Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vfjqv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T07:55:34.099Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Structure Thirty Years Later: Refashioning a Constructivist Metaphysical Program

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Sergio Sismondo*
Affiliation:
Cornell University

Extract

I argue here that for the past thirty years there has been a persistent misreading of Thomas Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Not everybody has participated in this misreading, but its persistence is remarkable. So one of my tasks is to diagnose the reasons for its continuance. It is also an important misreading, because it attributes to Kuhn a view that is from most people’s perspective highly untenable, that scientists in some strong sense construct the world by choosing a paradigm.

To avoid repeating work done by Gutting and many others (see Gutting 1980) I will focus on Kuhn’s constructivist metaphysical program, as seen by commentators.

Type
Part VIII. Kuhnian Themes: SSR at Thirty
Copyright
Copyright © 1992 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bloor, D. (1991), Knowledge and Social Imagery. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Boyd, R.N. (1990), “Realism, conventionality, and ‘realism about’”, in Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam, Boolos, G. (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p. 171-195.Google Scholar
Boyd, R.N.. (1992), “Constructivism, Realism, and Philosophical Method”, in Inference, Explanation, and Other Philosophical Frustrations, Earman, J. (ed.). Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Fine, A. (1986), The Shaky Game: Einstein, Realism and the Quantum Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gutting, G. (ed.) (1980), Paradigms and Revolutions: Applications and Appraisals of Thomas Kuhn’s Philosophy of Science. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Haraway, D. (1988), “Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective”, Feminist Studies 14: 575-599.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1989a), Die Wissenschaftsphilosophie Thomas S.Kuhns: Rekonstruktion und Grundlagenprobleme. Braunschweig: F. Vieweg & Sohn.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1989b), “Idealist Elements in Thomas Kuhn’s Philosophy of Science”, History of Philosophy Quarterly, Volume 6, Number 4: 393-401.Google Scholar
Kordig, C.R. (1971), The Justification of Scientific Change. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T.S. (1970a), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T.S. (1970b), “Reflections on my Critics”, in Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. (eds.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 231-278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T.S. (1974), “Second Thoughts on Paradigms”, in The Structure of Scientific Theories, Suppe, F.(ed.). Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press: 459-482.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T.S. (1979), “Metaphor in Science”, in Metaphor and Thought, Ortony, A. (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 409-419.Google Scholar
Price, D J. de Solla (1984), “Notes Towards a Philosophy of the Science/Technology Interaction”, in The Nature of Technological Knowledge, Laudan, R. (ed.). Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Scheffler, I. (1967), Science and Subjectivity. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar