Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0.001 Render date: 2024-05-21T04:05:32.363Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Aristotelian assumptions, 1668–69

from PART TWO - METAPHYSICS OF SUBSTANCE

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2010

Christia Mercer
Affiliation:
Columbia University, New York
Get access

Summary

In 1545, Catholic dignitaries from all over Europe convened in the imperial city of Trent to discuss the doctrinal and political problems produced by Luther and his reformation followers. It would take the Council three sessions and nearly twenty years to reach its conclusions. In the Papal bull announcing the Council, Pope Paul III asserted that two of its goals were to heal the schism perpetrated by the Protestant rebels and to reform the church. As much as its participants may have intended conciliation, their conclusions contradicted the Protestants on several crucial points and thereby guaranteed continued religious strife. Despite the failure in its task of reconciliation, however, the Council did succeed in asserting policy that would influence Christian Europe for centuries.

In 1668, Leibniz attempted to succeed where the sixteenth-century bishops and cardinals had failed. Under the encouragement of his friend and patron, Baron Johann Christian von Boineburg, Leibniz commenced work on an ambitious theological project entitled Catholic demonstrations. One of the explicit motivations behind the project was to effect a reconciliation between Roman Catholics and Lutherans. Leibniz hoped specifically to solve certain theological problems in a way that would satisfy members of both faiths and that would remain consistent with the doctrinal pronouncements of the Council of Trent. As I have argued, Leibniz intended to construct a true metaphysics that would answer the grand philosophical questions while remaining consistent with Christian doctrine.

Type
Chapter
Information
Leibniz's Metaphysics
Its Origins and Development
, pp. 63 - 98
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×