Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-skm99 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T02:11:54.850Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Markets and Morals: Self, Character and Markets

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Extract

A market may be defined as a set of competitive relationships in which agents strive, within limits set by ground rules, to better their own economic positions, not necessarily at the expense of other people, but not necessarily not at their expense either. A degree of indifference to the market fates of others is, manifestly, an inevitable feature of the market practice, so defined. But though indifference is clearly logically endemic to markets, it has been denied that selfishness is necessarily involved in the raw competition of market activity. Thus, Hayek maintains that market behaviour is not selfish on the grounds that the market is a competitive non zero-sum ‘wealth-creating game’ in which individuals ‘use their own knowledge for their own ends’ in a system whose operations, via the ‘Invisible Hand’, also produce unintended benefits for others. But for behaviour to be selfish it clearly need not necessarily disbenefit other people; it is enough that it is pursued, or persisted in, regardless of its effects upon others. And this is precisely what the institutional ‘indifference’ of market activity amounts to. Admittedly individuals who understand the Hayekian logic of the market know (or believe) that the long-run chances of everyone's benefiting are maximized by acting in a rigorously competitive manner, and so they at least in one sense act with a ‘regard for others’. But ipso facto this category of market agents has an even stronger reason than the ignorantly selfish for disregarding the specific interests of all the particular individuals with whom they have economically to do. ‘Market selfishness’, the disregard for others' market interests, is thus a logically inevitable feature of market activity.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 1989

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Hayek, F. A., Law, Legislation and Liberty, Vol. 2, The Mirage of Social Justice (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1982), 153–4.Google Scholar

2 Acton, H. B., The Morals of Markets: an Ethical Exploration (London: Longman, 1971), 13.Google Scholar

3 Waldron, J. (ed.), Nonsense Upon Stilts: Bentham, Burke and Marx on the Rights of Man (London: Methuen, 1987), 204.Google Scholar

4 ‘Political Theory and Ideology: the case of the state’, in Miller, D. and Siedentop, L. A. (eds), The Nature of Political Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), 5373.Google Scholar Hayek presents his own notable evolutionary view of social development, in which he situates the individual in a nexus of social relations—for him too the individual is ‘socially produced’. The difference, of course, is that for him the ‘abstract individual’ of market society is philosophically and ethically unproblematical. See e.g. Gray, John, Hayek On Liberty, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1984), esp. Ch. 1.Google Scholar

5 ‘Political Theory and Ideology’, 59.Google Scholar

6 Pashukanis, E. V., Law and Marxism: a General Theory, Arthur, C. (ed.) (London: Ink Links, 1978), esp. Ch. 4.Google Scholar

7 Marx, K., Grundrisse (Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1973), 265.Google Scholar

8 Marx, K. and Engels, F., The German Ideology, Arthur, C. (ed.) (New York: International Publishers, 1970), 83 and 82.Google Scholar

9 Smith, A., Lectures on Jurisprudence, Meek, R. L. et al. (eds) (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1982), 538.Google Scholar Smith's apparently self-depreciatory reference to the Scots loses its irony in the light of the vital difference for him between feckless Highland clansmen and canny Lowlanders like himself.

10 Lectures on Jurisprudence, 493.Google Scholar

11 Sen, A. K., On Ethics and Economics (Oxford: Blackwell, 1987), 24.Google Scholar

12 Sen, , On Ethics and Economics, 23–5.Google Scholar

13 Nieli, R., ‘Spheres of Intimacy and the Adam Smith Problem’, Journal of the History of Ideas, XLVII (1986), 611–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

14 See Sen, , On Ethics and EconomicsGoogle Scholar, Ch. 1 passim.

15 The locus classicus is, of course, Ch. 3 of On Liberty.

16 Berger, F. R., Happiness, Justice and Freedom: the Moral and Political Philosophy of J. S. Mill (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984), 1719.Google Scholar

17 Happiness, Justice and Freedom, 17.Google Scholar

18 Gray, J. N., ‘Mill's and Other Liberalisms’, in Haakonssen, K. (ed.), Traditions of Liberalism: Essays on Locke, Smith and j. S. Mill (St Leonards, NSW: Centre for Independent Studies, 1988), 119–41, esp. section 3.Google Scholar

19 Mill, J. S., System of Logic, Collected Works, Robson, J. M. (ed.) (Toronto: Toronto University Press, 1969), Vol. 8, Book 6 passim.Google Scholar

20 For a discussion of the connection between character, freedom and virtue in Mill's ‘proof’ of human freedom in a deterministic world, see my ‘The Logic of J. S. Mill on Liberty’ Political Studies, XXVIII (1980), 232–52.Google Scholar

21 Mill, J. S.Principles of Political Economy, Collected Works, Robson, J. M. (ed.) (Toronto University Press, 1965), Vol. 3, 794.Google Scholar

22 Ibid., 795.

23 Ibid., Vol. 3, Book 4, Ch. 7.

24 Ibid., Vol. 2, Book 3, Ch. 7, sections. 2 and 3.

25 Ibid., Vol. 3, Book 4.

26 ‘I confess I am not charmed with the ideal of life held out by those who think that the normal state of human beings is that of struggling to get on; that the trampling, crushing, elbowing, and treading on each other's heels, which form the existing type of social life, are the most desirable lot of human kind, or anything but the disagreeable symptoms of one of the phases of industrial progress.’ (Ibid., Vol. 3, 754.)

27 Gray, , ‘Mill's and Other Liberalisms’, 130–2.Google Scholar