the interventions of the musicians in the field of pure contingency, but it undermines the intentionality and the personality that often reside at the core of the music production. Rather than being only the sum of the addition of individual inspirations, the musical performance then becomes the result of the encounter between human and non-human actors (with different perceptive capacities, different expressive potentialities). The sound score based on field recordings of ambient sounds Footnote 21 thus poses listening as such as a central element of the process of comprovisation: collective perception plays a big role here in the becoming-together of the musical agencement. Because it is, once again, a matter of agencement: it is only according to the collective agencements that perception operates and participates in machines of expression and processes of subjectification (Guattari and Rolnik Reference Guattari and Rolnik2007: 45). Indeed, as Gilbert Simondon (Reference Simondon2013: 353) has shown in his lectures on the perception of the different living beings, the perception of sounds, the way in which a collective entity is affected by sound, orients its very capacity to perceive, to be affected by sounds.

The process of creation of the piece took on the challenge of collective listening in the heat of the moment: the musicians of the ensemble had to learn to elaborate common ears, in a way. In fact, if the collective orientation of the ensemble was mainly based on its listening skills, it is because listening came to be a real material for the piece. This is why the composition of Résonances manifestes involved, in the months before the first performance, a series of listening and reflection workshops with the musicians of the ensemble. This collective training was made necessary in regard to the plurality of sound interventions in the piece. Such a posture has proven to be demanding, requiring not only versatile concentration and opening to unpredictability, instability and loss of bearings, but also excitement and collective intensity which very often mark the autonomous demonstrations. Footnote 22 But such a creative posture of alert and feverish openness has also proven to be uncomfortable for musicians, since it breaks with the metaphysics of individual subjectivity that underlies a large number of musical approaches (Nesbitt Reference Nesbitt, Criton and Chouvel2015: 187–8). There is something risky in these decisive turning points which escape personal will, a risk which can also be the occasion for a magnificent concordance in the adventurous moment, where this fragility of the individual artist turns into a common force that exceeds the sum of its components. A vibrant ecology emerging from a loss of reference points to find others through joint research work and mutual trust in intuitions, which allows for affective densification.

7. Thought-music and ecosophy

As intensification and refinement of listening, music as such is a practice of sustained attention to tones that can actively contribute to the collective flexibilisation of sound perception. By its capacity to generate percepts, that is to say ways of perceiving, music is able to open listening to what remains in the imperceptible, to make appreciable what was previously considered to be a disturbance, to distinguish nuances, textures, the play of vibrations, contrasts, continuities and discontinuities. Isn’t music aimed at exploding the lived perceptions in sound events that transport, invigorate listening itself? Footnote 23

But that does not only concern musical aesthetics: the broadening and the flexibility of perception is a political issue in itself; in fact, refining common perceptions may never have been more crucial, as this epoch can be described as collective torpor, a numbness and/or stiffness in the capacity to share perceptions of the situation. To think between music, philosophy and politics incites to seek the rhythms underlying formal meanings, to explore the multiplicities populating life, to pay attention to potentials of resonance, to start from the productive instability of relationships, to emphasise the openness of processes. This is what the composer and author Pascale Criton (Reference Criton, Criton and Chouvel2015: 11) calls a ‘music-thought’: ‘an ethical posture whose impact is political, an ecology of signs turned towards the play of differences, more than ever very topical’. The elaboration of this ‘music-thought’ will probably need to depart from the logos and its logic of seizure and representation – that remains in the concept of ecology – to embrace the strange and distant relation to knowledge that lives in the sophia. And for this, phonosophy will be a path to explore further, from different trajectories towards multiple experimentations. This one was only a beginning.

Supplementary material

To view supplementary material for this article, please visit https://doi.org/10.1017/S1355771820000230

Footnotes

1 In an interview a year later from this intervention, Guattari (and Johnston Reference Guattari and Johnston2000) felt the need to bring some precision to the concept: ‘I do not propose an aestheticization of the social. I refer to art as a paradigm which highlights three types of problems: that of processual creativity, of the permanent questioning of the identity of the object; that of the polyphony of the enunciation; that of autopoiesis, that is to say of the production of foci of partial subjectification. This type of paradigmatic cocktail is something very important in the field of science, in the social field, for the recomposition of agencements of enunciation. And art is a kind of avant-garde, like a military commando, which is there at the heart of the problem’ (Author’s translation).

2 The concept of agencement (usually translated as ‘assemblage’) elaborated by Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari names the set of interrelated components coming into relation in the production of an event, an enunciation, etc. The concept will not be translated here because, as Erin Manning explains, ‘[the term] “assemblage” has too often been read as an object or existent configuration, rather than in its potentializing directionality. This is why I return to the French term here. Agencement, which carries within itself a sense of movement and connectibility, of processual agency’ (Manning Reference Manning2016: 123).

3 These two concepts, fundamental in Whitehead’s (1967: 176; Reference Whitehead1978: 19, 23) thought, need to be unfolded a little more here. A prehension is a ‘concrete fact of relatedness’ attached to an occasion of experience of which it constitutes a mode of activity, a detail resulting from a division and referring to an outside world. A prehension is thus a vector movement of capture of a particular element of reality, movement that brings to the actual existence. The actual occasion is in a way the atomic unit of Whitehead’s meta-physics. If, for the author, the actual world is a process, the actual occasion can in a way be understood as the ‘landing’ of this process, the elementary component of the fluctuation of the world.

4 For more developments on this idea, see Evens (Reference Evens and Massumi2002), Cox (Reference Cox2009) and Goodman (Reference Goodman2010), among others.

5 For Whitehead (1967: 176; Reference Whitehead1978: 16, 233–4), the subject (of a feeling) emerges as such only in that occasion of experience, that is, as an ‘occasion of sensitive reaction to an actual world’. In that sense, it is often the process itself, or at least what stands out from/through the process, the contrasting element – for instance a perceived noise – that is the real subject of the experience. The concept of datum names the part of the actual world, the surrounding environment that is prehended by a given physical feeling (then becoming the datum of this feeling). Following the example of the noise heard, the datum not only constitutes the objectification of the resonating space of this noise, but also its specific physical qualities and the bodies perceiving it (Whitehead Reference Whitehead1978: 22, 225, 234). This means, since ‘every prehension is a prehension of prehension’ (Deleuze Reference Deleuze1988: 105; author’s translation), that subject and object appear to be relative terms, which could be distinguished only according to their activity (or, for William James (Reference James2012 1, III, VI), in function of their potential perspective in a given context of experience and not in function of a so-called ontological essence). In other words, in the philosophy of process, subjectivity and objectivity become co-implying terms in an occasion.

6 A fundamental type of entity in Whitehead’s process philosophy (with actual occasions), the eternal objects embody permanence in the flow of events, and that is what makes them so precious for conceptual feelings (Deleuze Reference Deleuze1988: 107). ‘[Eternal objects] are what give the occasion its nuance. They are the thisness of the event’s qualitative difference – just this quality of sound, just this colour tone, just this affective tonality’ (Manning Reference Manning2020).

7 This process of capture implies among others a decoding of the immanent but unheard forces that move the social, a process without which the creation would not pass the threshold of the sensible (Deleuze and Guattari Reference Deleuze and Guattari1980: 271, 630).

8 But Westerkamp has an ambivalent relation to the deterritorialisation inherent to the musical operation, insisting on the necessity for a music piece to preserve some link with the place of origin of the recorded sounds: ‘What does it take then to create such a composition from the found sound materials, in other words a piece with its own integrity, a new moment in time in a new place with its very own life and characteristics, yet still sonically connected to the place and time of the original recordings and the composer’s own experiences?’ (Westerkamp Reference Westerkamp2002: 53). This issue will be addressed in the following sections.

9 Because very often, a method implies the application of categories fixed beforehand to an object defined as such, then excluding or ignoring the processes that do not fit into its thought schemes. Almost never able to get rid of its Cartesian foundations, the method is thus based on a narrow conception of knowledge, where consciousness, language and rationality take precedence, and which often ends up extracting the immanent dimension of thought from experience: ‘Despite its best intentions, method works as the safeguard against the ineffable’ (Manning Reference Manning2016: 32).

10 The concept of use is understood here in the Agambian (Agamben Reference Agamben2015: 136) sense, that is, as a field of tension between loss and capture. In what matters here, ‘using’ then underlies to respect the radical autonomy of what is captured in the moment of creation. In that sense, ‘mastering’ a technique implies a perpetual opening to an exteriority that exceeds all notion of property. This idea, which concerns art, politics, life, will be developed in the following sections.

11 The abstract machine designates the singular operation that opens (or sometimes closes, depending on) the agencement to its potential by deterritorialising it through the continuous variation of one or more of its components and/or by the association with other components (logistic-material, conceptual, biological, etc.). ‘The abstract machines … constitute a kind of matter of change … composed of crystals of potentiality catalysing the connexions, the destratifications and the reterritorialisations from both the living world and the inanimate world’ (Guattari Reference Guattari1979: 13; author’s translation).

12 Technicity can be closely associated to the abstract machines: the concept refers to all the ‘enabling conditions’ capturing the affective tone of a process to project it towards a new expression, it is the operational field of the expressiveness of the techniques, opening them to their compositional potential. Technique and technicity are inseparable: the technicity is in a way the excess of potential of the technique. The different techniques create potential opportunities for a singularity of form to give rise to a generative process, they actualise the potential which lies in the field of technicity (Manning Reference Manning2013: 33).

13 It is also important to specify briefly that the work on the piece has been the occasion to develop the ecological dimension of the concept of affective community. The affective community takes in a common becoming all bodies – living or not, human or not – that are linked by/in its field of resonance (Collectif pour l’intervention 2012: 47–8). It is the tonality of this relationship between bodies, worlds, which qualifies the affective community. Indeed, in a music performance or in a demonstration, it is through the ecological attunement to the multiplicities that animate the event that a new collective individuation can emerge (Manning Reference Manning2013: 219).

14 The concept of comprovisation comes from the contributions and limits of the poles of musical practice that improvisation and composition are to deepen the concomitant zone between the two and create affirmative machinic propositions from it – think and experiment from the in-between.

15 The notion of rule must be understood here as the construction of a continuum of variation, a series of optional norms that emerge from the variability of the components (Deleuze and Guattari Reference Deleuze and Guattari1980: 130).

16 Recording – listening/discussion/collective reflection – composition(s)/intervention(s) – new recording: this is the perpetual cycle that marks the militant sound investigation of the collective Ultra-red (2008), whose approach greatly influenced the sound study realised for this project of research-creation.

17 The affective tonality marks the quality of the consistency that takes on beings, things and ambiances – in sum all the molecular multiplicities animating any event – in a common becoming. The sensible quality of a vibrating ecology comes from the affective tonality that characterises its expressibility, the way this occasion of experience feels itself with others. The interplay between the affective tones, to which we can access through practices of affective attunement, reveals a whole politics of frequencies.

18 In this sense, the relationship with these singular sounds in the creation of the score can be situated between two major contemporary tendencies in the sound editing of field recordings. The soundscape composition insists on the link between the ambient sounds and their context of ‘origin’, a link which must be maintained (at some point) in order to avoid the creation of (mainly) schizophonic relationships to ambient sounds or even the control of nature through sound manipulation (Westerkamp Reference Westerkamp2002: 52–5; DeLuca Reference DeLuca2017). At the opposite, the acousmatic approach allows all possible transformations, without any consideration for the ‘original’ context of a recorded sound in order to subsume all the components under the musical quality of the sounds. The approach mobilised in Résonances manifestes was determined by the considerations required by the process of creation of the piece, without any moral relation to these contemporary tendencies.

19 Such an approach is inspired by the one developed by Bob Ostertag (Reference Ostertag2009: 116) for the piece All the Rage, created in collaboration with the Kronos Quartet from sounds captured during the queer riots in San Francisco (Ostertag and the Kronos Quartet Reference Ostertag1991): ‘The point was not to transform the riot into something else, but to use music to bring the listener into the riot. Not the gimmicky sense of creating an audio illusion of actually being in the riot, but to get inside the energy, the passion, and most of all the anger.’

20 This non-representational approach determined many more dimensions of the music piece; for instance, it also influenced the relatively non-chronological progression of the different movements composing the piece, which have rather been organised according to a potential succession of affective tonalities. A similar approach has been used in Christopher DeLaurenti’s activist sound series (DeLaurenti Reference DeLaurenti2016), where the cut-up montage amplifies the contrasts in/between the acoustic ecologies of/around demonstrations, far from any chronological structuration. But DeLaurenti’s work on demonstrations differ in many ways, among others through the emphasis put on human voices (that lower the attention accorded to the non-human plurality in the acoustic ecologies) and the restraint in the musical expression living with the recorded sounds. In spite of these differences, which cannot really be unfolded here, the activist sound series and the Protest Symphonies can be considered as true phonosophic creations.

21 Westerkamp stresses the specific capacity of such sounds to make hear what is often unheard in the everyday experience: the field recordings interrupt the familiarity to a given context, putting the ears in a state of auditory alertness (Westerkamp Reference Westerkamp, Rothenberg and Ulvaeus2001: 148). Listening to recorded ambient sounds can potentially refine the attention to the nuances and contrasts present (but often not perceived) in a sound ecology, giving access to the non-perceived dimensions of the environment and opening up listening to different modes of perception.

22 Indeed, the composite acoustic ecology of Résonances manifestes – formed of a complex association of field recordings, ambient sounds specific to the place of the performance and sounds produced by the instruments of musicians – directly echoes to issues related to the attention to the ambiances and affective tones in the consistency of communities, to the musicality of the actual sounds of politics and to the collective perception of sounds. But this collectivisation of listening corresponds only partly to the ‘sonic commons’ mentioned by Eric Drott (Reference Drott2018: 637) in his article on the drum circle of Occupy Wall Street: these commons refer to the sharing of a soundscape, while the work of common listening effectuated in the creation of the piece Résonances manifestes implies a collective refinement of the perception of sound. In other words, it was not only to learn to interact in a shared soundscape, but also to sharpen a capacity to phonosophy together in live performance.

23 This question underlies a nuance too crucial for the little place it has taken in this article: the bodies are affected by (dimensions of) sounds and music that they are not able to perceive. As Brian Massumi (Reference Massumi2011: 145) stresses, music mobilises incorporeal signs. Hearing – like other senses – is too slow to perceive the atomic actuality of a sound in the tiny instant when it reaches the body: at a certain level, what is perceived is rather a question of non-sensuous perceptions, that is to say, the micro-intervals qualitatively and abstractly charged with affects which come from the virtual (abstract) composition of the senses (Massumi Reference Massumi2011: 18, 65). It means that vibrational force (potentially able to contract in sounds) has effects, even when it is unperceived or even imperceptible. Nevertheless, this effectiveness of the imperceptible must be thought, for most living beings, in relation to the physical-sensory dimension of perception – as the virtual can never be separated from its actualisations in experience.

References

REFERENCES

Agamben, G. 2015. L’Usage des corps. Homo Sacer, IV, 2, trans. J. Gayraud. Paris: Seuil.Google Scholar
Attali, J. 1977. Bruits. Essai sur l’économie politique de la musique. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Bergson, H. 1966. La Pensée et le mouvant. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Bhagwati, S. 2010. Composing through the Realm of Shadows. Conceptual Layers in ‘Inside a Native Land’ and ‘Vineland Stelae’. In Paquet, B. (ed.) Faire œuvre. Transparence et opacité. Sainte-Foy: Presses de l’Université Laval, 311.Google Scholar
Cage, J. 1961. Silence: Lecture and Writings. Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press.Google Scholar
Collectif pour l’intervention. 2012. Communisme: un manifeste. Caen: Nous.Google Scholar
Comité invisible. 2014. À nos amis. Montreal: pirate edition.Google Scholar
Cox, C. 2009. Sound Art and the Sonic Unconscious. Organised Sound 14 (1): 1926.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Criton, P. 2015. Avant-propos. In Criton, P. and Chouvel, J.-M. (eds.) Gilles Deleuze. La pensée-musique. Paris: Centre de documentation de la musique contemporaine, 912.Google Scholar
DeLaurenti, C. 2016. Activist Sound. Soundcloud. https://soundcloud.com/delaurenti/sets/activist-sound (accessed 24 March 2020).Google Scholar
Deleuze, G. 1988. Le Pli – Leibniz et le baroque. Paris: Minuit.Google Scholar
Deleuze, G. 2002. Francis Bacon. Logique de la sensation. Paris: Seuil.Google Scholar
Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. 1980. Mille plateaux. Capitalisme et schizophrénie 2. Paris: Minuit.Google Scholar
Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. 2005. Qu’est-ce que la philosophie?. Paris: Minuit.Google Scholar
DeLuca, Erik. 2017. Wolf Listeners: Acoustemological Politics and Poetics of Isle Royale National Park. Presentation at the Still Listening: Pauline Oliveros Commemoration. Montréal: Institute for the Public Life of Ideas.Google Scholar
Drott, Eric. 2018. Music Contention and Contentious Music; or, the Drums of Occupy Wall Street. Contemporary Music Review 37 (5–6): 626645.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evens, A. 2002. Sound ideas. In Massumi, B. (ed.) A Shock to Thought. Expression after Deleuze and Guattari. London: Routledge, 171–87.Google Scholar
Gilbert, J. 2004. Becoming-Music: The Rhizomatic Moment of Improvisation. In Buchanan, I. and Swiboda, P. (eds.) Deleuze and Music. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 118–39.Google Scholar
Goodman, S. 2010. Sonic Warfare. Sound, Affect, and the Ecology of Fear. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Guattari, F. 1979. L’Inconscient machinique. Paris: Recherches.Google Scholar
Guattari, F. 2011. Produire une culture du dissensus. Hétérogenèse et paradigme esthétique. Université ouverte. http://cip-idf.org/article.php3?id_article=5613 (accessed 7 August 2018).Google Scholar
Guattari, F. and Johnston, J. 2000. Vertige de l’immanence. Félix Guattari, entretien. Chimères. 38: 1-18 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guattari, F. and Rolnik, S. 2007. Micropolitiques. Paris: Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond/Seuil.Google Scholar
Harney, S. and Moten., F. 2014. The Undercommons: Fugitive Planning and Black Study. New York: Autonomedia.Google Scholar
James, W. 2012. Essays on Radical Empiricism. Adelaïde: University of Adelaïde Library.Google Scholar
Manning, E. 2013. Always More than One. Individuation’s Dance. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Manning, E. 2016. The Minor Gesture. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manning, E. 2020 [forthcoming]. For a Pragmatics of the Useless. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Manning, E. and Massumi, B. 2014. Thought in the Act. Passages in the Ecology of Experience. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Massumi, B. 2011. Semblance and Event. Activist Philosophy and the Occurent Arts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Nesbitt, N. 2015. Critique and Clinique. From Sounding Bodies to the Musical Event. In Criton, P. and Chouvel, J.-M. (eds.) Gilles Deleuze. La pensée-musique. Paris: Centre de documentation de la musique contemporaine, 187–98.Google Scholar
Ostertag, B. 2009. Creative Life . Music, Politics, People and Machines. Champaign: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Rector, T. and Ernest, M. 2017. Standing Rock, Protest, Sound and Power (part 2). Sounding Out! 64. http://soundstudiesblog.com/2017/11/30/sounding-out-podcast-64-standing-rock-protest-sound-and-power-part-2 (accessed 25 June 2019).Google Scholar
Simondon, G. 2013. Cours sur la perception. 1964–1965. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ultra-red. 2008. Some Thesis on Militant Sound Investigation, or, Listening for a Change. In the Middle of a Whirlwind. http://inthemiddleofthe whirlwind.wordpress.com/some-theses-on-militant-sound-investigationor-listening-for-a-change/ Google Scholar
Westerkamp, H. 2001. Speaking From Inside the Soundscape. In Rothenberg, D. and Ulvaeus, M. (eds.) The Book of Music and Nature. Middletown: Wesleyan University Press, 143–53.Google Scholar
Westerkamp, H. 2002. Linking Soundscape Composition and Acoustic Ecology. Organised Sound 7 (1): 51–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whitehead, A. N. 1967. Adventure of Ideas. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Whitehead, A. N. 1978. Process and Reality. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar

Discography

Devenir-ensemble. 2020 [forthcoming]. Résonances manifestes. Montreal: Cuchabata records.Google Scholar
Ostertag, B. and the Kronos Quartet. 1991. All the Rage. New York: Nonesuch records.Google Scholar

Gendron-Blais Supplementary Materials

Gendron-Blais Supplementary Materials 1

Download Gendron-Blais Supplementary Materials(Audio)
Audio 4 MB

Gendron-Blais Supplementary Materials

Gendron-Blais Supplementary Materials 2

Download Gendron-Blais Supplementary Materials(Audio)
Audio 7 MB

Gendron-Blais Supplementary Materials

Gendron-Blais Supplementary Materials 3

Download Gendron-Blais Supplementary Materials(Audio)
Audio 3.7 MB