Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x5gtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-16T22:28:18.064Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Explanation v. Prediction: Which Carries More Weight?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Peter Achinstein*
Affiliation:
Johns Hopkins University

Extract

According to a standard view, predictions of new phenomena provide stronger evidence for a theory than explanations of old ones. More guardedly, a theory that predicts phenomena that did not prompt the initial formulation of that theory is better supported by those phenomena than is a theory by known phenomena that generated the theory in the first place. So say various philosophers of science, including William Whewell (1847) in the 19th century and Karl Popper (1959) in the 20th, to mention just two.

Stephen Brush takes issue with this on historical grounds. In a series of fascinating papers he argues that generally speaking scientists do not regard the fact that a theory predicts new phenomena, even ones of a kind totally different from those that prompted the theory in the first place, as providing better evidential support for that theory than is provided by already known facts explained by the theory.

Type
Part V. Do Explanations or Predictions (or Neither) Provide More Evidential Support for Scientific Theories?
Copyright
Copyright © 1995 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Achinstein, P. (1991), Particles and Waves. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brush, S. (1989), “Prediction and Theory Evaluation: The Case of Light Bending,Science 246: 1124-29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchwald, J. (1994), The Creation of Scientific Effects. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, R. (1962), Logical Foundations of Probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2nd ed.Google Scholar
Glymour, C. (1980), Theory and Evidence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. (1945), “Studies in the Logic of Confirmation,Mind 54: 126, 97-121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hertz, H. (1896), Miscellaneous Papers. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Keynes, J.M. (1921), A Treatise on Probability. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Mayo, D. (1991), “Novel Evidence and Severe Tests,Philosophy of Science 58: 523-52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Musgrave, A. (1974), “Logical versus Historical Theories of Confirmation,British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 25: 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. (1959), The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Rayleigh, R. (1942), The Life of Sir J.J. Thomson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Snyder, L. (1994), “Is Evidence Historical,Scientific Methods: Conceptual and Historical Problems, Achinstein, P. and Snyder, L., eds. Malabar, Florida: Krieger.Google Scholar
Thomson, J.J. (1897), “Cathode Rays,The Electrician 39: 104108.Google Scholar
Whewell, W. (1847), The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences. New York: Johnson Reprint, 1967.Google Scholar
Zahar, E. (1973), “Why Did Einstein's Programme Supercede Lorentz's,British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24: 95123, 223-62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar