Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-qxdb6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T13:25:33.189Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

12 - Substances and Modes, Space and Time

from II - The Science of Human Nature

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Heiner Klemme
Affiliation:
Otto-von-Güricke-Universität Magdeburg
Knud Haakonssen
Affiliation:
University of Sussex
Get access

Summary

Discussion of the nature of substances, their relationships, and their interactions is at the heart of metaphysics. There seems to be no question of metaphysics which is not more or less obviously connected with the problem of substances: knowledge of the world, soul, and God, the relationship of body and soul, the freedom of the will and moral responsibility, the immortality of the soul, and the question of a first cause of being. Eighteenth-century conceptions of substances and modes and of space and time cannot be properly understood without an appreciation of the debates of the seventeenth century, particularly as they related to Descartes’s philosophy.

Starting from an Aristotelian definition, Descartes, in the Meditationes de prima philosophia (1641), understands substance as something existing for itself which cannot be expressed as a predicate of something else. Assuming a methodically understood doubt, he finds in the cogito the epistemological basis of a res cogitans, an immaterial spiritual substance that must be distinguished from the res extensa, which is understood as extensive and movable matter (31). Since all other substances can exist only with the assistance of God, the term ‘substance’ in its strict sense applies only to God, the eternal substance. In the ‘Third Meditation’, even the certainty of the existence of the res cogitans is made to depend on the knowledge of God’s existence.

With Descartes’s new metaphysics, three basic questions are raised which came to dominate further debates concerning the nature and essence of substances. The first is how res cogitans and res extensa are interacting, the second refers to the religious and ethical consequences of the concept of substance, and the third relates to the growing success of physical theory and the experimental sciences, which seem to have no place for Descartes’s theory of innate ideas.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allison, Henry E.Kant’s Transcendental Idealism: An Interpretation and Defense.New Haven, CT, 1983.
Aristotle, . The Complete Works, ed. Barnes, J., 2 vols. Princeton, NJ, 1984.
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb, Metaphysica (Halle, 1739), in German as Metaphysik, trans. Meier, G. F. (Halle, 1766).
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. Metaphysik, trans. Meier, G. F.. Halle, 1766; 2nd edn., Halle, 1783.
Berkeley, George. A Treatise concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge [1710], in Works, vol. 2 (1949).
Berkeley, George. An Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision (1709), in Works, vol. 1 (1948).
Brands, Hartmut. ‘Cogito ergo sum’: Interpretationen von Kant bis Nietzsche.Freiburg, 1982.
Brandt, Reinhard. “Raum und Zeit in der ‘Transzendentalen Ästhetik’ der Kritik der reinen Vernunft”, in Rehabilitierung des Subjektiven: Festschrift für Hermann Schmitz, eds. Großheim, M. and Waschkies, H.–J.. Bonn, 1993.Google Scholar
Casula, Mario. “Die historische Entwicklung der Frage: Ob die Materie denken kann? Von F. Suarez bis P. J. G. Cabanis. Ein Beitrag zur Einführung in die philosophische Problematik der künstlichen Intelligenz”. Filosofia oggi 12 (1989):.Google Scholar
Condillac, Étienne Bonnot. Traité des sensations, 2 vols. London, 1754; in Oeuvres complètes, vol. 3; and in Oeuvres phil., vol., 1.
Crusius, Christian August. Entwurf der nothwendigen Vernunft-Wahrheiten, wiefern sie den zufälligen entgegen gesetzet werden.Leipzig, 1745; also in Hauptwerke, vol. 2.
Descartes, René. Meditationes de prima philosophia.Paris, 1641.
Descartes, René. Principia philosophiœ.Amsterdam, 1644.
Descartes, René. Principles of Philosophy [1644], in Phil. Writings, vol. 1; trans. Miller, V. R. and Miller, R. P., Dordrecht, 1983.
Descartes, René. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, trans. Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, R., and Murdoch, D., 3 vols. Cambridge, 1984–91.
Dessoir, Max. Geschichte der neueren deutschen Psychologie. Berlin, 1902.
Eberhard, Johann August. “Vorbericht”, in Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb, Metaphysik, trans. Meier, G. F., 2nd ed., Halle, 1783.Google Scholar
Euler, Leonhard. Briefe an eine deutsche Prinzessinn über verschiedene Gegenstände aus der Physik und Philosophie, 2 vols. Leipzig, 1769.
Euler, Leonhard. Letters … to a German Princess on Different Subjects in Physics and Philosophy, trans. Hunter, H., 2 vols. London, 1795.
Fabian, Gerd. Beitrag zur Geschichte des Leib-Seele-Problems (Lehre von der prästabilierten Harmonie und vom psychophysischen Parallelismus in der Leibniz-Wolffschen Schule). Langensalza, 1926.
Finster, Reinhardt. “Zur Kritik von Christian August Crusius an der Theorie der einfachen Substanzen bei Leibniz und Wolff”. Studia Leibnitiana 18 (1986):.Google Scholar
Gawlick, Günther, and Kreimendahl, Lothar. Hume in der deutschen Aufklärung. Umrisse einer Rezeptionsgeschichte. Stuttgart and Bad Cannstatt, 1987.
Grau, K. J.Die Entwicklung des Bewusstseins begriffes im XVII. und XVIII. Jahrhundert. Halle, 1916. Hildesheim and New York, 1981.
Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan, or The Matter, Forme and Power of a Commonwealth Ecclesiasticall and Civill [1651], in Works, vol. 3.
Hobbes, Thomas. The Collected Works, ed. Molesworth, W., 12 vols. London, 1839–45; facsim. London, 1992.
Hume, David. A Treatise of Human Nature [1739–40], eds. Norton, D. F. and Norton, M. J., in The Clarendon Edition, 2006.
Hume, David. An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding [1748], ed. Fichte, T. L., in The Clarendon Edition of the Works of David Hume (2000).
Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich. David Hume über den Glauben, oder Idealismus und Realismus.Breslau, 1787; in Werke, vol. 2.
Kant, Immanuel. Concerning the Ultimate Ground of the Differentiation of Directions in Space, in Works/Theoretical Philosophy, 1755–1770, trans. Walford, D.. and Meerbote, R. (1992).
Kant, Immanuel. Correspondence, trans. and ed. Zweig, A., in Works (1999).
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Practical Reason, trans. and ed. Gregor, M. J., in Works/Practical Philosophy (1996).
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason, trans. and eds. Guyer, P. and Wood, A. W., in Works (1998).
Kant, Immanuel. De mundi sensibilis atque intelligibilis forma et principiis (1770), in Ak (1770), vol. 2.
Kant, Immanuel. Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der bloβen Vernunft [1793], in Ak, vol. 6.
Kant, Immanuel. Kritik der praktischen Vernunft (1788), in Ak, vol. 5.
Kant, Immanuel. Kritik der reinen Vernunft (1781; 2nd edn. 1787), in Ak, vols. 3 and 4
Kant, Immanuel. Lectures on Metaphysics, trans. and eds Ameriks, K. and Naragon, S., in Works (1997).
Kant, Immanuel. On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and the Intelligible World [Inaugural Dissertation] [1770], in Works/Theoretical Philosophy 1755–1770.
Kant, Immanuel. Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik, die als Wissenschaft wird auftreten können (1783), in Ak, vol. 4.
Kant, Immanuel. Religion and Rational Theology, trans. and eds. Wood, A. W. and Giovanni, G., in Works (1996).
Kant, Immanuel. Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, trans. Giovanni, G., in Works/Religion and Rational Theology (1996).
Kant, Immanuel. Theoretical Philosophy after 1781, trans. Hatfield, G.. et al., eds. Allison, H. and Heath, P., in Works (2002).
Kant, Immanuel. Vorlesungen über Metaphysik (1770–80), in Ak, vol. 28 and.
Klemme, Heiner F.Kants Philosophie des Subjekts. Systematische und entwicklungs geschichtliche Un-tersuchungen zum Verhältnis von Selbstbewusstsein und Selbsterkenntnis. Hamburg, 1996.
Krieger, Martin. Geist, Welt und Gott bei Christian August Crusius. Erkenntnistheorisch-psychologische, kosmologische und religions philosophische Perspektiven im Kontrast zum Wolffschen System. Würzburg, 1993.
Kuehn, Manfred. Scottish Common Sense in Germany, 1768–1800: A Contribution to the History of Critical Philosophy. Kingston and Montreal, 1987.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. Essais de théodicée sur la bonté de Dieu, la liberté de l’homme et l’origine du mal [1710], in Phil. Schriften, vol. 6.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. Monadologie [1714, publ. 1840], ed. Fichte, H. Herring., 1956; ed. Boutroux, É., Paris, 1970.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. Philosophical Papers and Letters, trans. and ed. Leomker, L. E., 2 vols. Chicago, IL, 1956; 2nd edn. in 1 vol., Dordrecht, 1969.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. Theodicy: Essays on the Goodness of God, the Freedom of Man and the Origin of Evil, trans. Huggard, E. M., ed. Farrer, A.. London, 1951; La Salle, IL, 1985.
Locke, John. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Nidditch, P. H., in The Clarendon Edition (1975).
Malebranche, Nicolas. De la recherche de la vérité [1674–5]
Malebranche, Nicolas. Oeuvres complètes, ed. Robinet, A., 22 vols. Paris, 1958–84.
Malebranche, Nicolas. The Search after Truth, trans. Lennon, T. M. and Olscamp, P. J.. Columbus, OH, 1980.
Marcil-LaCoste, Louise. Claude Buffier and Thomas Reid: Two Common-Sense Philosophers. Kingston and Montreal, 1982.
Mendelssohn, Moses, Morgenstunden, in Gesammelte Schriften: Jubiläumsausgabe, eds. Bamberger, F. and Altmann, A. (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt, 1971–), vol. 3.2, ed. Strauss, L. (1974).
Mendelssohn, Moses. An die Freunde Lessings: Ein Anhang zu Herrn Jacobi, Briefwechsel über die Lehre des Spinoza [1786], in Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 3.2, ed. Strauss, L. (1974).
Mendelssohn, Moses. Morgenstunden [Berlin, 1785], ed. Strauss, L., in Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 3.2 (1974).
Mijuskovic, Ben Lazare. The Achilles of Rationalist Arguments: The Simplicity, Unity and Identity of Thought and Soul from the Cambridge Platonists to Kant. A Study in the History of an Argument. The Hague, 1974.
Norton, David Fate. David Hume: Common-Sense Moralist, Sceptical Metaphysician. Princeton, NJ, 1982.
O’Neill, Eileen. “Influxus Physicus”, in Causation in Early Modern Philosophy: Cartesianism, Occasionalism and Preestablished Harmony, ed. Nadler, S.. University Park, PA, 1993.Google Scholar
Prauss, Gerold. Kant und das Problem der Dinge an sich. Bonn, 1974.
Puster, Rolf W.Britische Gassendi-Rezeption am Beispiel John Lockes. Stuttgart and Bad Cannstatt, 1991.
Reid, Thomas. An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense [1764], ed. Brookes, D. R.. Edinburgh, 1997.
Reid, Thomas. Practical Ethics: Being Lectures and Papers on Natural Religion, Self-Government, Natural Jurisprudence, and the Law of Nations, ed. Haakonssen, K.. Princeton, NJ, 1990.
Robinson, Hoke, ed. Proceedings of the 8th International Kant Congress in Memphis. Milwaukee, WI, 1995.
Schulze, Gottlob Ernst, in his anonymously published Aenesidemus, oder Über die Fundamente der Elementarphilosophie (1792)
Spinoza, Baruch. Ethica ordine geometrico demonstrata. n.p., 1677.
Spinoza, Baruch. Ethics [1677], trans. Stirling, S.., ed. Feldman, S.. Indianapolis, IN, 1992.
Strawson, Peter F.The Bounds of Sense: An Essay on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. London, 1966.
Vaihinger, Hans. Kommentar zu Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 2nd ed., 2 vols. Stuttgart, 1922.
Wolff, Christian. Anmerckungen über die vernünfftigen Gedancken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen [1724] (facsim. repr. of 4th edn, 1740)
Wolff, Christian. Vernünfftige Gedancken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen überhaupt [1719–20] (facsim. repr. of 11th edn., 1757)
Wolff, hristian. Philosophia prima, sive Ontologia, methodo scientifica pertractata [1730] (facsim. of 2nd edn., Frankfurt, 1736)
Woolhouse, Roger S.Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz: The Concept of Substance in Seventeenth-Century Metaphysics. London, 1993.
Yolton, John W.Thinking Matter: Materialism in Eighteenth-Century Britain. Minneapolis, MN, 1983. Oxford, 1984.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×