Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wg55d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-05T21:37:34.825Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - The Cogito circa a.d. 2000

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

David Woodruff Smith
Affiliation:
University of California, Irvine
Get access

Summary

Abstract. What are we to make of the cogito (cogito ergo sum) today, as the walls of Cartesian philosophy crumble around us? The enduring foundation of the cogito is consciousness. It is in virtue of a particular phenomenological structure that an experience is conscious rather than unconscious. Drawing on an analysis of that structure, the cogito is given a new explication that synthesizes phenomenological, epistemological, logical, and ontological elements. What, then, is the structure of conscious thinking on which the cogito draws? What kind of certainty does the experience of thinking give one about one's thinking and about one's existence? What form of inference is the cogito, and what is the source of its validity and soundness? Does the cogito itself lead to an ontology of mind and body like Descartes's dualism? The discussion begins with Descartes's own careful formulations of some of these issues. Then the cogito is parsed into several different principles, the phenomenological principle emerging as basic. In due course the analysis sifts through Husserl's epistemology, Hintikka's logic (or pragmatics) of the cogito, and Kaplan's logic of demonstratives, as these bear specifically on the cogito.

Segue. In “Three Facets of Consciousness” we proposed that the nature of any entity, including an act of consciousness, divides into form, appearance, and substrate. Here we explore the form of consciousness – that of self-aware intentionality – through its appearance within an act, that is, through “inner awareness.” We approach the analysis of inner awareness by a critical review of the traditional “cogito,” drawing on Descartes's analysis but from today's perspective (without dualism and without incorrigibility). […]

Type
Chapter
Information
Mind World
Essays in Phenomenology and Ontology
, pp. 42 - 75
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2004

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anscombe, G. E. M. 1975. “The First Person.” In S. Guttenplan, ed., Mind and Language, pp. 45–65. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Bencivenga, Ermanno. 1986. “Free Logics.” In D. Gabbay and F. Guenther, eds., Handbook of Philosophical Logic, 3: 373–426. Dordrecht: D. ReidelCrossRef
Burge, Tyler. 1979. “Individualism and the Mental.” In Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, and Howard Wettstein, eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy, IV: Studies in Metaphysics, pp. 73–121. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
Burge, Tyler. 1988. “Cartesian Error and the Objectivity of Knowledge.” In Robert H. Grimm and Daniel E. Merrill, eds., Contents of Thought, pp. 62–76. Tucson: University of Arizona Press
Castañeda, Hector-Neri 1966. “‘He’: A Study in the Logic of Self-Consciousness.” Ratio 8: 130–57Google Scholar
Curley, E. M. 1978. Descartes against the Skeptics. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
Descartes, René. 1984–85. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Vols. I and II. Translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Descartes, René 1988. Descartes: Selected Philosophical Writings. Translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Frege, Gottlob. 1967. “The Thought: A Logical Inquiry.” In P. F. Strawson, ed., Philosophical Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Hintikka, Jaakko. 1962a. “Cogito, Ergo Sum: Inference or Performance?” Philosophical Review 71: 3–32. Reprinted in Alexander Sesonske and Noel Fleming, eds., Meta-Meditations: Studies in Descartes, pp. 50–76. Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth, 1965
Hintikka, Jaakko. 1962b. Knowledge and Belief. Ithaca: Cornell University Press
Hintikka, Jaakko. 1975. The Intentions of Intentionality. Dordrecht: D. Reidel
Hintikka, Merrill B., and Jaakko Hintikka 1986. Investigating Wittgenstein. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Husserl, Edmund. 1960. Cartesian Meditations. Translated by Dorion Cairns. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. German original, 1931
Husserl, Edmund. 1966. The Phenomenology of Internal Time-Consciousness. Translated by James S. Churchill. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. German original, from lectures of 1905–10
Kaplan, David. 1977. Demonstratives. University of California, Los Angeles. Typescript. Revised and updated version appeared as “The Logic of Demonstratives,” in Joseph Almog, John Perry, and Howard Wettstein, eds., Themes from Kaplan. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989
Kaplan, David 1979. “On the Logic of Demonstratives.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 8: 81–98CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katz, Jerrold J. 1987. Cogitations. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Miller, Izchak. 1984. Husserl, Perception and Temporal Awareness. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press
Montague, Richard. 1972. “Pragmatics and Intensional Logic.” In Donald Davidson and Gilbert Harman, eds., Semantics of Natural Language. Dordrecht: D. Reidel
Nagel, Thomas. 1987. The View from Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Perry, John. 1979. “The Problem of the Essential Indexical.” Nous 103: 3–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert. 1965. The Concept of Mind. New York: Barnes and Noble
Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1966. Being and Nothingness. Translated by Hazel Barnes. New York: Washington Square Press
Smith, David Woodruff. 1981. “Indexical Sense and Reference.” Synthese 49: 101–27Google Scholar
Smith, David Woodruff. 1986. “The Structure of (Self-)Consciousness.” Topoi 52: 149–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, David Woodruff. 1989. The Circle of Acquaintance. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers
Smith, David Woodruff. 1990. “Thoughts.” Philosophical Papers 19(3): 163–89CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, David Woodruff, and Ronald McIntyre. 1982. Husserl and Intentionality. Dordrecht: D. Reidel
Wilson, Margaret Dauler. 1978. Descartes. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. Philosophical Investigations. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. New York: Macmillan
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1965. The Blue and Brown Books. New York: Harper Torchbooks

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×