Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-4rdrl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-18T13:38:09.385Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

What Is It to Be Responsible for What You Say?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 May 2024

Abstract

In asserting something I incur certain kinds of liabilities, including a responsibility for the truth of the content I express. If I say ‘After leaving the EU, the UK will take back control of c. £350 million per week’, or I tell you that ‘The number 14 bus stops at the British Museum’, I become liable for the truth of these claims. As my audience, you could hold me unreliable or devious if it turns out that what I said is false. Yet this socio-linguistic practice – of acquiring and ascribing ‘linguistic liability’ – is complicated, especially given philosophical distinctions between the various different kinds of contents people can express (am I liable, for instance, for the claim that the number 14 bus stops at the British Museum today or only usually?). This paper explores the different kinds of contents speakers might be taken to express, arguing that our practices around linguistic liability (including in legal disputes) reveal a crucial role for a notion of context-independent, literal meaning attaching to words and sentences. These practices thus vindicate what philosophers tend to term ‘minimal semantic content’.

Type
Paper
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2024

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bach, Kent, ‘The Top Ten Misconceptions about Implicature’, in Birner, Betty and Ward, Gregory (eds), Drawing the Boundaries of Meaning: Neo-Gricean Studies in Pragmatics and Semantics in Honor of Laurence R. Horn (Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 2006), 2130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borg, Emma and Connolly, Patrick, ‘Strict and Conversational Linguistic Liability: Some Empirical Observations’, in Lepore, Ernest and Sosa, David (eds), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2022), 122.Google Scholar
Borg, Emma, Minimal Semantics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borg, Emma, Pursuing Meaning (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borg, Emma, ‘Explanatory Roles for Minimal Content’, Noûs, 53:3 (2019), 513–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Alexander, ‘What is Hate Speech? Part 1: The Myth of Hate’, Law and Philosophy, 36:4 (2017), 419–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carston, Robyn, Thoughts and Utterances (Oxford: Blackwell, 2002).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carston, Robyn, ‘Review of Minimal Semantics’, Mind & Language, 23:3 (2008), 359–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grice, Paul, Studies in the Way of Words (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989).Google Scholar
Gries, Stefan, ‘Corpora and Legal Interpretation: Corpus Approaches to Ordinary Meaning in Legal Interpretation’, in Coulthard, Malcolm and Johnson, Alison (eds), Routledge Handbook of Forensic Linguistics, 2nd edition (London: Routledge, 2020), 628–43.Google Scholar
Hansen, Nathaniel, ‘“Nobody Would Really Talk That Way!” The Critical Project in Contemporary Ordinary Language Philosophy’, Synthese, 197:6 (2018), 2433–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard, Jeffrey, ‘Dangerous Speech’, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 47:2 (2019), 208–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard, Jeffrey, ‘Terror, Hate, and the Demands of Counterspeech’, British Journal of Political Science, 51:3 (2021), 924–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, Thomas and Mouritsen, Stephen, ‘Judging Ordinary Meaning’, Yale Law Journal, 127:4 (2017), 788879.Google Scholar
Lee, Thomas and Mouritsen, Stephen, ‘The Corpus and the Critics’, University Chicago Law Review, 88:2 (2021), 275366.Google Scholar
Lepoutre, Maxime, Vilar-Lluch, Sara, Borg, Emma, and Hansen, Nat, ‘What is Hate Speech? The Case for a Corpus Approach’, Criminal Law and Philosophy, (2023).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinson, Stephen, Presumptive Meanings: The Theory of Generalized Conversational Implicature (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2000).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mouritsen, Stephen, ‘Hard Cases and Hard Data’, Columbia Science & Technology Law Review, 13:1 (2012), 156205.Google Scholar
Searle, John, ‘The Background of Meaning’, in Searle, John, Keifer, Ferenc, and Bierwisch, Manfred (eds), Speech Act Theory and Pragmatics (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1980), 221–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sperber, Dan and Wilson, Deirdre, Relevance: Communication and Cognition (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986).Google Scholar
Tobia, Kevin, ‘Testing Ordinary Meaning’, Harvard Law Review, 134:2 (2020), 726806.Google Scholar
Williamson, Timothy, ‘Knowing and Asserting’, The Philosophical Review, 105:4 (1996), 489523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar