Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-x4r87 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-30T01:00:13.591Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

14 - Lucretius in early modern France

from Part III: - Reception

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 May 2010

Stuart Gillespie
Affiliation:
University of Glasgow
Philip Hardie
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Get access

Summary

Thanks to a large extent to Montaigne’s interest in Lucretius as well as the strong tradition of rationalism in French philosophy which developed towards the end of the sixteenth century, the role of the author of the DRN in early modern French literature and thought has been generally recognised by scholars, though it has not been explored as fully as it deserves. Fraisse 1962 establishes the main areas of influence but is very often forced to admit that direct allusions to the Roman poet are rarer than might have been expected. Essays and articles have subsequently concentrated in particular on Lucretius’ place in Montaigne’s Essays, where he is the second most frequently cited poet after Horace. However, because of his association with the ideas of Epicurus, Lucretius was throughout the early modern period treated in France with a mixture of admiration and caution. It is no doubt a tribute to his poetic powers that he is to a large extent exempted from the more general climate of hostility towards Epicureanism.

Sixteenth-century French readers of Lucretius tended to view him in one of two ways. On the one hand he could be seen principally as a poet, whose archaising style and rugged hexameters provided a model for the increasingly popular genre of scientific poetry, or whose famous topoi might be taken out of context and used and reused by poets in a range of genres. On the other hand, he was also seen as a philosopher, a mouthpiece for a form of rationalism which would contribute to the rise of libertinism in the early seventeenth century, when Lucretius served as a literary and philosophical source for many of the theories which the libertins embraced.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×