Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-31T11:13:11.913Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Leader Authenticity and Ethics: A Heideggerian Perspective

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 November 2023

Florence Villesèche
Affiliation:
Copenhagen Business School, Denmark
Anders Klitmøller
Affiliation:
Royal Danish Defence College, Denmark
Cathrine Bjørnholt Michaelsen
Affiliation:
Copenhagen Business School, Denmark
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In the shadow of various business scandals and societal crises, scholars and practitioners have developed a growing interest in authentic leadership. This approach to leadership assumes that leaders may access and leverage their “true selves” and “core values” and that the combination of these two elements forms the basis from which they act resolutely, lead ethically, and benefit others. Drawing on Heidegger’s work, we argue that a concern for authenticity can indeed instigate a leadership ethic, albeit one that acknowledges the unfounded openness of existence and its inherent relationality. On this basis, we propose an ethics-as-practice approach in which leaders respond to the situation at hand by being “attuned to attunement,” which cultivates an openness to otherness and a responsibility to others.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Society for Business Ethics

If you yearn for authentic, moral, and character-based leaders, read on (George, Reference George2003: 5).

Leadership ethics—the ethical formulations and foundations of how leaders should act in organizations—attracts both scholarly and practitioner interest. Moreover, “in many ways, leadership ethics is an umbrella for all areas of professional ethics” (Ciulla, Reference Ciulla2020: xi), and leadership ethics is thus central to business ethics in a way that cannot be represented by ethics statements or codes for business conduct alone (Flynn & Werhane, Reference Flynn, Werhane and Flynn2022: 1). Regardless of whether they have formal roles, leaders are expected to be effective, to be morally exemplary, and to help their organizations and others to thrive (Ciulla, Knights, Mabey, & Tomkins, Reference Ciulla, Knights, Mabey and Tomkins2018). Although leadership may be defined in a more processual or distributed manner, attributions of leadership tend to be made toward persons rather than relations (Ciulla et al., Reference Ciulla, Knights, Mabey and Tomkins2018). In addition, “followers” tend to question a leader’s competence and morality when crises arise (Ciulla, Reference Ciulla1995), including team-level conflicts, project failure, and corporate bankruptcy. Leaders are cognizant of such expectations and may become deeply concerned, or even experience anxiety, at the prospect of failing their followers and their organizations and ceasing to be seen as leaders (Segal, Reference Segal2010).

In response to such concerns, a substantial body of work is engaging with normative leadership theories in which ethics takes center stage, such as transformational leadership, servant leadership, aesthetic leadership, and authentic leadership (Ciulla & Forsyth, Reference Ciulla, Forsyth, Bryman, Collinson, Grint, Jackson and Uhl-Bien2011; Johnson, Reference Johnson2019; Lemoine, Hartnell, & Leroy, Reference Lemoine, Hartnell and Leroy2019). In this article, we focus on authentic leadership (AL), which is growing in popularity among current and aspiring leaders in the business world. AL is concerned with the salience of self over role (Lemoine et al., Reference Lemoine, Hartnell and Leroy2019) and with how self-knowledge grounds leaders’ morality and is conducive to effective and ethical action in business (Ciulla, Reference Ciulla2020: 154). The concern for authenticity in leadership has been popularized through best-selling business books by George (George, Reference George2003; George & Clayton, Reference George and Clayton2022; George & Sims, Reference George and Sims2007), Brown (Reference Brown2012, Reference Brown2018), and Cashman (Reference Cashman2017), among others. This approach to leadership assumes that leaders may access and leverage their “true selves” and “core values” and that the combination of these two elements forms the basis from which they act resolutely, lead ethically, and benefit others. AL has also become the subject of a stream of scholarly literature that echoes and thus legitimizes the rationale presented in the aforementioned bestsellers. It appears, for example, in studies defining traits of authentic leaders and measuring how they are perceived and how they perform (Iszatt-White, Carroll, Gardiner, & Kempster, Reference Iszatt-White, Carroll, Gardiner and Kempster2021). The topic of AL furthermore features in various higher education courses and programs, including those at top-ranking institutions like Harvard.

However, in their recent work, Fischer and Sitkin (Reference Fischer and Sitkin2023) dispute that so-called positive styles of leadership inevitably lead to desirable outcomes. Moreover, the foundational theories and implications of AL have been challenged in recent research. Arguments have been put forward concerning the supposed existence of a “true” and “stable” self, the idea that we can and should align or even merge our personal and professional selves, and how to distinguish authentic from inauthentic leaders (Alvesson & Einola, Reference Alvesson and Einola2019; Johnsen, Reference Johnsen2018; Kempster, Iszatt-White, & Brown, Reference Kempster, Iszatt-White and Brown2019; Ladkin & Taylor, Reference Ladkin and Taylor2010). Regarding efforts to practice AL, the literature shows how difficult it is for women and persons from other (organizational) minority groups to come across as authentic leaders (Ladkin, Reference Ladkin2021; Monzani, Hernandez Bark, Van Dick, & Peiró, Reference Monzani, Hernandez Bark, Van Dick and Peiró2015) or to perceive themselves as such (Lee, Reference Lee2020).

Iszatt-White and Kempster (Reference Iszatt-White and Kempster2019) suggest that we need to go beyond the positive psychology aspect of AL and approach authenticity from other angles, such as psychoanalytic or existentialist perspectives, to interrogate the practice of (authentic) leadership. Their proposal echoes calls over the years, including in this journal, for a more rigorous, philosophical discussion, in business ethics, of leadership ethics and leadership styles that focus on the moral dimension (Ciulla, Reference Ciulla1995; Ciulla et al., Reference Ciulla, Knights, Mabey and Tomkins2018). Responding to these calls, we draw on discussions of authenticity in Heidegger’s work. Our interest in authenticity as a relevant concern for business ethics and leadership resonates with philosophical arguments positing authenticity as an unavoidable ethos in contemporary times, notably the work of Taylor (Reference Taylor1991). Our aim here is thus not to “correct” practitioners in their aspirations and desires for what they refer to as authenticity but to contemplate what it means to invoke authenticity in relation to leadership and the implications for the ethics of leadership practice in the AL versus Heideggerian perspective. Other work related to leadership and authenticity has employed Heideggerian concepts (see, e.g., Cunliffe & Hibbert, Reference Cunliffe, Hibbert and Raelin2016; Segal, Reference Segal2010; Zundel, Reference Zundel2012); however, in these studies, the ethics discussion remains rather implicit (Ciulla, Reference Ciulla2020) or concerns a group of philosophers connected to existentialism in business ethics more broadly (Agarwal & Cruise Malloy, Reference Agarwal and Cruise Malloy2000; Ashman & Winstanley, Reference Ashman and Winstanley2006).

In this article, we argue for leadership ethics derived from Heidegger’s understanding of authenticity and advocate a resolute practice of being “attuned to attunement,” which cultivates an openness to otherness and a responsibility to others in day-to-day leadership performance. Moreover, we discuss how leadership ethics derived from AL raises ethical concerns, particularly related to a circular logic in judging what constitutes authenticity and, by extension, ethical leadership (Ciulla, Reference Ciulla2020). In developing these arguments, we contribute to the integration of insights from Continental philosophy into business ethics (see, e.g., Ciulla et al., Reference Ciulla, Knights, Mabey and Tomkins2018; Painter-Morland, Reference Painter-Morland, Werhane, Freeman and Dmytriyev2017). Our work adds an existential-ontological ethics dimension to the discussion of authenticity in relation to leadership and the consequences for business ethics. We provide an alternative to the dominant conceptualization of authenticity in leadership and contribute to the scholarship on nonfoundational approaches to ethical questions in business, which is notably found in the stream of research on ethics-as-practice (Clegg, Kornberger, & Rhodes, Reference Clegg, Kornberger and Rhodes2007; Painter-Morland, Reference Painter-Morland2008). Here it should be noted that nonfoundational ethics does not indicate indifferent, neutral, or merely descriptive ethics. We define nonfoundational ethics as an approach to ethical concerns in which there is no principal or ultimate basis of ethics and which therefore demands us to respond to ethical questions that have no final or universal answers. Thus nonfoundational ethics is not concerned with defining or formulating universal, general, or transcendental principles and standards of what is right or good but instead focuses on the practice of responding to singular ethical concerns and situations.

Moreover, this article holds significance for leaders eager to lead ethically and who have an interest in AL. Indeed, it takes their wish for “authenticity” seriously and acknowledges the deep, potentially existential consequences of their experiences of disruption to, or dealignment with, their professional surroundings. Our reconceptualization of authenticity in leadership may particularly resonate with leaders who do not correspond to stereotypes of how a leader looks and acts and who may therefore struggle with how to come to terms with the calls for authenticity in leadership. Thus our work also opens avenues in relation to recent discussions connecting the concern for diversity in ethics and AL (Gardiner, Reference Gardiner2017; Iszatt-White, Stead, & Elliott, Reference Iszatt-White, Stead and Elliott2021; Ladkin, Reference Ladkin2021; Ngunjiri & Hernandez, Reference Ngunjiri and Hernandez2017).

UNDERSTANDING AUTHENTICITY

To discuss authenticity in relation to leadership ethics, we first need to understand the possible meanings of authenticity and how leaders can relate to it. In both the AL literature and Heidegger’s work, we find common ground in viewing authenticity as being worthy of consideration and in the claim that we are inauthentic when we are unreflectively absorbed in the world around us, in culturally prescribed ways of being and acting. However, there are notable differences between the AL and Heideggerian perspectives on authenticity, not least regarding the possibility to “look inside” and derive leadership ethics from one’s values. To understand the possible meanings of authenticity, we examine the perspectives on authenticity that appear in popular AL books and related scholarly work before contrasting them to the Heideggerian perspective and discussing its connection to our focus on leader authenticity.

Authentic Leadership

George’s best-selling business book begins with this striking statement:

Thank you Enron and Arthur Andersen. The depth of your misconduct shocked the world and awakened us to the reality that the business world was on the wrong track, worshiping wrong idols and headed for self-destruction. . . . We needed this kind of shock therapy to realize that something is sorely missing in many of our corporations. What’s missing? In a word, leadership. Authentic leadership (George, Reference George2003: 1).

George and Clayton (Reference George and Clayton2022) subsequently add systemic shocks, such as the financial crisis of 2008, the COVID-19 pandemic, George Floyd’s murder, the war in Ukraine, and climate change, to the shocks in the business world. Overall, in popular AL books, authenticity is interpreted as a necessary “moral turn” for leadership to address the moral breakdown that supposedly threatens the liberal, capitalist model of (Western) society. This echoes broader business ethics discussions that argue that without any concern for ethics in leadership, “even the most meticulously prepared ethics statements are destined to founder, as evidenced at Enron and elsewhere” (Flynn & Werhane, Reference Flynn, Werhane and Flynn2022: 1).

This view of authenticity is also echoed in executive education programs:

Companies need to be developing leaders who exhibit high standards of integrity, take responsibility for their actions, and make decisions based on enduring principles rather than short-term expedience. The best leaders are authentic leaders—people whose inner compass guides their daily actions and enables them to earn the trust of subordinates, peers, and shareholders.Footnote 1

We see here that, beyond responding to large-scale crises, AL is seen as a positive approach to leadership that can help leaders address and possibly avoid day-to-day crises. This is important not only for the organization and its members but also for the leaders themselves. Once leaders have realized that they need somehow to respond to the crises—small and large—that may occur around them, but may find it difficult to decide how, they can find themselves in a personal and professional crisis. Confronted by possible shortcomings in how they view themselves and their failure to meet expectations others have set for them, leaders need to find a way “to be” and to act in accordance with expectations once again.

Indeed, not acting, or being immobilized by crises, may be interpreted as a breach of authenticity (Iszatt-White, Stead et al., Reference Iszatt-White, Stead and Elliott2021). Doing nothing or simply expressing and experiencing confusion signifies deficiencies in organizational responsibility and confidence, and “executives who cope with the conflicts of responsibility with anxiety are likely not to exhibit authenticity in their behaviour” (Novicevic, Harvey, Buckley, & Brown, Reference Novicevic, Harvey, Buckley and Brown2006: 70). The aim for proponents of AL is thus to propose a way for leaders to escape anxiety or any other affective state that clouds their judgment, prevents authenticity, or stops them from meeting the expectations and needs of others. Thus deploying AL arguably provides leaders with a way out of crises.

From the AL perspective, becoming an authentic leader means identifying our core values. These values cannot be learned from a book but are the result of life’s experiences and challenges:

Many people do not know who they are. They are so focused on trying to impress others that they let the world shape them rather than shaping themselves into the kind of leaders they want to be. . . . Your True North is the moral compass that guides your actions, derived from your most deeply held beliefs, your values, and the principles you lead by. It is your internal compass, unique to you, that represents who you are at your deepest level (George & Clayton, Reference George and Clayton2022: 2).

If leaders are serious about change, they need to commit to identifying these building blocks of authenticity and developing their own moral compass; it is thus not about simply following steps in a superficial, run-of-the-mill way (George, Reference George2003). Nevertheless, some general guidance may be found in the related executive education course at Harvard University: “Develop greater confidence in your own capabilities; Recognize and address your blind spots as a leader; Learn from feedback and the challenges you encounter daily; Lead an integrated life that enables you to balance work, home, and other pursuits.”Footnote 2 Aligned with this perspective, scholarly work on AL posits that authenticity can be viewed as a range of mental and behavioral processes through which one can discover and maintain the core self (Kernis & Goldman, Reference Kernis, Goldman and Zanna2006).

In summary, the AL perspective advises that, rather than remaining focused on the desire to fulfill shareholder and stakeholder expectations (which may be immoral or harmful to the business and society), individuals must actively look inward to find a path to authenticity and become ethical and effective leaders.

Heidegger on Authenticity

By way of contrast, we now turn to the Heideggerian perspective on the meaning of authenticity. Gardner, Cogliser, Davis, and Dickens (Reference Gardner, Cogliser, Davis and Dickens2011) relate the modern concern for authenticity in leadership to its philosophical roots in the Greek aphorism “know thyself,” in Socrates’s call to not live an unexamined life, and in Aristotle’s virtue ethics. They argue, however, that AL research has been more strongly influenced by social psychology, yet they acknowledge that current work on authenticity also “owes a great deal” to that of more contemporary philosophers, such as Heidegger and Sartre (Gardner et al., Reference Gardner, Cogliser, Davis and Dickens2011: 1121).

Although AL-related work and leadership ethics more broadly do not feature detailed discussions of Heidegger’s work (Ciulla, Reference Ciulla2020), the German philosopher is indeed one of the key thinkers on what it is “to be” and on the meaning of authenticity. For Heidegger, each of us is (a) “being there” (Dasein), thrown into the world and, as such, already intimately related to other people (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger and Stambaugh2010: 116). However, “initially, and for the most part, the self is lost in the They [das Man]. It understands itself in terms of the possibilities of existence that ‘circulate’ in the present day ‘average’ public interpretations of Dasein” (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger and Stambaugh2010: 365). This means that we are absorbed in the world around us (the They) in an unreflectedFootnote 3 and unquestioned manner, whereby “one simply does what one does.” This unquestioned absorption in the surrounding sociality gives us a sense of “being at home” in the world, a sense we strive to maintain and do not question.

However, for Heidegger, this apparent sense of being at home and the continual drive toward a familiar, comforting experience of the world constitute “a flight of Dasein from itself as an authentic potentiality for being itself” (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger and Stambaugh2010: 178). In other words, Heidegger emphasizes that when we feel most at home, we may be the furthest from engaging with our own existence. We are constantly drawn toward acting uncritically according to the They and thus to repeatedly “choose inauthenticity” (Dreyfus, Reference Dreyfus1991: 315). For Heidegger, the concern here is not to discuss authenticity as a willful reaction (e.g., to shocks and crises as presented in the AL literature) but to make the more general point that we live mostly inauthentic lives in the comfort of sharing a homely feeling with those around us.

Importantly, inauthenticity is not judged as morally bad or wrong; it is merely the customary way of living in the world—a way that may, however, obscure other ways and possibilities for living our lives. Authentic being, or its potentiality, can be glimpsed only when we are somehow interrupted, distanced, or alienated from this customary being at home in the world, when there is discord, dissonance, or disruption in the previously unquestioned norms of the social They. For Heidegger, in such moments of disruption, we may face a sense of “unhomeliness” (Unheimlichkeit), unfamiliarity, or uncanniness and no longer feel at home in our common world (Heidegger Reference Heidegger and Stambaugh2010, 182–83). In his view, this sense of not being at home constitutes an experience of our authentic existence—of our being thrown into the world without absolute bearings, solid foundations, or universal meaning.

Furthermore, Heidegger argues that anxiety is a prominent “mood” or “attunement” through which this “uncanny” condition of our existence may be disclosed to us (Withy, Reference Withy2015). With the notion of mood or attunement, Heidegger means that we never experience the world in a way that is neutral or objective but always in a way that is affective, entangled, and situated.Footnote 4 More specifically, anxiety is a “fundamental attunement” (Grundbefindlichkeit) (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger and Stambaugh2010: 178) of our “being-in-the-world.” Fundamental attunements are ways in which we experience the world that provide us with an “opening” to (re)think some of the most prevalent issues of our existence: “being,” time, and finitude (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger, McNeill and Walker1995). Fundamental attunements shake our foundations and displace our presupposed understandings of ourselves. Through fundamental attunements like anxiety, in which “everyday familiarity collapses” (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger and Stambaugh2010: 182), we can be brought face-to-face with our potential for authentic being (in the original German text, eigentlich, meaning “proper” or “actual” being).

Going beyond the AL approach to anxiety as an individual psychological state, Segal (Reference Segal2010: 386), for example, invokes Heidegger’s work to argue that anxiety in a leadership context arises when a leader finds their “identity as a leader–person to be at stake.” Segal argues that the CEO experiences anxiety when the company’s future, and thus the leader’s standing in the company, is at stake. Experiencing anxiety at such times means that leaders can no longer live undisturbed in their practice and surroundings (Chia & Holt, Reference Chia and Holt2006). At stake here is seeing oneself and being seen as a worthy person and leader, as someone who not only executes (as managers do) but also acts on a vision to make a positive difference in the world (Spoelstra, Reference Spoelstra2018).

For Heidegger, such a confrontation with our (potential for) authentic being is thus not the consequence of an act of will or a rational decision. Furthermore, the consequence of this confrontation is not an opening toward one’s core values, firm beliefs, or other supposedly stable elements of being. Rather, “in the clear night of the nothing of anxiety, the original openness of beings as such arises” (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger and Mcneill1998: 90). Anxiety is thus an attunement through which we can be exposed to unhomeliness as the ontological condition of Dasein, to the lack of stable and solid ground, to the unfounded openness of being. Hence uncanniness, rather than being at home in the world, (un)grounds the meaning of “being” (Withy, Reference Withy2015).

It follows that, from a Heideggerian perspective, encouraging leaders to “resolve” anxiety, as AL suggests, is neither desirable nor possible. Neither is there an “unsullied inner self” (Lawler & Ashman, Reference Lawler and Ashman2012: 333) that leaders can use as a foundation, providing them with certain, solid ground for action. Noting such differences, however, does not immediately enable us to deduce how a Heideggerian view of authenticity might lead to a different and potentially better course of action in the conduct of business, that is, a renewed leadership ethics. We now turn to engaging in such discussions to further the argument that we may find grounds to retain authenticity as a concept relevant to leadership ethics while remaining critical of AL.

THE ETHICS OF AUTHENTICITY

In this section, we move on to discussing the ethical implications of AL versus Heideggerian views on authenticity. We first examine the ethics of authenticity prescribed by AL, arguing that such ethics cannot constitute a reasonable course of action. Then, we examine how ethics can be derived from a Heideggerian understanding of authenticity to provide a more persuasive alternative while sustaining the validity of striving for authenticity in leadership.

The Ethics of Authentic Leadership

According to popular AL books, once a leader has identified their true, authentic values, they must “dare to lead” from this place of vulnerability (Brown, Reference Brown2018). Deploying AL involves being “self-aware and acting in accord with one’s true self” and thus being ethically responsible toward others (Gardner et al., Reference Gardner, Cogliser, Davis and Dickens2011: 1121). There is also an assumption that authenticity can somehow be projected onto followers, who will then emulate this way of being (Lemoine et al., Reference Lemoine, Hartnell and Leroy2019). Practicing AL thus creates an alignment between the ethical actions of the leader, the business ethics enacted throughout the company, and even the organization’s mission (see, e.g., George & Clayton, Reference George and Clayton2022: Figure 9.2). Such harmonious outcomes of AL have been linked to the Aristotelian concept of eudaimonia (Lemoine et al., Reference Lemoine, Hartnell and Leroy2019), a form of happiness or human flourishing resulting from rational action grounded in intellectual and moral virtues and that is argued to be “the ultimate test of ethical and effective leadership” (Ciulla, Reference Ciulla1995: 238). Furthermore, Gardner et al. (Reference Gardner, Cogliser, Davis and Dickens2011) interpret eudaimonia as an alignment between who we truly are and how we act as leaders.

This view of leadership ethics suggests that leaders who are leading from their core values are inherently morally responsible; therefore accusing them of acting immorally becomes impossible (Johnsen, Reference Johnsen2018). Conversely, if leaders are found to act immorally, this must be because they were not authentic enough in the first place and need to try harder, or because a given company or organization is not the right setting in which to deploy their authentic leadership, as George (Reference George2003) concluded from his own experience. Yet, if we adopt this logic, would not a Mafia godfather also feel that his values of loyalty and strength align with those of his organization and therefore that both he and the organization he is leading are authentic and thus ethically responsible? Johnsen (Reference Johnsen2018) argues that Skilling, as CEO of Enron, was seduced by his own moral values. Leaders who believe they are being true to themselves, leading authentically for the good of others, and experiencing the promised alignment and comfort of homeliness, may thus, from a different perspective or at a later date, be judged to have been acting unethically.Footnote 5

Following AL reasoning, authentic leaders hence cannot be challenged morally, as “morality seems to be both the result of being authentic and a quality of authenticity” (Ciulla, Reference Ciulla2020: 154). The successful deployment of AL appears to be a “happy coincidence” (Spoelstra, Reference Spoelstra2018) between ontology and ethics, or between the “being” of a leader and the morality of their organization, or an instance of “moral luck” whereby business success makes leaders appear moral (Ciulla et al., Reference Ciulla, Knights, Mabey and Tomkins2018). Moreover, striving to deploy AL demands intense emotional work, especially in the case of leaders from organizational minority groups who struggle to live up to what they believe will make them good leaders (Iszatt-White, Stead et al., Reference Iszatt-White, Stead and Elliott2021). The prescribed AL approach and ethics are thus setting up many “real-life” leaders for failure in the short or longer term and suggest that only near-“saintly” leaders may succeed in practicing AL (Ford & Harding, Reference Ford and Harding2011).

In summary, deploying a leadership ethics grounded in personal values may lead to several troublesome outcomes. AL ideals can result in leaders who are seduced by their own personal belief systems and deploy a hegemonic leadership style, which is not inherently ethical. They can also make many leaders feel ongoingly inauthentic and inadequate and lead to them blaming themselves for failing their own ideals, their colleagues, and their organizations—professionally and personally. Overall, leaders have no way of establishing whether their failure to act as effective and ethical leaders (and emulating this throughout the organization) is due to their own misidentified values, others’ misperceptions that they are not authentic, or AL itself not being able to deliver on its promises.

Heidegger and Ethics

Earlier, we explained how Heidegger (Reference Heidegger and Stambaugh2010: 184) asserts the potential, via anxiety, to reveal both “authenticity and inauthenticity as possibilities of [one’s] being.” Not fleeing from anxiety may enable us to reconsider who we are and who we want to be; in other words, it can help us ethically contemplate possible relations to the openness of being. When we use ethically here, we are informed by Heidegger’s interpretation of ethics as a manner of being or existing in the world that is neither stable nor fixed (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger and Mcneill1998: 253), where ethics concerns a contemplation of the “open region in which the human being dwells” (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger and Mcneill1998: 269, 271). For Heidegger, ethics is thus an existential or ontological concern: “In its principle, the ethics that thus announces itself refers to nothing other than existence. No ‘value,’ no ‘ideal’ floating above anyone’s concrete, everyday existence provides it in advance with a norm and a signification” (Nancy, Reference Nancy, Raffoul and Pettigrew2002: 71). Anxiety thus reveals existence without a preexistent meaning or significance, which also means that “Dasein cannot have a meaningful life simply by taking over and acting on the concerns provided by society” (Dreyfus, Reference Dreyfus1991: 304). Instead, one must explore the uniqueness and specificity of a given situation and its context to perceive the openness of possible significations, responses, and actions within this context. However, for Heidegger, such possibilities are not found deep within ourselves. The proposed ethics is, instead, one grounded in ontology and understood as a “responsibility to otherness” (White, Reference White1991).

If we apply this to our interest in leadership, this means there is no transcendental position outside leadership practice from which we can derive definitive principles of action, as we are always situated in a changing world (Zundel, Reference Zundel2012). The significance and meaning of a situation and the response that it demands must be reconsidered each and every time. Thus, given that the relationship between leaders and their surroundings is such that they cannot, in practice, be separated, a space within practice needs to exist where the leader can “become philosophical in an existential sense” (Segal, Reference Segal2010: 385). A leader is just one individual among others in the world. Leaders do not have a superior, extraordinary capacity to be unaffected by their surroundings and perform their actions based on unwavering personal moral grounds. Importantly, from this perspective, there is also no guaranteed or safeguarded way in which the leader can judge if the newly chosen course of action is better than the previous one—or if it is a good one in general.

On Resoluteness

Heidegger (Reference Heidegger and Stambaugh2010: 365) suggests that to endure the vertiginous opening of existence in anxiety, we must respond with “authentic resoluteness” (eigentliche Entschlossenheit). In its general meaning, resoluteness is the “quality of being strong and determined”Footnote 6 or a “firm or unwavering adherence to one’s purpose.”Footnote 7 This meaning is also echoed in the AL literature, where we can, for example, read that companies are looking for “confident executives, [whose] secure self-esteem is the foundation of authenticity exhibited in their individual behaviour as leaders” (Novicevic et al., Reference Novicevic, Harvey, Buckley and Brown2006: 70), or who, “when their principles are tested, … refuse to compromise” (George, Reference George2003: 12).

In contrast to the steadfastness of acting from determinate principles (one’s core values) toward fixed goals, Heidegger’s conception of resoluteness—as signaled by the Ent- in Entschlossenheit—denotes a “removal of closure” (ent + schliessen). For Heidegger, resoluteness concerns an attitude of unclosing, refraining from definitive conclusions, or a dis-enclosing of closure. Resoluteness is thus the authentic responsiveness to the openness of being. We further note that this, for Heidegger, ontological meaning of Entschlossenheit resonates with the etymology of the term resoluteness, which stems from the Latin resolvere—a process of breaking up, loosening, untying, or even dissolving.

Practicing resoluteness thus means enduring and being concerned about this “openness of being” without immediately trying to close it down. Leaders who are inclined to act in a generalized or standardized manner across various situations by delving into an already developed toolbox of principles, goals, or values are closing themselves off from the openness and uniqueness of each situation and are thus acting inauthentically. Instead, Heideggerian resoluteness describes a letting go or suspension of any preconceptions of the reactions required in different situations. Thus leaders can become open to the specific demands and unique needs of each situation, which may call for very different responses and require leaders to alter their “belief systems” (Dreyfus, Reference Dreyfus1991).

This, however, does not suggest that we cannot, or should not, make any decisions at all, nor that we cannot “cut through” the open space of interminable interpretations of who we can be and how we can act. Indeed, Heidegger emphasizes an intimate connection between authentic resoluteness, as an attitude of dis-enclosure, and the necessity of decision-making: “Resolutely taking over one’s own factical ‘there’ implies at the same time resolve [Entschluss] in the situation” (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger and Stambaugh2010: 364). The difference between Heidegger’s view and the conception of resolute decision-making in the AL literature, however, is in the former’s acute awareness that our actions and decisions could always have been “otherwise” and that this “otherwise” could have been better. In other words, there is an acknowledgment of the necessity and obligation to make decisions, alongside a strong realization that we can never do this from a transcendental position of absolute certainty but always only in situ.

Heideggerian resoluteness thus acknowledges the uncertain and fragile boundedness of our decisions, no matter how informed by principles or values they may be. The unending ethical task, then, is one of “becoming homely in being unhomely” (Heimischwerden im Unheimischsein) (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger1984: 143), in other words, of becoming attuned to the primordial “not being at home” of human existence and responding to it. However, this primordial “not being at home” is not a curse that dooms us to eternal nonbelonging; rather, we belong to the dis-enclosure of being, to the fundamental openness of existence—our own and that of others—that never stops questioning us.

ACTING RESOLUTELY: TOWARD AN ETHICS-AS-PRACTICE FOR LEADERSHIP

If we can turn our gaze neither outward toward transcendental principles nor inward toward a set of core values to reveal how to be an authentic leader, what does this mean for leaders who strive for authenticity and seek to change their leadership ethics? On the basis of Heidegger’s understanding of authenticity and resoluteness, we suggest that leaders move toward a practice of being attuned to attunement and developing an awareness of one’s own and others’ attunements (that always already influence one’s being-in-the-world) and the possible differences, or dissonances, among them.

Being Attuned to Attunement

Heidegger was concerned with what it is to “be” rather than with theorizing and prescribing particular ways of being and acting. We here argue that we need to devise ways in which we can learn from his philosophy to develop leadership practices, not least ones that would not presume a prevailing or permanent attunement of anxiety. Indeed, even though “anxiety can arise in the most harmless of situations” (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger and Stambaugh2010: 183), we cannot predict, provoke, or control our experience of it nor ascertain that we are actually experiencing anxiety. We can, however, try to develop practices that can be more generally meaningful and deployable in business.

Specifically, we contend that leaders should demonstrate sensitivity toward idiomatic differences in practice so they can guide their responses toward exploring how the uniqueness and dissimilarities of each situation inform the various calls for action that resist generalization. This entails, instead of holding an uncompromising attitude toward their own values, that leaders practice preparedness to continually reconsider their decisions should the situation so demand, whatever their reasons for the original decision at the time. Thus leaders would demonstrate responsiveness to the openness of situations, an openness to otherness, and enact a responsibility for their decisions before, during, and after they are made. This would demand that leaders try to distance themselves from an unquestioned “being at home” or from “thinking as a reflex” (Alvesson, Blom, & Sveningsson, Reference Alvesson, Blom and Sveningsson2017: 14).

We propose this to be a practice of being “attuned to attunement,” in other words, a practice of awareness—cognitive, perceptual, emotional, and physical—of attunements and the possible dissonances among them. As discussed earlier, attunements cannot be chosen or controlled, and the world is experienced through them. Yet, leaders can practice becoming attuned to these attunements—both their own and those of others. This is not a purely speculative, intellectual exercise nor a way of trying to detach from the world; rather, it is a way of actually staying close to what is “going on.” Notably, though leaders, like everyone else, are always traversed by attunement, by mood, they could practice noticing when they or others around them are “not in the mood” (Ahmed, Reference Ahmed2014) as a basis for reopening their way of acting as leaders. Attunements are thus affective states for practice while simultaneously providing a backdrop for actions directed at phenomena (Elpidorou & Freeman, Reference Elpidorou and Freeman2015: 668). We therefore argue that being attuned to attunement—being attentive to and reflexive about the attunements that one and others experience—can be a practical, ethical direction for leaders. In such a practice, the leader can become “attuned to the wonder of the usual” (Zundel, Reference Zundel2012: 121), which here includes the ordinariness of difference.

An Existentially Informed Ethics-as-Practice

Practicing being attuned to attunement resonates not only with Heidegger’s notion of ethics but also with an ethics-as-practice perspective. In ethics-as-practice, “ethical choices can be understood as defying predetermination by ethical models, rules, or norms; ethics are both unpredictable and future oriented, situated, and contextual” (Clegg et al., Reference Clegg, Kornberger and Rhodes2007: 108–9), and thus ethical decisions can be made only with regard to a particular situation. Moreover, the ethics-as-practice perspective does not make personal values irrelevant to decision-making but rather implies that predefined moral frameworks cannot simply be applied to address the messiness of the real world and of day-to-day business (Painter-Morland, Reference Painter-Morland2008). Furthermore, ethics-as-practice does not mean that “anything goes” or that we should be “crudely pragmatic, but instead is one that emphasizes the context and interpretation of ethics” (Clegg et al., Reference Clegg, Kornberger and Rhodes2007: 117). In a similar vein, Painter-Morland (Reference Painter-Morland2008) argues that, even if we adopt an ethics-as-practice approach, we should not abandon other forms of ethical training, as this training provides an opportunity for repetition, discussion, and an extension of the repertoire of ways to be and to act ethically in organizations. In turn, this idea of training and repetition harks back to the meaning of the Greek term ethos. Footnote 8

As we are thrown into and immersed in the social world, becoming attuned to attunement and eventually changing leadership practices is no small feat, and there is no guarantee that doing so will lead to better leadership. However, we contend that taking an existentially informed ethics-as-practice perspective can put leaders on a different path—one that offers the potential for them to see and sense their own leadership (in) practice and how it affects the relationships in that practice. Thus leaders can reflexively distance themselves not only from single acts or tools of leadership but also from the way in which they understand their ethics of leadership while being immersed in practice (Chia & Holt, Reference Chia and Holt2006). This also aligns with Cunliffe and Hibbert’s (Reference Cunliffe, Hibbert and Raelin2016: 55) view that leadership learning in practice “requires reflexive attunement within an unfolding world [and] may only occur with disruption to unnoticed practices.”

Finally, although anxiety is a central notion in this article, notably echoing its discussion in Heidegger’s work, it is important to underline again that the practice we propose is not tied to experiences of anxiety or to particular types of events or shocks. We wish to emphasize, however, that taking our condition of uncanniness, of unhomeliness, seriously in fine means that striving for authenticity is less about trying to feel good and comfortable and more about the Heideggerian notions of attunement and resoluteness as constitutive, existential elements of our being-in-the-world. This being-in-the-world is abyssal in that it can never be grounded, and this abyssal nonfundamentality is at the same time the (un)ground that commits us to doing something in the world. As previously offered, resoluteness is an opening of closure, a dis-enclosure (Nancy, Reference Nancy2008), and a way of enduring this opening rather than trying to reenclose it by retreating or fleeing to familiar ways of being—and leading. The Heideggerian approach thus also contrasts with approaches in which leaders resort to moral disengagement to avoid discomfort (Bonner, Greenbaum, & Mayer, Reference Bonner, Greenbaum and Mayer2016).

CONTRIBUTIONS, LIMITATIONS, AND RESEARCH AVENUES

In this article, we have engaged with the AL literature and Heidegger’s work to understand what it might mean to pursue authenticity in leadership and how these different conceptualizations lead to distinct paths in terms of ethics. We contribute to leadership ethics by building on previous work that considers the link between Continental philosophy and business ethics (Agarwal & Cruise Malloy, Reference Agarwal and Cruise Malloy2000; Ashman & Winstanley, Reference Ashman and Winstanley2006) and answering the call for a more rigorous philosophical discussion, in business ethics, of leadership ethics and leadership styles centering on the moral dimension (Ciulla, Reference Ciulla1995; Ciulla et al., Reference Ciulla, Knights, Mabey and Tomkins2018). We argue how, for Heidegger, there is neither a transcendental or general principle nor an inner core of authenticity to be revealed by turning inward that would guarantee an ethical foundation for leaders’ actions and decisions. Instead, striving for authenticity in leadership demands that the leader acknowledge the unfounded openness of being and resolutely take this into account when acting and making decisions. In other words, the leader must take responsibility for others by making decisions that acknowledge the entanglement with the surrounding world and the specificity of each situation that may arise. This also involves a continued preparedness to reverse or alter decisions should the situation require it. The focus is thus more on the situation, event, or “other” that calls for a response and a decision to be made than on the leader who makes the decisions.

Moreover, we contribute to existing discussions of leadership, authenticity, and ethics by proposing a practical suggestion for deploying leadership ethics that builds on a Heideggerian perspective on authenticity. Given the socially embedded ontology inherent in a Heideggerian approach to leadership (Cunliffe & Hibbert, Reference Cunliffe, Hibbert and Raelin2016), our proposed practice of being attuned to attunement must therefore be approached as a relational practice that requires purposeful engagement with those around us. However, we acknowledge that adopting such an existential-ontological approach may not be self-evident to practitioners and may require some more bridging work. Also, we need to study and develop organizational cultures with space for leaders to both retain their authority claims and relationally redefine their day-to-day leadership practices to be ethical and effective leaders (Bolle, Reference Bolle2006).

To deal with each situation in a way that may need to differ from the expectations and norms prescribed by the They, Heidegger suggests that we look to practices from the past—those that were once constitutive of the They and have been marginalized or even forgotten (Dreyfus, Reference Dreyfus1991). For Heidegger, history is about forgetting particular understandings of being and the practices linked to such understandings (Hopkins, Reference Hopkins2011). Yet, practices are handed down through culture and can thus be recalled, enabling the contemporary “us” to view the situation at hand differently (Dreyfus, Reference Dreyfus1991). Whereas Heidegger was concerned with marginalized practices in a particular (Western) culture, that is, he adopted a rather cultural-conservative standpoint, we suggest that contemporary leaders be open to new practices that somehow break with normative, scripted behavior beyond their own cultural heritages and comfort zones. Some of these variations may be forgotten—we cannot recall them—or not yet known to us, but all are part of the shared world we inhabit (see, e.g., an inspirational example about Māori leadership by Spiller, Maunganui Wolfgramm, Henry, and Pouwhare [Reference Spiller, Maunganui Wolfgramm, Henry and Pouwhare2019] or Warner and Grint’s [Reference Warner and Grint2006] discussion of “American Indian ways of leading”). As Ciulla (Reference Ciulla2020: 157) suggested, “since Heidegger believes life projects are done in history they are also done as part of various groups … hence the primary question in the context of history is not about ‘Who shall I become?’ but ‘Who shall we become’?” Still, we should not romanticize particular “alternative” leadership approaches, as there may be a trap in searching for a morally and socially superior way of leading, as well as issues of cultural appropriation.

Thus what is needed here is a combination of contextual sensitivity to difference with a readiness to explore the social-relational consequences of leadership action. In this way, the opening toward otherness can reveal other possibilities of being that are closed to us when we are absorbed in the They. Striving for authenticity in leadership thus becomes a quest that is inherently relational, contextual, and potentially available to all leaders. As remarked earlier, AL studies point to the difficulties encountered by members of minority groups in organizations to come across or see themselves as authentic leaders (Iszatt-White, Stead et al., Reference Iszatt-White, Stead and Elliott2021). It would thus be relevant to explore whether minoritized leaders who are more likely to be “not in the mood” and feel estranged from their surroundings (Ahmed, Reference Ahmed2014), or leaders who have worked in a varied range of settings in their careers and who may be more habituated to reframing their actions accordingly, have already devised ways of practicing being attuned to attunement. Moreover, in this article, we are concerned mainly with people in a formal leadership role, who are the main focus of AL and large parts of leadership ethics discussions. Future work should expand on this viewpoint and consider how the practice we propose is relevant to a broader range of leaders, including those in nonformalized leadership positions.

Also, besides anxiety, researchers may wish to consider how other fundamental attunements of our being-in-the-world that Heidegger discusses in his oeuvre, such as astounded wondering, profound boredom, and love (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger, Rojcewicz and Schuwer1994: 133ff.; 1995: 160ff.; 1998: 87), might fuel discussions of leadership ethics. For example, Carroll, Parker, and Inkson (Reference Carroll, Parker and Inkson2010: 1046) find that leaders are “too ready to dismiss boredom as an enemy, and too uninterested in facing up to boredom, tolerating it, and using it reflectively as a tool of diagnosis for both their own and their organizations’ states.” In addition, the practice of being attuned to attunement that we are proposing here would cohere with a more detailed discussion of the Heideggerian notion of care (Sorge), which is understood as primordial caregiving and concern for “being,” including our own being, other beings around us, and the world. We are not talking here about an altruistic morality, but instead, we follow Nancy (Reference Nancy, Raffoul and Pettigrew2002: 72): “what is established is rather that, whatever the moral choice, the other is essential to opening.” This unlocks many avenues for future research, as Heidegger’s notion of care has only rarely been considered from angles relevant to business ethics, whether in relation to caring leadership (Ciulla, Reference Ciulla2009; Tomkins & Simpson, Reference Tomkins and Simpson2015) or to caring organizations more broadly (Elley-Brown & Pringle, Reference Elley-Brown and Pringle2021).

Finally, to build on our Heideggerian perspective on authenticity, more work is needed to delineate concrete practices besides the one of being attuned to attunement that we propose. Although Agarwal and Cruise Malloy (Reference Agarwal and Cruise Malloy2000) attempt to build a decision-making model for business ethics related to authenticity, Ashman and Winstanley (Reference Ashman and Winstanley2006) point to issues in their definition of authenticity and to broader criticisms of the possibility of developing ethics from existentialism. We suggest that future research considers philosophers who have engaged with Heidegger’s ideas on authenticity in relation to ethics with a stronger focus on action. These include De Beauvoir’s (1947/Reference De Beauvoir2013) discussion of the ethics of ambiguity, connecting the existentialist concern for authenticity to ambiguity and freedom; Taylor’s (Reference Taylor1991) work on the ethics of authenticity beyond the risk of self-centered relativism; and Fanon’s (1952/Reference Fanon2015) discussion of identity, authenticity, and the experience of otherness. Other philosophers’ work in this wake, emphasizing the relational dimensions in ethics, includes Arendt’s (1958/Reference Arendt2013) view on the moral obligation to act for the world (see also, in this journal, Gardiner, Reference Gardiner2018) and Levinas’s (1961/Reference Levinas1979) view of ethics as preontological and relational. Here we return to Ashman and Winstanley’s (Reference Ashman and Winstanley2006) prompt that both theoretical and empirical work developing existentialist (or existentialist-inspired) perspectives is warranted and would contribute greatly to business ethics.

CONCLUSION

In this article, we have proposed a Heideggerian pathway to thinking about authenticity in leadership and its ethical implications, as an alternative to the AL perspective. The AL literature suggests that, when faced with shocks and crises putting their leadership at stake, leaders should connect to and leverage their “true selves” as a steady foundation for leadership ethics. Instead, following Heidegger, striving for authenticity means not to flee from the attunement of anxiety that opens us up to our uncanny condition of existence. Faced with this lack of firm ground, we need to act resolutely and repeatedly be open to deciding on alternative (and, it is hoped, better) courses of action, instead of falling back on the familiar. Connecting these Heideggerian insights to leadership ethics, we have argued that this demands an ethics-as-practice stance—a situated, reflexive, and relational view of who to be, how to act, and how to lead in the particular situation at hand. On this basis, we propose that leaders can cultivate being “attuned to attunement,” that is, being reflexive about how they and others are experiencing the world around them. Leaders can thus practice being open to difference and to other ways of dwelling in the world of business and beyond.

This constant reopening and contemplation does not, however, make ethical questions and decisions “simply relative” in the pejorative sense; it makes them matters of interminable negotiation without determinable conclusions, whereby leaders may need to reopen each decision on how to act while maintaining their responsibility to otherness. The challenge therefore becomes how to develop additional, practical ways for leaders to navigate business ethically without transcendental, fixed points of orientation. In Nietzsche’s (Reference Nietzsche2001: 119) words, this leaves us with the horizon of the infinite: “we have forsaken the land and gone to sea!”

Acknowledgments

We thank Frank den Hond and the three reviewers for their careful engagement with our work. We hope to continue the discussion with them in other forums. We also extend our appreciation to Sverre Spoelstra and the members of the CBS Leadership Centre for their feedback on various versions of this article.

Florence Villesèche is associate professor at Copenhagen Business School. Her current research interests include diversity, identity, feminism, leadership, and business ethics and morality in markets. Her published works include books and book chapters, such as the recently published Routledge companion to organizational diversity research methods, and contributions to recognized outlets like Human Relations and Work, Employment, and Society.

Anders Klitmøller (, corresponding author) is associate professor at the Royal Danish Defence College. He has published book chapters and made contributions to international peer-reviewed journals, including Organization Studies. His current research interests include command, complexity thinking, and different aspects of leadership, including popular forms of leadership, leadership ethics, and leadership politics.

Cathrine Bjørnholt Michaelsen is assistant professor at Copenhagen Business School. Her published works include the monograph Remains of a self: Solitude in the aftermath of psychoanalysis and deconstruction and contributions to journals like the Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, Comparative and Continental Philosophy, and the International Journal for Philosophical Studies. Her main interests are philosophical and business ethics, deconstruction, psychoanalysis, phenomenology, and theories of subjectivity and selfhood.

Footnotes

3 An issue in Heidegger’s work is the distinction between reflection and reflexivity. We note that he does not use the German for either concept but instead uses the term Verstehen (understanding), a discussion of which is beyond the scope of this article. However, in line with definitions and usage in academic literature, we consider that reflection and reflexivity may be distinguished as follows: “Reflection involves reliving and rerendering: who said and did what, how, when, where, and why. Reflection might lead to insight about something not noticed in time, pinpointing perhaps when the detail was missed.” Contrastingly, “to be reflexive involves thinking from within experiences, or as the Oxford English Dictionary puts it ‘turned or reflected back upon the mind itself’” (Bolton, Reference Bolton2010: 13–14). Depending on the meaning intended, we thus use reflected/reflection or reflexive/reflexivity.

4 Heidegger (Reference Heidegger and Stambaugh2010: 133) writes, “Mood assails. It comes neither from ‘without’ nor from ‘within,’ but rises from being-in-the-world itself as a mode of that being.” A mood is thus not a psychological “inner condition” (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger and Stambaugh2010: 133) that would concern only a single individual; rather, attunements are always somehow reflections or resonances of a collective and historical situatedness. As such, Heidegger argues that one of the fundamental attunements of ancient Greece was astounded wonder (thaumazein), whereas two of the most prominent attunements of modernity are profound boredom and anxiety, which are also the attunements most elaborated on in Heidegger’s work—even if love also gets a brief mention (Heidegger, Reference Heidegger, Rojcewicz and Schuwer1994: 133ff.; 1995: 160ff.; 1998: 87). Finally, we note that Heidegger is not consistent in distinguishing between the terms mood (Stimmung) and attunement (Befindlichkeit), and neither are the various English translations of his work. In the remainder of the article, we mainly use the term attunement, even though we are aware of its possible distinction.

5 Best-selling AL books present many examples of successful businesspeople who are also authentic leaders, and the authors are themselves successful and wealthy business leaders. However, as Spoelstra (Reference Spoelstra2018) notes, the earlier books by George include examples of now-discredited authentic leaders like Lance Armstrong (former professional road-racing champion and team leader whose titles were stripped for doping) and Mike Baker (former CEO of the US-based ArthroCare Corporation who was sentenced to 240 months in prison for fraud), which defeats the proof-by-example logic.

6 Oxford Advanced Learner’s Dictionary, s.v. “resoluteness.”

7 Merriam-Webster, s.v. “resoluteness.”

8 In the second book of the Eudemian Ethics, Aristotle explains that the term ἦθος (ethos) has a close relationship to the term ἔθους, meaning “habit” or “custom,” and that ethos therefore denotes the “moral character” or “disposition” that a person, virtuous or not, acquired by way of “repetition” and “habituation” (Aristotle, Reference Aristotle2014: 2.1220a–b [50]). On the notion of ethos in Aristotle and Heidegger, see also Bjørnholt Michaelsen (Reference Bjørnholt Michaelsen2021).

References

REFERENCES

Agarwal, J., & Cruise Malloy, D. 2000. The role of existentialism in ethical business decision‐making. Business Ethics: A European Review, 9(3): 143–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ahmed, S. 2014. Not in the mood. New Formations: A Journal of Culture/Theory/Politics, 82: 1328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alvesson, M., Blom, M., & Sveningsson, S. 2017. Reflexive leadership: Organizing in an imperfect world. London: Sage.Google Scholar
Alvesson, M., & Einola, K. 2019. Warning for excessive positivity: Authentic leadership and other traps in leadership studies. Leadership Quarterly, 30(4): 383–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arendt, H. 1958/2013. The human condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 2014. Aristotle’s ethics: Writings from the complete works. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ashman, I., & Winstanley, D. 2006. The ethics of organizational commitment. Business Ethics: A European Review, 15(2): 142–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bjørnholt Michaelsen, C. 2021. The ethos of poetry: Listening to poetic and schizophrenic expressions of alienation and otherness. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 52(4): 334–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolle, E. 2006. Existential management. Critical Perspectives on International Business, 2(3): 259–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolton, G. E. J. 2010. Reflective practice: Writing and professional development (3rd ed.). London: Sage.Google Scholar
Bonner, J. M., Greenbaum, R. L., & Mayer, D. M. 2016. My boss is morally disengaged: The role of ethical leadership in explaining the interactive effect of supervisor and employee moral disengagement on employee behaviors. Journal of Business Ethics, 137: 731–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, B. 2012. The power of vulnerability: Teachings on authenticity, connection and courage. Louiseville, CO: Sounds True.Google Scholar
Brown, B. 2018. Dare to lead: Brave work. Tough conversations. Whole hearts. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Carroll, B. J., Parker, P., & Inkson, K. 2010. Evasion of boredom: An unexpected spur to leadership? Human Relations, 63(7): 1031–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cashman, K. 2017. Leadership from the inside out: Becoming a leader for life (3rd ed.). Oakland, CA: Berrett-Koehler.Google Scholar
Chia, R., & Holt, R. 2006. Strategy as practical coping: A Heideggerian perspective. Organization Studies, 27(5): 635–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ciulla, J. B. 1995. Leadership ethics: Mapping the territory. Business Ethics Quarterly, 5(1): 528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ciulla, J. B. 2009. Leadership and the ethics of care. Journal of Business Ethics, 88(1): 34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ciulla, J. B. 2020. The search for ethics in leadership, business, and beyond, vol. 50. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ciulla, J. B., & Forsyth, D. R. 2011. Leadership ethics. In Bryman, A., Collinson, D., Grint, K., Jackson, B., & Uhl-Bien, M. (Eds.), The SAGE handbook of leadership: 229–41. London: SAGE.Google Scholar
Ciulla, J. B., Knights, D., Mabey, C., & Tomkins, L. 2018. Guest editors’ introduction: Philosophical contributions to leadership ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly, 28(1): 114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clegg, S., Kornberger, M., & Rhodes, C. 2007. Business ethics as practice. British Journal of Management, 18(2): 107–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cunliffe, A. L., & Hibbert, P. 2016. The philosophical basis of leadership-as-practice from a hermeneutical perspective. In Raelin, J. A. (Ed.), Leadership-as-practice: Theory and application: 5069. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Beauvoir, S. 1947/2013. Pour une morale de l’ambiguïté. Paris: Gallimard.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. 1991. Being-in-the world: A commentary on Heidegger’s Being and time, division I. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Elley-Brown, M. J., & Pringle, J. K. 2021. Sorge, Heideggerian ethic of care: Creating more caring organizations. Journal of Business Ethics, 168: 2325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elpidorou, A., & Freeman, L. 2015. Affectivity in Heidegger I: Moods and emotions in being and time. Philosophy Compass, 10(10): 661–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fanon, F. 1952/2015. Peau noire, masques blancs. Paris: Editions du Seuil.Google Scholar
Fischer, T., & Sitkin, S. B. 2023. Leadership styles: A comprehensive assessment and way forward. Academy of Management Annals, 17(1): 331–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flynn, G., & Werhane, P. H. 2022. A framework for leadership and ethics in business and society. In Flynn, G. (Ed.), Leadership and business ethics, vol. 60: 118. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ford, J., & Harding, N. 2011. The impossibility of the “true self” in authentic leadership. Leadership, 7(4): 463–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardiner, R. A. 2017. Authentic leadership through an ethical prism. Advances in Developing Human Resources, 19(4): 467–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardiner, R. A. 2018. Ethical responsibility—an Arendtian turn. Business Ethics Quarterly, 28(1): 3150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardner, W. L., Cogliser, C. C., Davis, K. M., & Dickens, M. P. 2011. Authentic leadership: A review of the literature and research agenda. Leadership Quarterly, 22(6): 1120–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
George, B. 2003. Authentic leadership: Rediscovering the secrets to creating lasting value. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley.Google Scholar
George, B., & Clayton, Z. 2022. True north, emerging leader edition: Leading authentically in today’s workplace. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley.Google Scholar
George, B., & Sims, P. 2007. True north: Discover your authentic leadership. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1984. Hölderlins Hymne “der Ister .” Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1994. Basic questions of philosophy: Selected “problems” of “logic” (Rojcewicz, R. & Schuwer, A., Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1995. Fundamental concepts of metaphysics (McNeill, W. & Walker, N., Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1998. Pathmarks (Mcneill, W., Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heidegger, M. 2010. Being and time (Stambaugh, J., Trans.). Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Hopkins, J. 2011. Education as authentic dialogue or resolute attunement. Journal of Russian and East European Psychology, 49(2): 5055.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iszatt-White, M., Carroll, B., Gardiner, R. A., & Kempster, S. 2021. Leadership special issue: Do we need authentic leadership? Interrogating authenticity in a new world order. Leadership, 17(4): 389–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iszatt-White, M., & Kempster, S. 2019. Authentic leadership: Getting back to the roots of the “root construct”? International Journal of Management Reviews, 21: 356–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iszatt-White, M., Stead, V., & Elliott, C. 2021. Impossible or just irrelevant? Unravelling the “authentic leadership” paradox through the lens of emotional labour. Leadership, 17(4): 464–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnsen, C. G. 2018. Authenticating the leader: Why Bill George believes that a moral compass would have kept Jeffrey Skilling out of jail. Journal of Business Ethics, 147: 5363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, C. E. 2019. Normative leadership theories, meeting the ethical challenges of leadership: Casting light or shadow (7th ed.). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.Google Scholar
Kempster, S., Iszatt-White, M., & Brown, M. 2019. Authenticity in leadership: Reframing relational transparency through the lens of emotional labour. Leadership, 15(3): 319–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kernis, M. H., & Goldman, B. M. 2006. A multicomponent conceptualization of authenticity: Theory and research. In Zanna, M. P. (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology, vol. 38: 283–57. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Ladkin, D. 2021. Problematizing authentic leadership: How the experience of minoritized people highlights the impossibility of leading from one’s “true self.” Leadership, 17(4): 395400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ladkin, D., & Taylor, S. S. 2010. Enacting the “true self”: Towards a theory of embodied authentic leadership. Leadership Quarterly, 21(1): 6474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lawler, J., & Ashman, I. 2012. Theorizing leadership authenticity: A Sartrean perspective. Leadership, 8(4): 327–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, C. 2020. How does openness about sexual and gender identities influence self-perceptions of teacher leader authenticity? Educational Management Administration and Leadership, 50(1): 140–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lemoine, G. J., Hartnell, C. A., & Leroy, H. 2019. Taking stock of moral approaches to leadership: An integrative review of ethical, authentic, and servant leadership. Academy of Management Annals, 13(1): 148–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinas, E. 1961/1979. Totality and infinity. An essay on exteriority. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Monzani, L., Hernandez Bark, A. S., Van Dick, R., & Peiró, J. M. 2015. The synergistic effect of prototypicality and authenticity in the relation between leaders’ biological gender and their organizational identification. Journal of Business Ethics, 132: 737–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nancy, J. L. 2002. Heidegger’s “originary ethics.” In Raffoul, F. & Pettigrew, D. (Eds.), Heidegger and practical philosophy: 6586. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Nancy, J. L. 2008. Dis-enclosure: The deconstruction of Christianity. New York: Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Ngunjiri, F. W., & Hernandez, K.-A. C. 2017. Problematizing authentic leadership: A collaborative autoethnography of immigrant women of color leaders in higher education. Advances in Developing Human Resources, 19(4): 393406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nietzsche, F. 2001. The gay science: With a prelude in German rhymes and an appendix of songs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Novicevic, M. M., Harvey, M. G., Buckley, M. R., & Brown, J. A. 2006. Authentic leadership: A historical perspective. Journal of Leadership and Organizational Studies, 13(1): 6476.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Painter-Morland, M. 2008. Business ethics as practice: Ethics as the everyday business of business. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Painter-Morland, M. 2017. The role of Continental philosophy in business ethics research. In Werhane, P. H., Freeman, E. R., & Dmytriyev, S. (Eds.), Research approaches in business ethics: 3649. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Segal, S. 2010. A Heideggerian approach to practice-based reflexivity. Management Learning, 41(4): 339–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spiller, C., Maunganui Wolfgramm, R., Henry, E., & Pouwhare, R. 2019. Paradigm warriors: Advancing a radical ecosystems view of collective leadership from an indigenous Māori perspective. Human Relations, 73(4): 516–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spoelstra, S. 2018. Leadership and organization: A philosophical introduction. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, C. 1991. The ethics of authenticity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Tomkins, L., & Simpson, P. 2015. Caring leadership: A Heideggerian perspective. Organization Studies, 36(8): 1013–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Warner, L. S., & Grint, K. 2006. American Indian ways of leading and knowing. Leadership, 2(2): 225–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, S. K. 1991. Political theory and postmodernism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Withy, K. 2015. Heidegger on being uncanny. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zundel, M. 2012. Walking to learn: Rethinking reflection for management learning. Management Learning, 44(2): 109–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar